Skip to main content

Full text of "Chance, love, and logic; philosophical essays"

See other formats


International  Library  of  Psychology 
Philosophy   and    Scientific    Method 


Chance,   Love  and   Logic 


International  Library  of  Psychology 
Philosophy  and  Scientific  Method 

GENERAL  EDITOR  :  C.  K.  OGDEN,  M.A. 

(Magdalene  College,  Cambridge) 

VOLUMES  ALREADY  PUBLISHED 

PHILOSOPHICAL  STUDIES  .  .  .  .  by  G.  E.  MOORE,  Litt.D. 
THE  MISUSE  OF  MIND by  KARIN  STEPHEN 

Prefatory  Note  by  Henri  Bergson 

CONFLICT  AND  DREAM  .  .  .  .  by  W.  H.  R.  RIVERS,  F.R.S. 
PSYCHOLOGY  AND  POLITICS  .  .  .  by  W.  H.  R.  RIVERS,  F.R.S. 
TRACTATUS  LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS  .  .  .  by  L.  WITTGENSTEIN 

Introduction  by  Bertrand  Russell 
THE  MEASUREMENT  OF   EMOTION       .         .     by  W.  WHATELY  SMITH 

Introduction  by  William  Brown 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  TYPES by  C.  G.  JUNG,  M.D.,  LL.D. 

SCIENTIFIC   METHOD by  A.  D.  RITCHIE 

SCIENTIFIC  THOUGHT by  C.  D.  BROAD,  LittD. 

THE  MEANING  OF  MEANING  .  .  by  C.  K.  OGDEN  and  I.  A.  RICHARDS 
CHARACTER  AND  THE  UNCONSCIOUS  .  by  J.  H.  VAN  DER  HOOP 
THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  REASONING  .  .  by  EUGENIC  RIGNANO 

IN   PREPARATION 

THE  ANALYSIS  OF  MATTER  .  .  by  BERTRAND  RUSSELL,  F.R.S. 
PSYCHOLOGY  AND  ETHNOLOGY  .  .  by  W.  H.  R.  RIVERS,  F.R.S. 

INDIVIDUAL  PSYCHOLOGY by  ALFRED  ADLER 

MATHEMATICS  FOR  PHILOSOPHERS  .  .  by  G.  H.  HARDY,  F.R.S. 
THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  MYTHS  .  .  by  G.  ELLIOT  SMITH,  F.R.S. 
THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  THE  UNCONSCIOUS  by  E.  VON  HARTMANN 

Introduction  by  Professor  G.  Elliot  Smith 
THE  THEORY   OF   MEDICAL   DIAGNOSIS 

by  F.  G.  CROOKSHANK,  M.D.,  F.R.C.P. 
ELEMENTS  OF  PSYCHOTHERAPY    .        by  WILLIAM  BROWN,  M.D.,  D.Sc. 

EMOTION  AND  INSANITY by  S.  THALBITZER 

Introduction  by  Professor  H.  H  off  ding 
SUPERNORMAL  PHYSICAL  PHENOMENA      .  by  E.  J.  DINGWALL 

THE  LAWS  OF  FEELING by  F.  PAULHAN 

THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  MUSIC by  EDWARD  J.  DENT 

COLOUR-HARMONY by  JAMES  WOOD 

DEVELOPMENT  OF  CHINESE  THOUGHT     .        .  by  LIANG  CHE-CHIAO 

THE   HISTORY   OF  MATERIALISM by  F.  A.  LANGE 

PSYCHE by  E.  ROHDE 

THE  PRIMITIVE  MIND by  P.  RADIN,  Ph.D. 

PSYCHOLOGY  OF  PRIMITIVE  PEOPLES  .  by  B.  MALINOWSKI,  D.Sc. 
STATISTICAL  METHOD  IN  ECONOMICS  by  P.  SARGANT  FLORENCE 
SCOPE  AND  VALUE  OF  ECONOMIC  THEORY  by  BARBARA  WOOTTON 

EDUCATIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY by  CHARLES  Fox 

THE  PRINCIPLES  OF  CRITICISM  .  .  .  .  by  I.  A.  RICHARDS 
THE  PHILOSOPHY  OF  '  AS  IF  '  .  .  .  .  by  H.  VAIHINGER 


Chance,  Love  and  Logic 

Philosophical  Essays 


By  the  late 

CHARLES    S.    PEIRCE 


Edited  with  an  Introduction  by 
MORRIS    R.   COHEN 


With  a  Supplementary  Essay  on  the 
Pragmatism  of  Peirce  by 

JOHN    DEWEY 


,    LONDON 
KEGAN  PAUL,  TRENCH,  TRUBNER  &  CO.,  LTD. 

NEW  YORK  :  HARCOURT,  BRACE  &  COMPANY,  INC. 

1923 


B 


PRINTED    IN   THE    U.S.A. 


PREFACE 

IN  the  essays  gathered  together  in  this  volume  we  have 
the  most  developed  and  coherent  available  account  of  the 
philosophy  of  Charles  S.  Peirce,  whom  James,  Royce, 
Dewey,  and  leading  thinkers  in  England,  France,  Ger 
many  and  Italy  have  placed  in  the  forefront  of  the  great 
seminal  minds  of  recent  times.  Besides  their  inherent 
value  as  the  expression  of  a  highly  original  and  fruitful 
mind,  unusually  well  trained  and  informed  in  the  exact 
sciences,  these  essays  are  also  important  as  giving  us  the 
sources  of  a  great  deal  of  contemporary  American  philoso 
phy.  Because  of  this  historical  importance  >lo  omissions 
or  changes  have  been  made  in  the  text  beyond  the  correc 
tion  of  some  obvious  slips  and  the  recasting  of  a  few  ex 
pressions  in  the  interest  of  intelligibility. 

In  a  subject  which  bristles  with  suggestions  and  diffi 
culties  the  temptation  to  add  notes  of  explanation  or  dis 
sent  is  almost  insuperable.  But  as  such  notes  might  easily 
have  doubled  the  size  of  this  volume  I  have  refrained  from 
all  comment  on  the  text  except  in  a  few  footnotes  (indi 
cated,  as  usual,  in  brackets).  The  introduction  is  intended 
(and  I  hope  it  will)  help  the  reader  to  concatenate  the 
various  lines  of  thought  contained  in  these  essays.  I  can 
not  pretend  to  have  adequately  indicated  their  significance. 
Great  minds  like  those  of  James  and  Royce  have  been 
nourished  by  these  writings  and  I  am  persuaded  that  they 


iv  PREFACE 

still  offer  mines  of  fruitful  suggestion.  Prof.  Dewey's  sup 
plementary  essay  indicates  their  value  for  the  fundamental 
question  of  metaphysics,  viz.  the  nature  of  reality. 

Grateful  acknowledgment  is  here  made  to  Mrs.  Paul 
Carus  and  to  the  Open  Court  Publishing  Co.  for  permission 
to  reprint  the  essays  of  Part  II  from  the  Monist.  The  late 
Paul  Carus  was  one  of  the  very  few  who  not  only  gave 
Peirce  an  opportunity  to  publish,  but  publicly  recognized 
the  importance  of  his  writings. 

I  must  also  acknowledge  my  obligation  to  Professor 
Dewey  for  kind  permission  to  reprint  his  essay  on  the 
Pragmatism  of  Peirce  from  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  and 
to  the  editors  of  that  Journal,  Professors  Woodbridge  and 
Bush,  for  permission  to  reprint  some  material  of  my  own. 
Part  V  of  the  Bibliography  was  compiled  by  Mr.  Irving 
Smith. 

MORRIS    R.   COHEN 

THE  COLLEGE  OF  THE  CITY  OF  NEW  YORK. 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

INTRODUCTION vii  - 

PROEM.    THE  RULES  OF  PHILOSOPHY i 

PART  I.   CHANCE  AND  LOGIC  (Illustrations  of  the  Logic 
of  Science.) 

1.  The  Taxation  of  Belief , 7 

2.  How  to  Make  Our  Ideas  Clear    Y 32^ 

3.  The  Doctrine  of  Chances 61 

4.  Th'e  Probability  of  Induction 82 

5.  The  Order  of  Nature 106 

6.  Deduction,  Induction  and  Hypothesis 131 

PART  II.    LOVE  AND  CHANCE 

<-  1.  The  Architecture  of  Theories 157 

*  2.  The  Doctrine  of  Necessity  Examined 179 

3.  The  Law  of  Mind 202 

4.  Man's  Glassy  Essence 238 

5.  Evolutionary  Love 267 

SUPPLEMENTARY     ESSAY  —  The     Pragmatism     of     Peirce, 

by  John  Dewey 301  v 


INTRODUCTION 

MANY  and  diverse  are  the  minds  that  form  the  philo 
sophic  community.  There  are,  first  and  foremost,  the  great 
masters,  the  system  builders  who  rear  their  stately  palaces  I 
towering  to  the  moon.  These  architectonic  minds  are 
served  by  a  varied  host  of  followers  and  auxiliaries.  Some 
provide  the  furnishings  to  make  these  mystic  mansions  of 
the  mind  more  commodious,  while  others  are  engaged  in 
making  their  facades  more  imposing.  Some  are  busy 
strengthening  weak  places  or  building  much-needed  addi 
tions,  while  many  more  are  engaged  in  defending  these 
structures  against  the  impetuous  army  of  critics  who  are 
ever  eager  and  ready  to  pounce  down  upon  and  destroy  all 
that  is  new  or  bears  the  mortal  mark  of  human  imperfec 
tion.  There  are  also  the  philologists,  those  who  are  in  a 
more  narrow  sense  scholars,  who  dig  not  only  for  facts  or 
roots,  but  also  for  the  stones  which  may  serve  either  for 
building  or  as  weapons  of  destruction.  Remote  from  all' 
these,  however,  are  the  intellectual  rovers  who,  in  their 
search  for  new  fields,  venture  into  the  thick  jungle  that  | 
surrounds  the  little  patch  of  cultivated  science.  They  are 
not  gregarious  creatures,  these  lonely  pioneers;  and  in  their 
wanderings  they  often  completely  lose  touch  with  those 
who  tread  the  beaten  paths.  Those  that  return  to  the  com 
munity  often  speak  strangely  of  strange  things;  and  it  is 
not  always  that  they  arouse  sufficient  faith  for  others  to 
follow  them  and  change  their  trails  into  high  roads. 

vii 


viii  INTRODUCTION 

Few  nowadays  question  the  great  value  of  these  pioneer 
minds;  and  it  is  often  claimed  that  universities  are  estab 
lished  to  facilitate  their  work,  and  to  prevent  it  from  being 
lost.  But  universities,  like  other  well-managed  institutions, 
can  find  place  only  for  those  who  work  well  in  harness. 
The  restless,  impatient  minds,  like  the  socially  or  conven 
tionally  unacceptable,  are  thus  kept  out,  no  matter  how 
fruitful  their  originality.  Charles  S.  Peirce  was  certainly 
one  of  these  restless  pioneer  souls  with  the  fatal  gift  of 
genuine  originality.  In  his  early  papers,  in  the  Journal  of 
Speculative  Philosophy,  and  later,  in  the  Monist  papers 
reprinted  as  Part  II  of  this  volume,  we  get  glimpses  of  a 
vast  philosophic  system  on  which  he  was  working  with  an 
unusual  wealth  of  material  and  apparatus.  To  a  rich 
imagination  and  extraordinary  learning  he  added  one  of  the 
most  essential  gifts  of  successful  system  builders,  the  power 
to  coin  an  apt  and  striking  terminology.  But  the  admitted 
incompleteness  of  these  preliminary  sketches  of  his  philo 
sophic  system  is  not  altogether  due  to  the  inherent  difficulty 
of  the  task  and  to  external  causes  such  as  neglect  and 
poverty.  A  certain  inner  instability  or  lack  of  self-mas 
tery  is  reflected  in  the  outer  moral  or  conventional  way 
wardness  which,  except  for  a  few  years  at  Johns  Hopkins, 
caused  him  to  be  excluded  from  a  university  career,  and 
thus  deprived  him  of  much  needed  stimulus  to  ordinary 
consistency  and  intelligibility.  As  the  years  advanced, 
bringing  little  general  interest  in,  or  recognition  of,  the  bril 
liant  logical  studies  of  his  early  years,  Peirce  became  more 
and  more  fragmentary,  cryptic,  and  involved;  so  that 
James,  the  intellectual  companion  of  his  youth,  later  found 


INTRODUCTION  ix 

his  lectures  on  pragmatism,  "  flashes  of  brilliant  light  re 
lieved  against  Cimmerian  darkness  "  —  a  statement  not  to 
be  entirely  discounted  by  the  fact  that  James  had  no  inter 
est  in  or  aptitude  for  formal  logical  or  mathematical  con 
siderations. 

Despite  these  limitations,  however,  Peirce  stands  out  as 
one  of  the  great  founders  of  modern  scientific  logic;  and  in 
the  realm  of  general  philosophy  the  development  of  some 
of  his  pregnant   ideas   has  led   to   the   pragmatism   and 
radical  empiricism  of  James,  as  well  as  to  the  mathematical 
idealism  of  Royce,  and  to  the  anti-nominalism  which  char- 1 
acterizes  the  philosophic  movement  known  as  Nee-Realism.  | 
At  any  rate,  the  work  of  James,  Royce,  and  Russell,  as" 
well  as  that  of  logicians  like  Schroeder,  brings  us  of  the 
present  generation  into  a  better  position  to  appreciate  the 
significance  of  Peirce's  work,  than  were  his  contemporaries. 


Peirce  was  by  antecedents,  training,  and  occupation  a 
scientist.  He  was  a  son  of  Benjamin  Peirce,  the  great 
Harvard  mathematician,  and  his  early  environment,  to 
gether  with  his  training  in  the  Lawrence  Scientific  School, 
justified  his  favorite  claim  that  he  was  brought  up  in  a 
laboratory.  He  made  important  contributions  not  only  in 
mathematical  logic  but  also  in  photometric  astronomy, 
geodesy,  and  psychophysics,  as  well  as  in  philology.  For 
many  years  Peirce  worked  on  the  problems  of  geodesy,  and 
his  contribution  to  the  subject,  his  researches  on  the  pendu 
lum,  was  at  once  recognized  by  European  investigators 
in  this  field.  The  International  Geodetic  Congress,  to 


x  INTRODUCTION 

which  he  was  the  first  American  representative,  gave  un 
usual  attention  to  his  paper,  and  men  like  Cellerier  and 
Plantamour  acknowledged  their  obligations  to  him.1 

This  and  other  scientific  work  involving  fine  measure 
ment,  with  the  correlative  investigations  into  the  theory 
of  probable  error,  seem  to  have  been  a  decisive  influence 
in  the  development  of  Peirce's  philosophy  of  chance. 
Philosophers  inexperienced  in  actual  scientific  measurement 
may  naively  accept  as  absolute  truth  such  statements  as 
"every  particle  of  matter  attracts  every  other  particle 
directly  as  the  product  of  their  masses  and  inversely  as  the 
square  of  the  distance,"  or  "when  hydrogen  and  oxygen 
combine  to  form  water  the  ratio  of  their  weights  is  1:8." 
But  to  those  who  are  actually  engaged  in  measuring  natural 
phenomena  with  instruments  of  precision,  nature  shows  no 
such  absolute  constancy  or  simplicity.  As  every  laboratory 
worker  knows,  no  two  observers,  and  no  one  observer  in 
successive  experiments,  get  absolutely  identical  results.  To 
the  men  of  the  heroic  period  of  science  this  was  no  difficulty. 
They  held  unquestioningly  the  Platonic  faith  that  nature 
was  created  on  simple  geometric  lines,  and  all  the  minute 
variations  were  attributable  to  the  fault  of  the  observer  or 
the  crudity  of  his  instruments.  This  heroic  faith  was, 
and  still  is,  a  most  powerful  stimulus  to  scientific  research 
and  a  protection  against  the  incursions  of  supernaturalism. 
But  few  would  defend  it  to-day  in  its  explicit  form,  and 
there  is  little  empirical  evidence  to  show  that  while  the 
observer  and  his  instruments  are  always  varying,  the  ob- 

1  See  Plantamour's  "  Recherche s  Experitnentales  sur  le  mouvement 
simultant  d'un  pendtde  et  de  ses  supports,"  Geneva,  1878,  pp.  3-4. 


INTRODUCTION  xi 

jects  which  he  measures  never  deviate  in  the  slightest  from 
the  simple  law.  Doubtless,  as  one  becomes  more  expert  in 
the  manipulation  of  physical  instruments,  there  is  a  notice 
able  diminution  of  the  range  of  the  personal  "  error,"  but 
no  amount  of  skill  and  no  refinement  of  our  instru 
ments  have  ever  succeeded  in  eliminating  irregular,  though 
small,  variations.  "  Try  to  verify  any  law  of  nature  and 
you  will  find  that  the  more  precise  your  observations,  the 
more  certain  they  will  be  to  show  irregular  departure  from 
the  law."  2  There  is  certainly  nothing  in  our  empirical  in 
formation  to  prevent  us  from  saying  that  all  the  so-called 
constants  of  nature  are  merely  instances  of  variation  be 
tween  limits  so  near  each  other  that  their  differences 
may  be  neglected  for  certain  purposes.  Moreover,  the  ap 
proach  to  constancy  is  observed  only  in  mass  phenomena, 
when  we  are  dealing  with  very  large  numbers  of  particles; 
but  social  statistics  also  approach  constant  ratios  when 
the  numbers  are  very  large.  Hence,  without  denying  dis 
crepancies  due  solely  to  errors  of  observation,  Peirce  con 
tends  that  "  we  must  suppose  far  more  minute  discrepancies 
to  exist  owing  to  the  imperfect  cogency  of  the  law  itself, 
to  a  certain  swerving  of  the  facts  from  any  definite 
formula."  3 

if  It  is  usual  to  associate  disbelief  in  absolute  laws  of  na- 
ffture  with  sentimental  claims  for  freedom  or  theological 
^miracles.    It  is,  therefore,  well  to  insist  that  Peirce's  attack 
is  entirely  in  the  interests  of  exact  logic  and  a  rational 
account  of  the  physical  universe.    As  a  rigorous  logician 
familiar  with  the  actual  procedures  by  which  our  knowledge 
2  P.  190.  3  Pp.  162-163. 


xii  INTRODUCTION 

of  the  various  laws  of  nature  is  obtained,  he  could  not 
admit  that  experience  could  prove  their  claim  to  absolute 
ness.  All  the  physical  laws  actually  known,  like  Boyle's 
law  or  the  law  of  gravitation,  involve  excessive  simplifica 
tion  of  the  phenomenal  course  of  events,  and  thus  a  large 
element  of  empirical  inaccuracy.  But  a  more  positive 
objection  against  the  traditional  assumption  of  absolute  or 
invariable  laws  of  nature,  is  the  fact  that  such  assumption 
makes  the  regularities  of  the  universe  ultimate,  and  thus 
cuts  us  off  from  the  possibility  of  ever  explaining  them  or 
how  there  comes  to  be  as  much  regularity  in  the  universe 
as  there  is.  But  in  ordinary  affairs,  the  occurrence  of  any 
regularity  is  the  very  thing  to  be  explained.  Moreover, 
modern  statistical  mechanics  and  thermodynamics  (theory 
of  gases,  entropy,  etc.)  suggest  that  the  regularity  in  the 
universe  is  a  matter  of  gradual  growth;  that  the  whole  of\ 
physical  nature  is  a  growth  from  a  chaos  of  diversity  to  a 
maximum  of  uniformity  or  entropy.  A  leading  physicist  of 
the  igth  Century,  Boltzmann,  has  suggested  that  the 
process  of  the  whole  physical  universe  is  like  that  of  a 
continuous  shaking  up  of  a  hap-hazard  or  chance  mixture 
of  things,  which  thus  gradually  results  in  a  progressively 
more  uniform  distribution.  Since  Duns  Scotus,  students 
of  logic  have  known  that  every  real  entity  has  its  individual 
character  (its  haecceitas  or  thisness)  which  cannot  be  ex 
plained  or  deduced  from  that  which  is  uniform.  Every 
explanation,  for  example,  of  the  moon's  path  must  take 
particular  existences  for  granted.  Such  original  or  unde- 
rived  individuality  and  diversity  is  precisely  what  Peirce 
means  by  chance;  and  from  this  point  of  view  chance  is 
prior  to  law. 


INTRODUCTION  xiii 

All  that  is  necessary  to  visualize  this  is  to  suppose  that 
there  is  an  infinitesimal  tendency  in  things  to  acquire 
habits,  a  tendency  which  is  itself  an  accidental  variation 
grown  habitual.  We  shall  then  be  on  the  road  to  explain 
the  evolution  and  existence  of  the  limited  uniformities 
actually  prevailing  in  the  physical  world. 

A  good  deal  of  the  foregoing  may  sound  somewhat 
mythologic.  But  even  if  it  were  so  it  would  have  the  merit 
of  offering  a  rational  alternative  to  the  mechanical  mythol 
ogy  according  to  which  all  the  atoms  in  the  universe  are 
to-day  precisely  in  the  same  condition  in  which  they  were 
on  the  day  of  creation,  a  mythology  which  is  forced  to 
regard  all  the  empirical  facts  of  spontaneity  and  novelty 
as  illusory,  or  devoid  of  substantial  truth. 

The  doctrine  of  the  primacy  of  chance  naturally  suggests 
the  primacy  of  mind.  Just  as  law  is  a  chance  habit  so  is 
matter  inert  mind.  The  principal  law  of  mind  is  that  ideas 
literally  spread  themselves  continuously  and  become  more 
and  more  general  or  inclusive,  so  that  people  who  form 
communities  of  any  sort  develop  general  ideas  in  common. 
When  this  continuous  reaching-out  of  feeling  becomes  nur 
turing  love,  such,  e.g.,  which  parents  have  for  their  off 
spring  or  thinkers  for  their  ideas,  we  have  creative 
evolution. 

James  and  Royce  have  called  attention  to  the  similarity 
between  Peirce's  doctrine  of  tychistic-agapism  (chance  and  N 
love)  and  the  creative  evolution  of  Bergson.  But  while 
both  philosophies  aim  to  restore  life  and  growth  in  their 
account  of  the  nature  of  things,  Peirce's  approach  seems  to 
me  to  have  marked  advantages,  owing  to  its  being  in  closer 


xiv  INTRODUCTION 

touch  with  modern  physics.  Bergson's  procedure  is  largely  ^ 
based  on  the  contention  that  mechanics  cannot  explain 
certain  empirical  facts,  such  as  the  supposed  identity  of 
the  vertebrate  eye  and  the  eye  of  the  scallop.  But  the  fact 
here  is  merely  one  of  a  certain  resemblance  of  pattern,  which 
may  well  be  explained  by  the  mechanical  principles  of  con 
vergent  evolution.  Peirce's  account  involves  no  rejection 
of  the  possibility  of  mechanical  explanations.  Indeed,  by 
carrying  chance  into  the  laws  of  mechanics  he  is  enabled  to 
elaborate  a  positive  and  highly  suggestive  theory  of  proto 
plasm  to  explain  the  facts  of  plasticity  and  habit.*  Instead 
of  postulating  with  Spencer  and  Bergson  a  continuous 
growth  of  diversity,  Peirce  allows  for  growth  of  habits  both 
in  diversity  and  in  uniformity.  The  Spencerian  mechanical 
philosophy  reduces  all  diversity  to  mere  spatial  differences. 
There  can  be  no  substantial  novelty;  only  new  forms  or 
combinations  can  arise  in  time.  The  creative  evolution  of 
Bergson  though  intended  to  support  the  claims  of  spon 
taneity  is  still  like  the  Spencerian  in  assuming  all  evolution 
as  proceeding  from  the  simple  to  the  complex.  Peirce 
allows  for  diversity  and  specificity  as  part  of  the  original 
character  or  endowment  of  things,  which  in  the  course  of 
time  may  increase  in  some  respects  and  diminish  in  others. 
Mind  acquires  the  habit  both  of  taking  on,  and  also  of  lay 
ing  aside,  habits.  Evolution  may  thus  lead  to  homogeneity 
or  uniformity  as  well  as  to  greater  heterogeneity. 

Not  only  has  Peirce  a  greater  regard  than  even  Bergson 
for  the  actual  diversity  and  spontaneity  of  things,  but  he 
is  in  a  much  better  position  than  any  other  modern  phi- 

*  Pp.  249  ft. 


INTRODUCTION  xv 

losopher  to  explain  the  order  and  coherence  of  the  world. 
This  he  effects  by  uniting  the  medieval  regard  for  the 
reality  of  universals  with  the  modern  scientific  use  of  the 
concept  of  continuity.  The  unfortunate  war  between  the 
pioneers  of  modern  science  and  the  adherents  of  the  scho 
lastic  doctrine  of  substantial  forms,  has  been  one  of  the 
great  misfortunes  of  human  thought,  in  that  it  made  abso 
lute  atomism  and  nominalism  the  professed  creed  of  physi-  \ 
cal  science.  Now,  extreme  nominalism,  the  insistence  on 
the  reality  of  the  particular7  leaves  no  room  for  the  genuine 
reality  of  law.  It  leaves,  as  Hume  had  the  courage  to 
admit,  nothing  whereby  the  present  can  determine  thej 
future;  so  that  anything  is  as  likely  to  happen  as  not. 
From  such  a  chaotic  world,  the  procedure  of  modern  natural 
and  mathematical  science  has  saved  us  by  the  persistent 
use  of  the  principle  of  continuity;  and  no  one  has  indicated 
this  more  clearly  than  Peirce  who  was  uniquely  qualified 
to  do  so  by  being  a  close  student  both  of  Duns  Scotus  and 
of  modern  scientific  methods. 

It  is  instructive  in  this  respect  to  contrast  the  views  of 
Peirce  and  James.  James,  who  so  generously  indicated  his 
indebtedness  to  Peirce  for  his  pragmatism,  was  also  largely 
indebted  to  Peirce  for  his  doctrine  of  radical  empiricism.5 
The  latter  doctrine  seeks  to  rescue  the  continuity  and 
fluidity  of  experience  from  the  traditional  British  empiri 
cism  or  nominalism,  which  had  resolved  everything  into  a 
number  of  mutually  exclusive  mental  states.  It  is  curious, 
however,  that  while  in  his  psychology  James  made  extensive 
use  of  the  principle  of  continuity,  he  could  not  free  himself 

0  James,  Pluralistic  Universe,  pp.  398-400. 


xvi  INTRODUCTION 

from  British  nominalism  in  his  philosophy — witness  the 
extreme  individualism  of  his  social  philosophy  or  the  equally 
extreme  anthropomorphism  of  his  religion.  Certain  of 
Peirce's  suggestions  as  to  the  use  of  continuity  in  social 
philosophy  have  been  developed  by  Royce  in  his  theory  of 
social  consciousness  and  the  nature  of  the  community;6 
but  much  remains  to  be  worked  out  and  we  can  but  repeat 
Peirce's  own  hope:  "  May  some  future  student  go  over 
this  ground  again  and  have  the  leisure  to  give  his  results 
to  the  world." 

It  is  well  to  note,  however,  that  after  writing  the  papers 
included  in  this  volume  Peirce  continued  to  be  occupied 
with  the  issues  here  raised.  This  he  most  significantly 
indicated  in  the  articles  on  logical  topics  contributed  to 
Baldwin's  Dictionary  of  Philosophy.7 

In  these  articles  it  is  naturally  the  logical  bearing  of  the 
principles  of  tychism  (chance),  synechism  (continuity),  and 
agapism  (love)  that  is  stressed.  To  use  the  Kantian  ter 
minology,  almost  native  to  Peirce,  the  regulative  rather 
than  the  constitutive  aspect  of  these  principles  is  empha 
sized.  Thus  the  doctrine  of  chance  is  not  only  what  it  was 
for  James'  radical  empiricism,  a  release  from  the  blind 
necessity  of  a  "  block  universe,"  but  also  a  method  of  keep- 

fi  Royce,  Studies  in  Good  and  Evil,  and  The  Problem  oj  Christianity, 
esp.  Vol.  2.  Baldwin  (Mental  Development)  is  heavily  indebted  to  Royce 
in  this  respect. 

7  These  articles  are  by-products  or  fragments  of  a  comprehensive  work 
on  Logic  on  which  Peirce  was  engaged  for  many  years.  For  the  writing 
of  this  book,  Royce  declared,  no  greater  mind  or  greater  erudition  has 
appeared  in  America.  Only  several  chapters  seem  to  have  been  finished, 
and  will  doubtless  be  included  with  other  hitherto  unpublished  manu 
scripts  in  the  complete  edition  of  Peirce's  writings  that  is  now  being 
prepared  by  Harvard  University. 


INTRODUCTION  xvii 

ing  open  a  possible  explanation  of  the  genesis  of  the  laws 
of  nature  and  an  interpretation  of  them  in  accordance  with 
the  theorems  of  probability,  so  fruitful  in  physical  science 
as  well  as  in  practical  life.  So  the  doctrine  of  love  is  not 
only  a  cosmologic  one,  showing  how  chance  feeling  generates 
order  or  rational  diversity  through  the  habit  of  generality 
or  continuity,  but  it  also  gives  us  the  meaning  of  truth  in 
social  terms,  in  showing  that  the  test  as  to  whether  any 
proposition  is  true  postulates  an  indefinite  number  of  co 
operating  investigators.  On  its  logical  side  the  doctrine  of 
love  (agapism)  also  recognized  the  important  fact  that 
general  ideas  have  a  certain  attraction  which  makes  us  divine 
their  nature  even  though  we  cannot  clearly  determine  their 
precise  meaning  before  developing  their  possible  conse 
quences. 

Of  the  doctrine  of  continuity  we  are  told  expressly 8  that 
"synechism  is  not  an  ultimate  absolute  metaphysical 
doctrine.  It  is  a  regulative  principle  of  logic,"  seeking  the 
thre^d_of  identity  in  diverse  .cases  and  avoiding  hypotheses 
that  this  or  that  is  ultimate  and,  therefore,  inexplicable. 
(Examples  of  such  hypotheses  are:  the  existence  of  abso 
lutely  accurate  or  uniform  laws  of  nature,  the  eternity  and 
absolute  likeness  of  all  atoms,  etc.)  To  be  sure,  the 
synechist  cannot  deny  that  there  is  an  element  of  the  in 
explicable  or  ultimate,  since  it  is  directly  forced  upon  him. 
But  he  cannot  regard  it  as  a  source  of  explanation.  The 
assumption  of  an  inexplicability  is  a  barrier  on  the  road  to 
science.  "The  form  under  which  alone  anything  can  be 
understood  is  the  form  of  generality  which  is  the  same  thing 

8  Baldwin's  Dictionary,  article  Synechism. 


xviii  INTRODUCTION 

as  continuity."9  This  insistence  on  the  generality  of 
intelligible  form  is  perfectly  consistent  with  due  emphases 
on  the  reality  of  the  individual,  which  to  a  Scotist  realist 
connotes  an  element  of  will  or  will-resistence,  but  in  logical 
procedure  means  that  the  test  of  the  truth  or  falsity  of  any 
proposition  refers  us  to  particular  perceptions.10  But 
as  no  multitude  of  individuals  can  exhaust  the  meaning  of 
a  continuum,  which  includes  also  organizing  relations  of 
,  order,  the  full  meaning  of  a  concept  cannot  be  in  any 
individual  reaction,  but  is  rather  to  be  sought  in  the  manner 
in  which  all  such  reactions  contribute  to  the  development  of 
the  concrete  reasonableness  of  the  whole  evolutionary 
process.  In  scientific  procedure  this  means  that  integrity 
of  belief  in  general  is  more  important  than,  because  it  is 
the  condition  of,  particular  true  beliefs. 

II 

This  insistence  on  the  continuity  so  effectually  used  as  a 
heuristic  principle  in  natural  and  mathematical  science, 
distinguishes  the  pragmatism  of  Peirce  from  that  of  his 
follower  James.  Prof.  Dewey  has  developed  this  point 
authoritatively  in  the  supplementary  essay;  but  in  view  of 
the  general  ignorance  as  to  the  sources  of  pragmatism  which 
prevails  in  this  incurious  age,  some  remarks  on  the  actual 
historical  origin  of  pragmatism  may  be  in  order. 

There  can  be  little  doubt  that  Peirce  was  led  to  the  formu 
lation  of  the  principle  of  pragmatism  through  the  influence 


10  Baldwin's  Dictionary,  art.  Individual:      "  Everything  whose  identity 
consists  in  a  continuity  of  reactions  will  be  a  single  logical  individual." 


INTRODUCTION  xix 

of  Chauncey  Wright.11  Wright  who  had  first  hand  ac 
quaintance  with  creative  scientific  work  in  mathematics, 
)hysics,  and  botany  was  led  by  the  study  of  Mill  and  Bain 
to  reflect  on  the  characteristics  of  scientific  method.  This 
reflection  led  him  to  draw  a  distinction  between  the  use  of 
popular  scientific  material,  by  men  like  Spencer,  to  con 
struct  a  myth  or  picture  of  the  world,  and  the  scientific 
use  of  laws  by  men  like  Newton  as  means  for  extending  our 
knowledge  of  phenomena.  Gravitation  as  a  general  fact 
had  interested  metaphysicians  long  before  Newton.  What 
made  Newton's  contribution  scientific  was  the  formulation 
of  a  mathematical  law  which  has  enabled  us  to  deduce  all 
the  then  known  facts  of  the  solar  system  and  to  anticipate 
or  predict  many  more  facts  the  existence  of  which  would 
not  otherwise  be  even  suspected,  e.g.,  the  existence  of  the 
planet  Neptune.  Wright  insists,  therefore,  that  the  prin 
ciples  of  modern  mathematical  and  physical  science  are 
the  means  through  which  nature  is  discovered,  that  scientific 

11  The  personal  relations  between  Peirce  and  Wright  were  thus  de 
scribed  by  Peirce  in  a  letter  to  Mrs.  Ladd-Franklin  (Journal  of  Philosophy 
Vol.  13,  p.  719):  "It  must  have  been  about  1857  when  1  first  made 
the  acquaintance  of  Chauncey  Wright,  a  mind  about  on  the  level  of 
J.  S.  Mill.  He  was  a  thorough  mathematician.  He  had  a  most  pene 
trating  intellect.  —  He  and  I  used  to  have  long  and  very  lively  and  close 
disputations  lasting  two  or  three  hours  daily  for  many  years.  In  the 
sixties  I  started  a  little  club  called  'The  Metaphysical  Club.'  — Wright 
was  the  strongest  member  and  probably  I  was  next.  —  Then  there  were 
Frank  Abbott,  William  James  and  others."  "It  was  there  that  the  name 
and  the  doctrine  of  pragmatism  saw  the  light."  It  might  be  added  that 
Peirce's  tychism  is  indebted  to  Wright's  doctrine  of  accidents  and  "  cosmic 
weather,"  a  doctrine  which  maintained  against  LaPlace  that  a  mind  know 
ing  nature  from  moment  to  moment  is  bound  to  encounter  genuine  novelty 
in  phenomena,  which  no  amount  of  knowledge  would  enable  us  to  foresee. 
See  Wright's  Philosophical  Discussions  — 1876,  also  Cambridge  Hist,  of 
American  Literature,  Vol.  3,  p.  234. 


XX 


INTRODUCTION 


laws  are  the  finders  rather  than  merely  the  summaries  of 
factual  truths.  This  conception  of  the  experimental  scien 
tist  as  translating  general  propositions  into  prescriptions 
for  attaining  new  experimental  truths,  is  the  starting  point 
of  Peirce's  pragmatism.  The  latter  is  embodied  in  the 
principle  that  the  meaning  of  a  concept  is  to  be  found  in 
"all  the  conceivable  experimental  phenomena  which  the 
affirmation  or  denial  of  the  concept  could  imply." 12 

In  the  earlier  statement  of  the  pragmatic  maxim,13 
Peirce  emphasized  the  consequences  for  conduct  that  follow 
from  the  acceptance  or  rejection  of  an  idea;  but  the  stoical 
maxim  that  the  end  of  man  is  action  did  not  appeal  to  him 
as  much  at  sixty  as  it  did  at  thirty.1*  Naturally  also  Peirce 
could  not  follow  the  development  of  pragmatism  by  Wm. 
James  who,  like  almost  all  modern  psychologists,  was  a 
thorough  nominalist  and  always  emphasized  particular 
sensible  experience.15  It  seemed  to  Peirce  that  such  em- 


12  Monist,  Vol.  15,  p.  180. 

13  This  volume,  pp.  43-45. 

14  "To  say  that  we  live  for  the  sake  of  action  would  be  to  say  that 
there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  rational  purport."    Monist,  Vol.  XV,  p.  175. 

15  The    letter    to    Mrs.    Ladd-Franklin    quoted    before,    explains    why 
James,  though  always  loyal  to  Peirce  and  anxious  to  give  him  credit  when 
ever  possible,  could  not  understand  the  latter's  lectures  on   pragmatism. 
Peirce's  incidental  judgments  on  others  is  worth  quoting  here: 

"  Modern  psycholoigsts  are  so  soaked  with  sensationalism  that  they 
cannot  understand  anything  that  does  not  mean  that.  How  can  I,  to 
whom  nothing  seems  so  thoroughly  real  as  generals,  and  who  regards 
Truth  and  Justice  as  literally  the  most  powerful  powers  in  the  world, 
expect  to  be  understood  by  the  thoroughgoing  Wundtian?  But  the  curious 
thing  is  to  see  absolute  idealists  tainted  with  this  disease,  —  or  men  who, 
like  John  Dewey,  hover  between  Absolute  Idealism  and  Sensationalism. 
Royce's  opinions  as  developed  in  his  World  and  Individualism  are  ex 
tremely  near  to  mine.  His  insistence  on  the  elements  of  purpose  in 
intellectual  concepts  is  essentially  the  pragmatic  position." 


INTRODUCTION  xxi 

phasis  on  particular  experiences  endangered  the  principle 
of  continuity  which  in  the  hands  of  men  like  Weierstrass 
had  reformed  modern  mathematics.  For  this  reason  he 
began  to  call  his  own  doctrine  pragmaticism,  a  sufficiently 
unattractive  name,  he  thought,  to  save  it  from  kidnappers 
and  from  popularity.  He  never,  however,  abandoned  the 
principle  of  pragmatism,  that  the  meaning  of  an  idea  is 
clarified  (because  constituted)  by  its  conceivable  experi 
mental  consequences.  Indeed,  if  we  want  to  clarify  the 
meaning  of  the  idea  of  pragmatism,  let  us  apply  the  prag 
matic  test  to  it.  What  will  be  the  effect  of  accepting  it? 
Obviously  it  will  be  to  develop  certain  general  ideas  or 
habits  of  looking  at  things. 

Peirce's  pragmatism  has,  therefore,  a  decidedly  intel 
lectual  cast.  The  meaning  of  an  idea  or  proposition  is 
found  not  by  an  intuition  of  it  but  by  working  out  its  im 
plications.  It  admits  that  thought  does  not  constitute 
reality.  Categories  can  have  no  concrete  being  without 
action  or  immediate  feeling.  But  thought  is  none  the  less 
an  essential  ingredient  of  reality;  thought  is  "  the  melody 
running  through  the  succession  of  our  sensations."  Prag 
matism,  according  to  Peirce,  seeks  to  define  the  rational 
purport,  not  the  sensuous  quality.  It  is  interested  not  in 
the  effect  of  our  practical  occupations  *or  desires  on  our 
ideas,  but  in  the  function  of  ideas  as  guides  pf^  action. 
Whether  a  man  is  to  pay  damages  in  a  certain  lawsuit  may 
depend,  in  fact,  on  a  term  in  the  Aristotelian  logic  such  as 
proximate  cause. 

It  is  of  interest  to  observe  that  though  Peirce  is  an  ardent 
admirer  of  Darwin's  method,  his  scientific  caution  makes 


xxii  INTRODUCTION 

him  refuse  to  apply  the  analogy  of  biologic  natural  selec 
tion  to  the  realm  of  ideas,  in  the  wholesale  and  uncritical 
manner  that  has  lately  become  fashionable.  Natural  selec 
tion  may  well  favor  the  triumph  of  views  which  directly 
influence  biologic  survival.  But  the  pleasure  of  entertain 
ing  congenial  illusions  may  overbalance  the  inconvenience 
resulting  from  their  deceptive  character.  Thus  rhetorical 
appeals  may  long  prevail  over  scientific  evidence. 

Ill 

Peirce  preferred  to  call  himself  a  logician,  and  his  con 
tributions  to  logic  have  so  far  proved  his  most  generally 
recognized  achievement.  For  a  right  perspective  of  these 
contributions  we  may  well  begin  with  the  observation  that 
though  few  branches  of  philosophy  have  been  cultivated  as 
continuously  as  logic,  Kant  was  able  to  affirm  that  the 
science  of  logic  had  made  no  substantial  progress  since  the 
time  of  Aristotle.  The  reason  for  this  is  that  Aristotle's 
logic,  the  logic  of  classes,  was  based  on  his  own  scientific 
procedure  as  a  zoologist,  and  is  still  in  essence  a  valid 
method  so  far  as  classification  is  part  of  all  rational  pro 
cedure.  But  when  we  come  to  describe  the  mathematical 
method  of  physical  science,  we  cannot  cast  it  into  the 
Aristotelian  form  without  involving  ourselves  in  such  com 
plicated  artificialities  as  to  reduce  almost  to  nil  the  value 
of  Aristotle's  logic  as  an  organon.  Aristotle's  logic  enables 
us  to  make  a  single  inference  from  two  premises.  But  the 
vast  multitude  of  theorems  that  modern  mathematics  has 
derived  from  a  few  premises  as  to  the  nature  of.  number, 
shows  the  need  of  formulating  a  logic  or  theory  of  inference 


INTRODUCTION  xxiii 

that  shall  correspond  to  the  modern,  more  complicated,  prac 
tice  as  Aristotle's  logic  did  to  simple  classificatory  zoology. 
To  do  this  effectively  would  require  the  highest  construc 
tive  logical  genius,  together  with  an  intimate  knowledge 
of  the  methods  of  the  great  variety  of  modern  sciences. 
This  is  in  the  nature  of  the  case  a  very  rare  combination, 
since  great  investigators  are  not  as  critical  in  examining 
their  own  procedure  as  they  are  in  examining  the  subject 
matter  which  is  their  primary  scientific  interest.  Hence, 
when  great  investigators  like  Poincare  come  to  describe 
their  own  work,  they  fall  back  on  the  uncritical  assumptions 
of  the  traditional  logic  which  they  learned  in  their  school 
days.  Moreover,  "  For  the  last  three  centuries  thought 
has  been  conducted  in  laboratories,  in  the  field,  or  otherwise 
in  the  face  of  the  facts,  while  chairs  of  logic  have  been 
filled  by  men  who  breathe  the  air  of  the  seminary." 16  The 
great  Leibnitz  had  the  qualifications,  but  here,  as  else 
where,  his  worldly  occupations  left  him  no  opportunity 
except  for  very  fragmentary  contributions.  It  was  not  until 
the  middle  of  the  igth  century  that  two  mathematicians, 
Boole  and  DeMorgan,  laid  the  foundations  for  a  more  gen 
eralized  logic.  Boole  developed  a  general  logical  algorithm 
or  calculus,  while  DeMorgan  called  attention  to  non-syllogis 
tic  inference  and  especially  to  the  importance  of  the  logic  of 
relations.  Peirce's  great  achievement  is  to  have  recognized 
the  possibilities  of  both  and  to  have  generalized  and  de 
veloped  them  into  a  general  theory  of  scientific  inference. 
The  extent  and  thoroughness  of  his  achievement  has  been 
obscured  by  his  fragmentary  way  of  writing  and  by  a  rather 

16  Baldwin's  Dictionary,  art.  Method. 


xxiv  /INTRODUCTION 

unwieldy  symbolism.  Still,  modern  mathematical  logic, 
such  as  that  of  Russell's  Principles  of  Mathematics,  is  but  a 
development  of  Peirce's  logic  of  relatives. 

This  phase  of  Peirce's  work  is  highly  technical  and  an 
account  of  it  is  out  of  place  here.  Such  an  account  will 
be  found  in  Lewis'  Survey  of  Symbolic  Logic.17  I  refer  to 
it  here  only  to  remind  the  reader  that  the  Illustrations  of 
the  Logic  of  the  Sciences  (Part  I  of  this  volume)  have  a 
background  of  patient  detailed  work  which  is  still  being 
developed  to-day. 

Symbolic  logic  has  been  held  in  rather  low  esteem  by 
the  followers  of  the  old  classical  methods  in  philosophy. 
Their  stated  objection  to  it  has  been  mainly  that  it  is 
concerned  with  the  minutiae  of  an  artificial  language  and  is 
of  no  value  as  a  guide  to  the  interpretation  of  reality. 
Now  it  should  be  readily  admitted  that  preoccupation  with 
symbolic  logic  is  rather  apt  to  retard  the  irresponsible 
flight  of  philosophic  fancy.  Yet  this  is  by  no  means  always 
an  evil.  By  insisting  on  an  accuracy  that  is  painful  to  those 
impatient  to  obtain  sweeping  and  comforting,  though  hasty, 
conclusions,  symbolic  logic  is  well  calculated  to  remove  the 
great  scandal  of  traditional  philosophy  —  the  claim  of  abso 
lutely  certain  results  in  fields  where  there  is  the  greatest 
conflict  of  opinion.  This  scandalous  situation  arises  in  part 
from  the  fact  that  in  popular  exposition  we  do  not  have  to 
make  our  premises  or  assumptions  explicit;  hence  all  sorts 
of  dubious  prejudices  are  implicitly  appealed  to  as  abso- 

17  "Peirca  anticipated  the  most  important  procedures  of  his  successors 
even  when  he  did  not  work  them,  out  himself.  Again  and  again  one  finds 
the  clue  to  the  most  recent  developments  in  the  writings  of  Peirce," 
Lewis'  Survey  of  Symbolic  Logic,  p.  79. 


INTRODUCTION  xxv 

lutely  necessary  principles.  Also,  by  the  use  of  popular 
terms  which  have  a  variety  of  meanings,  one  easily  slides 
from  one  meaning  to  another,  so  that  the  most  improbable 
conclusions  are  thus  derived  from  seeming  truisms.  By 
making  assumptions  and  rules  explicit,  and  by  using  tech 
nical  terms  that  do  not  drag  wide  penumbras  of  meaning 
with  them,  the  method  of  symbolic  logic  may  cruelly  reduce 
the  sweeping  pretensions  of  philosophy.  But  there  is  no 
reason  for  supposing  that  pretentiousness  rather  than 
humility  is  the  way  to  philosophic  salvation.  Man  is  bound 
to  speculate  about  the  universe  beyond  the  range  of  his 
knowledge,  but  he  is  not  bound  to  indulge  the  vanity  of 
setting  up  such  speculations  as  absolutely  certain  dogmas. 
There  is,  however,  no  reason  for  denying  that  greater 
rigor  and  accuracy  of  exposition  can  really  help  us  to  dis 
cern  new  truth.  Modern  mathematics  since  Gauss  and 
Weierstrass  has  actually  been  led  to  greater  f ruitfulness  by 
increased  rigor  which  makes  such  procedure  as  the  old 
proofs  of  Taylor's  theorem  no  longer  possible.  The  sub 
stitution  of  rigorous  analytic  procedures  for  the  old  Eu 
clidean  proofs  based  on  intuition,  has  opened  up  vast  fields 
of  geometry.  Nor  has  this  been  without  any  effect  on 
philosophy.  Where  formerly  concepts  like  infinity  and  con 
tinuity  were  objects  of  gaping  awe  or  the  recurrent  occa 
sions  for  intellectual  violence/8  we  are  now  beginning  to 
use  them,  thanks  to  Peirce  and  Royce,  in  accurate  and 
definable  senses.  Consider,  for  instance,  the  amount  of 
a  priori  nonsense  which  Peirce  eliminates  by  pointing  out 

18  Hans  Breitmann  is  symbolic  of  those  who  "  solved  the  infinite  as  one 
eternal  sphere." 


xxvi  INTRODUCTION 

that  the  application  of  the  concept  of  continuity  to  a  span 
of  consciousness  removes  the  necessity  for  assuming  a  first 
or  last  moment;  so  likewise  the  range  of  vision  on  a  large 
unobstructed  ground  has  no  line  between  the  visible  and  the 
invisible.  These  considerations  will  be  found  utterly  de 
structive  of  the  force  of  the  old  arguments  (fundamental 
to  Kant  and  others)  as  to  the  necessary  infinity  of  time  and 
space.  Similar  enlightenment  is  soon  likely  to  result  from 
the  more  careful  use  of  terms  like  relative  and  absolute, 
which  are  bones  of  contention  in  philosophy  but  Ariadne 
threads  of  exploration  in  theoretical  physics,  because  of 
the  definite  symbolism  of  mathematics.  Other  important 
truths  made  clear  by  symbolic  logic  is  the  hypothetical 
character  of  universal  propositions  and  the  consequent  in 
sight  that  no  particulars  can  be  deduced  from  universals 
alone,  since  no  number  of  hypotheses  can  without  given  data 
establish  an  existing  fact. 

There  is,  however,  an  even  more  positive  direction  in 
which  symbolic  logic  serves  the  interest  of  philosophy,  and 
that  is  in  throwing  light  on  the  nature  of  symbols  and  on 
the  relation  of  meaning.  Philosophers  have  light-heartedly 
dismissed  questions  as  to  the  nature  of  significant  signs  as 
c  merely '  (most  fatal  word!)  a  matter  of  language.  But 
Peirce  in  the  paper  on  Man's  Glassy  [Shakespearian  for 
Mirror-Like]  Essence,  endeavors  to  exhibit  man's  whole 
nature  as  symbolic.19  This  is  closely  connected  with  his 
logical  doctrine  which  regards  signs  or  symbols  as  one  of 

19  See  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy,  Vol.  2,  pp.  i55-i57,  article  on 
A  New  List  of  Categories  in  the  Proceedings  of  the  American  Academy 
of  Arts  and  Sciences,  Vol.  7,  287-298  and  article  on  Sign,  in  Baldwin's 
Dictionary. 


INTRODUCTION  xxrii 

the  fundamental  categories  or  aspects  of  the  universe 
(Thoughts  and  things  are  the  other  two).  Independently 
of  Peirce  but  in  line  with  his  thought  another  great  and 
neglected  thinker,  Santayana,  has  shown  that  the  whole  life 
of  man  that  is  bound  up  with  the  institutions  of  civilization, 
is  concerned  with  symbols. 

It  is  not  altogether  accidental  that,  since  Boole  and 
DeMorgan,  those  who  have  occupied  themselves  with  sym 
bolic  logic  have  felt  called  upon  to  deal  with  the  problem 
of  probability.  The  reason  is  indicated  by  Peirce  when  he 
formulates  the  problem  of  probable  inference  in  such  a  way 
as  to  make  the  old  classic  logic  of  absolutely  true  or  false 
conclusions,  a  limiting  case  (i.e.,  of  values  i  and  o)  of  the 
logic  of  probable  inference  whose  values  range  all  the  way 
between  these  two  limits.  This  technical  device  is  itself 
the  result  of  applying  the  principle  of  continuity  to  throw 
two  hitherto  distinct  types  of  reasoning  into  the  same  class. 
The  result  is  philosophically  significant. 

Where  the  classical  logic  spoke  of  major  and  minor 
premises  without  establishing  any  really  important  dif 
ference  between  the  two,  Peirce  draws  a  distinction  between 
the  premises  and  the  guiding  principle  of  our  argument. 
All  reasoning  is  from  some  concrete  situation  to  another. 
The  propositions  which  represent  the  first  are  the  premises 
in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word.  But  the  feeling  that  certain 
conclusions  follow  from  these  premises  is  conditioned  by  an 
implicit  or  explicit  belief  in  some  guiding  principle  which 
connects  the  premises  and  the  conclusions.  When  such  a 
leading  principle  results  in  true  conclusions  in  all  cases  of 
true  premises,  we  have  logical  deduction  of  the  orthodox 


xxviii  INTRODUCTION 

type.  If,  however,  such  a  principle  brings  about  a  true  con 
clusion  only  in  a  certain  proportion  of  cases,  then  we  have 
probability. 

This  reduction  of  probability  to  the  relative  frequency 
of  true  propositions  in  a  class  of  propositions,  was  suggested 
to  Peirce  by  Venn's  Logic  of  Chance.  Peirce  uses  it  to 
establish  some  truths  of  greatest  importance  to  logic  and 
philosophy. 

He  eliminates  the  difficulties  of  the  old  conceptualist 
view,  which  made  probability  a  measure  of  our  ignorance 
and  yet  had  to  admit  that  almost  all  fruitfulness  of  our 
practical  and  scientific  reasoning  depended  on  the  theorems 
of  probability.  How  could  we  safely  predict  phenomena  by 
measuring  our  ignorance? 

Probability  being  reduced  to  a  matter  of  the  relative  fre 
quency  of  a  class  in  a  larger  class  or  genus,  it  becomes, 
strictly  speaking,  inapplicable  to  single  cases  by  themselves. 
A  single  penny  will  fall  head  or  it  will  fall  tail  every  time; 
to-morrow  it  will  rain,  or  it  will  not  rain  at  all.  The 
probability  of  £  or  any  other  fraction  means  nothing  in 
the  single  case.  It  is  only  because  we  feel  the  single  event 
as  representative  of  a  class,  as  something  which  repeats 
itself,  that  we  speak  elliptically  of  the  probability  of  a 
single  event.  Hence  follows  the  important  corollary  that 
reasoning  with  respect  to  the  probability  of  this  or  that  ar 
rangement  of  the  universe  would  be  valid  only  if  universes 
were  as  plentiful  as  blackberries. 

To  be  useful  at  all,  theories  must  be  simpler  than  the 
complex  facts  which  they  seek  to  explain.  Hence,  it  is 
often  convenient  to  employ  a  principle  of  certainty  where 


INTRODUCTION  xxix 

the  facts  justify  only  a  principle  of  some  degree  of  proba 
bility.  In  such  cases  we  must  be  cautious  in  accepting 
any  extreme  consequence  of  these  principles,  and  also  be 
on  guard  against  apparent  refutations  based  on  such  ex 
treme  consequences. 

Finally  I  should  like  to  emphasize  the  value  of  Peirce's 
theory  of  inference  for  a  philosophy  of  civilization.  To  the 
old  argument  that  logic  is  of  no  importance  because  people 
learn  to  reason,  as  to  walk,  by  instinct  and  habit  and  not  by 
scientific  instruction,  Peirce  admits 20  that  "  all  human 
knowledge  up  to  the  highest  flights  of  science  is  but  the 
development  of  our  inborn  animal  instincts."  But  though 
logical  rules  are  first  felt  implicitly,  bringing  them  into 
explicit  consciousness  helps  the  process  of  analysis  and 
thus  makes  possible  the  recognition  of  old  principles  in  novel 
situations.  This  increases  our  range  of  adaptability  to  such 
an  extent  as  to  justify  a  general  distinction  between  the 
slave  of  routine  or  habit  and  the  freeman  who  can  anticipate 
and  control  nature  through  knowledge  of  principles.  Peirce's 
analysis  of  the  method  of  science  as  a  method  of  attain 
ing  stability  of  beliefs  by  free  inquiry  inviting  all  possible 
doubt,  in  contrast  with  the  methods  of  iteration  ("will  to 
believe  ")  and  social  authority,  is  one  of  the  best  intro 
ductions  to  a  theory  of  liberal  or  Hellenic  civilization,  as 
opposed  to  those  of  despotic  societies.  Authority  has  its 
roots  in  the  force  of  habit,  but  it  cannot  prevent  new  and 
unorthodox  ideas  from  arising;  and  in  the  effort  to  defend 
authoritative  social  views  men  are  apt  to  be  far  more  ruth 
less  than  in  defending  their  own  personal  convictions. 

20  Studies  in  Logic,  p.  181. 


xxx  INTRODUCTION 

IV 

Not  only  the  pragmatism  and  the  radical  empiricism  of 
James,  but  the  idealism  of  Royce  and  the  more  recent 
movement  of  neo-realism  are  largely  indebted  to  Peirce. 

It  may  seem  strange  that  the  same  thinker  should  be 
claimed  as  foster-father  of  both  recent  idealism  and  realism, 
and  some  may  take  it  as  another  sign  of  his  lack  of  con 
sistency.  But  this  seeming  strangeness  is  really  due  to 
the  looseness  with  which  the  antithesis  between  realism  and 
idealism  has  generally  been  put.  If  by  idealism  we  denote 
the  nominalistic  doctrine  of  Berkeley,  then  Peirce  is  clearly 
not  an  idealist;  and  his  work  in  logic  as  a  study  of  types 
of  order  (in  which  Royce  followed  him)  is  fundamental 
for  a  logical  realism.  But  if  idealism  means  the  old 
Platonic  doctrine  that  "  ideas,"  genera,  or  forms  are  not 
merely  mental  but  the  real  conditions  of  existence,  we  need 
not  wonder  that  Peirce  was  both  idealist  and  realist. 

Royce's  indebtedness  to  Peirce  is  principally  in  the  use 
of  modern  mathematical  material,  such  as  the  recent  de 
velopment  of  the  concepts  of  infinity  and  continuity,  to 
throw  light  on  fundamental  questions  of  philosophy,  such 
as  relation  of  the  individual  to  God  or  the  Universe.  At 
the  end  of  the  nineteenth  century  mathematics  had  almost 
disappeared  from  the  repertory  of  philosophy  (cf.  Kiilpe's 
Introduction  to  Philosophy),  and  Peirce's  essay  on  the 
Law  of  Mind  opened  a  new  way  which  Royce  followed  in 
his  World  and  the  Individual,  to  the  great  surprise  of  his 
idealistic  brethren.  In  his  Problem  of  Christianity  Royce 
has  also  indicated  his  indebtedness  to  Peirce  for  his  doc- 


INTRODUCTION  xxxi 

trine  of  social  consciousness,  the  mind  of  the  community, 
and  the  process  of  interpretation.  It  may  be  that  a  great 
deal  of  the  similarity  between  the  thoughts  of  these  two 
men  is  due  to  common  sources,  such  as  the  works  of  Kant 
and  Schelling;  but  it  is  well  to  note  that  not  only  in  his 
later  writings  but  also  in  his  lectures  and  seminars  Royce 
continually  referred  to  Peirce's  views. 

The  ground  for  the  neo-realist  movement  in  American 
philosophy  was  largely  prepared  by  the  mathematical  work 
of  Russell  and  by  the  utilization  of  mathematics  to  which 
Royce  was  led  by  Peirce.  The  logic  of  Mr.  Russell  is 
based,  as  he  himself  has  pointed  out,  on  a  combination  of 
the  work  of  Peirce  and  Peano.  In  this  combination  the 
notation  of  Peano  has  proved  of  greater  technical  fluency, 
but  all  of  Peano's  results  can  also  be  obtained  by  Peirce's 
method  as  developed  by  Schroeder  and  Mrs.  Ladd-Frank- 
lin.  But  philosophically  Peirce's  influence  is  far  greater  in 
insisting  that  logic  is  not  a  branch  of  psychology,  that  it 
is  not  concerned  with  merely  mental  processes,  but  with 
objective  relations.  To  the  view  that  the  laws  of  logic 
represent  "the  necessities  of  thought,"  that  propositions 
are  true  because  "  we  can  not  help  thinking  so,"  he  answers: 
"  Exact  logic  will  say  that  C's  following  logically  from  A  is 
a  state  of  things  which  no  impotence  of  thought  alone  can 
bring  about."21  "The  question  of  validity  is  purely  one 
of  fact  and  not  of  thinking.  ...  It  is  not  in  the  least  the 
question  whether,  when  the  premises  are  accepted  by  the 
mind,  we  feel  an  impulse  to  accept  the  conclusion  also. 

21  Monist,  Vol.  7,  p.  27.  Cf.  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy, 
Vol.  2,  p.  207 ;  Popular  Science  Monthly,  Vol.  58,  pp.  305-306. 


xxxii  INTRODUCTION 

The  true  conclusion  would  remain  true  if  we  had  no  im 
pulse  to  accept  it,  and  the  false  one  would  remain  false 
though  we  could  not  resist  the  tendency  to  believe  in  it." 22 
Since  the  days  of  Locke  modern  philosophy  has  been 
almost  entirely  dominated  by  the  assumption  that  one  must 
study  the  process  of  knowing  before  one  can  find  out  the 
nature  of  things  known;  in  other  words,  that  psychology  is 
the  central  philosophic  science.  The  result  of  this  has  been 
an  almost  complete  identification  of  philosophy  with  mental 
science.  Nor  did  the  influence  of  biologic  studies  of  the 
middle  of  the  nineteenth  century  shake  the  belief  in  that 
banal  dictum  of  philosophic  mediocrity:  "  The  proper 
study  of  mankind  is  man."  The  recent  renaissance  of 
logical  studies,  and  the  remarkable  progress  of  physics  in 
our  own  day  bid  fair  to  remind  us  that  while  the  Lockian 
way  has  brought  some  gains  to  philosophy,  the  more  ancient 
way  of  philosophy  is  by  no  means  exhausted  of  promise. 
Man  cannot  lose  his  interest  in  the  great  cosmic  play. 
Those  who  have  faith  in  the  ancient  and  fruitful  approach 
to  philosophy  through  the  doors  of  mathematics  and  physics 
will  find  the  writings  of  Charles  S.  Peirce  full  of  sugges 
tions.  That  such  an  approach  can  also  throw  light  on  the 
vexed  problem  of  knowledge  needs  no  assurance  to  those 
acquainted  with  Plato  and  Aristotle.  But  I  may  conclude 
by  referring  to  Peirce's  doctrine  of  ideal  as  opposed  to 
sensible  experiment,23  and  to  his  treatment  of  the  question 

22  This  vol.,  p.  15. 

23  Suggestive  for  a  theory  of  the  metaphysics  of  fictions  is  the  sugges 
tion  (p.  46)  "  that  the  question  of  what  would  occur  under  circumstances 
whjich  do  not  actually  arise,  is  not  a  question  of  fact,  but  only  of  the 
most  perspicuous  arrangement  of  them."  This  arrangement  is,  of  course, 
not  merely  subjective. 


INTRODUCTION  xxxiii 

how  it  is  that  in  spite  of  an  infinity  of  possible  hypotheses, 
mankind  has  managed  to  make  so  many  successful  induc 
tions.2*  And  for  the  bearing  of  mathematical  studies  on  the 
wisdom  of  life,  the  following  is  certainly  worth  serious  re 
flection:  "  All  human  affairs  rest  upon  probabilities.  If 
man  were  immortal  [on  earth]  he  could  be  perfectly  sure 
of  seeing  the  day  when  everything  in  which  he  had  trusted 
should  betray  his  trust.  He  would  break  down,  at  last,  as 
every  great  fortune,  as  every  dynasty,  as  every  civilization 
does.  In  place  of  this  we  have  death."  The  recognition 
that  the  death  of  the  individual  does  not  destroy  the  logical 
meaning  of  his  utterances,  that  this  meaning  involves  the 
ideal  of  an  unlimited  community,  carries  us  into  the  heart 
of  pure  religion. 

24  Pp.  128-129,  cf.  Monist,  Vol.  7,  p.  206,  and  Logical  Studies,  pp. 
175  ff. 


CHANCE,   LOVE,   AND   LOGIC 

PROEM 

THE   RULES   OF   PHILOSOPHY1 

DESCARTES  is  the  father  of  modern  philosophy,  and  the 
spirit  of  Cartesianism  —  that  which  principally  distin 
guishes  it  from  the  scholasticism  which  it  displaced  —  may 
be  compendiously  stated  as  follows: 

1.  It  teaches  that  philosophy  must  begin  with  universal 
doubt;  whereas  scholasticism  had  never  questioned  funda 
mentals. 

2.  It  teaches  that  the  ultimate  test  of  certainty  is  to  be 
found  in  the  individual  consciousness;  whereas  scholasticism 
had  rested  on  the  testimony  of  sages  and  of  the  Catholic 
Church. 

3.  The  multiform  argumentation  of  the  middle  ages  is 
replaced  by  a  single  thread  of  inference  depending  often 
upon  inconspicuous  premises. 

4.  Scholasticism  had  its  mysteries  of  faith,  but  undertook 
to  explain  all  created  things.     But  there  are  many  facts 
which  Cartesianism  not  only  does  not  explain  but  renders 
absolutely  inexplicable,  unless  to  say  that  "  God  makes  them 
so  "  is  to  be  regarded  as  an  explanation. 

In  some,  or  all  of  these  respects,  most  modern  philoso 
phers  have  been,  in  effect,  Cartesians.   Now  without  wishing 

1  From  the  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy,  vol.  2,  p.  140. 


2  PROEM 

to  return  to  scholasticism,  it  seems  to  me  that  modern 
science  and  modern  logic  require  us  to  stand  upon  a  very 
different  platform  from  this. 

1.  We  cannot  begin  with  complete  doubt.   We  must  begin 
with  all  the  prejudices  which  we  actually  have  when  we 
enter  upon  the  study  of  philosophy.    These  prejudices  are 
not  to  be  dispelled  by  a  maxim,  for  they  are  things  which 
it  does  not  occur  to  us  can  be  questioned.    Hence  this 
initial  skepticism  will  be  a  mere  self-deception,  and  not  real 
doubt;  and  no  one  who  follows  the  Cartesian  method  will 
ever  be  satisfied  until  he  has  formally  recovered  all  those 
beliefs  which  in  form  he  has  given  up.    It  is,  therefore,  as 
useless  a  preliminary  as  going  to  the  North  Pole  would  be 
in  order  to  get  to  Constantinople  by  coming  down  regularly 
upon  a  meridian.    A  person  may,  it  is  true,  in  the  course 
of  his  studies,  find  reason  to  doubt  what  he  began  by  be 
lieving;  but  in  that  case  he  doubts  because  he  has  a  positive 
reason  for  it,  and  not  on  account  of  the  Cartesian  maxim. 
Let  us  not  pretend  to  doubt  in  philosophy  what  we  do  not 
doubt  in  our  hearts. 

2.  The  same  formalism  appears  in  the  Cartesian  criterion, 
which  amounts  to  this:   "  Whatever  I  am  clearly  convinced 
of,  is  true."   If  I  were  really  convinced,  I  should  have  done 
with  reasoning  and  should  require  no  test  of  certainty. 
But  then  to  make  single  individuals  absolute  judges  of  truth 
is  most  pernicious.    The  result  is  that  metaphysics  has 
reached  a  pitch  of  certainty  far  beyond  that  of  the  physical 
sciences;  — only  they  can  agree  upon  nothing  else.    In 
sciences  in  which  men  come  to  agreement,  when  a  theory 


PROEM  3 

has  been  broached  it  is  considered  to  be  on  probation  until 
this  agreement  is  reached.  After  it  is  reached,  the  question 
of  certainty  becomes  an  idle  one,  because  there  is  no  one 
left  who  doubts  it.  We  individually  cannot  reasonably 
hope  to  attain  the  ultimate  philosophy  which  we  pursue; 
we  can  only  seek  it,  therefore,  for  the  community  of  philoso 
phers.  Hence,  if  disciplined  and  candid  minds  carefully  | 
examine  a  theory  and  refuse  to  accept  it,  this  ought  to  create 
doubts  in  the  mind  of  the  author  of  the  theory  himself. 

3.  Philosophy  ought  to  imitate  the  successful  sciences  in 
its  methods,  so  far  as  to  proceed  only  from  tangible  prem 
ises  which  can  be  subjected  to  careful  scrutiny,  and  to  trust 
rather  to  the  multitude  and  variety  of  its  arguments  than 
to  the  conclusiveness  of  any  one.    Its  reasoning  should  not 
form  a  chain  which  is  no  stronger  than  its  weakest  link, 
but  a  cable  whose  fibers  may  be  ever  so  slender,  provided 
they  are  sufficiently  numerous  and  intimately  connected. 

4.  Every  unidealistic  philosophy  supposes  some  absolutely 
inexplicable,  unanalyzable  ultimate;    in  short,  something 
resulting  from  mediation  itself  not  susceptible  of  mediation. 
Now  that  anything  is  thus  inexplicable,  can  only  be  known 
by  reasoning  from  signs.     But  the  only  justification  of  an 
inference  from  signs  is  that  the  conclusion  explains  the  fact. 
To  suppose  the  fact  absolutely  inexplicable,  is  not  to  explain 
it,  and  hence  this  supposition  is  never  allowable. 


PART  I 

CHANCE  AND  LOGIC 
(ILLUSTRATIONS  OF  THE  LOGIC  OF  SCIENCE) 


CHANCE  AND   LOGIC 

FIRST   PAPER 
THE   FIXATION   OF    BELIEF1 


FEW  persons  care  to  study  logic,  because  everybody  con 
ceives  himself  to  be  proficient  enough  in  the  art  of  reasoning 
already.  But  I  observe  that  this  satisfaction  is  limited  to 
x'  one's  own  ratiocination,  and  does  not  extend  to  that  of 
other  men. 

We  come  to  the  full  possession  of  our  power  of  drawing 
inferences  the  last  of  all  our  faculties,  for  it  is  not  so  much 
a  natural  gift  as  a  long  and  difficult  art.  The  history  of 
its  practice  would  make  a  grand  subject  for  a  book.  The 
medieval  schoolman,  following  the  Romans,  made  logic  the 
earliest  of  a  boy's  studies  after  grammar,  as  being  very 
easy.  So  it  was  as  they  understood  it.  Its  fundamental 
principle,  according  to  them,  was,  that  all  knowledge  rests 
on  either  authority  or  reason;  but  that  whatever  is  deduced 
by  reason  depends  ultimately  on  a  premise  derived  from 
authority.  Accordingly,  as  soon  as  a  boy  was  perfect  in 
the  syllogistic  procedure,  his  intellectual  kit  of  tools  was 
held  to  be  complete. 

1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  November,  1877. 

7 


8  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

To  Roger  Bacon,  that  remarkable  mind  who  in  the  middle 
of  the  thirteenth  century  was  almost  a  scientific  man,  the 
schoolmen's  conception  of  reasoning  appeared  only  an  ob 
stacle  to  truth.  He  saw  that  experience  alone  teaches  any 
thing  —  a  proposition  which  to  us  seems  easy  to  understand, 
because  a  distinct  conception  of  experience  has  been  handed 
down  to  us  from  former  generations;  which  to  him  also 
seemed  perfectly  clear,  because  its  difficulties  had  not  yet 
unfolded  themselves.  Of  all  kinds  of  experience,  the  best, 
he  thought,  was  interior  illumination,  which  teaches  many 
things  about  Nature  which  the  external  senses  could  never 
discover,  such  as  the  transubstantiation  of  bread. 

Four  centuries  later,  the  more  celebrated  Bacon,  in  the 
first  book  of  his  "  Novum  Organum,"  gave  his  clear  account 
of  experience  as  something  which  must  be  open  to  verifica 
tion  and  reexamination.  But,  superior  as  Lord  Bacon's 
conception  is  to  earlier  notions,  a  modern  reader  who  is  not 
in  awe  of  his  grandiloquence  is  chiefly  struck  by  the  in 
adequacy  of  his  view  of  scientific  procedure.  That  we  have 
only  to  make  some  crude  experiments,  to  draw  up  briefs 
of  the  results  in  certain  blank  forms,  to  go  through  these 
by  rule,  checking  off  everything  disproved  and  setting  down 
the  alternatives,  and  that  thus  in  a  few  years  physical 
science  would  be  finished  up  —  what  an  idea!  "  He  wrote 
on  science  like  a  Lord  Chancellor," 2  indeed. 

The  early  scientists,  Copernicus,  Tycho,  Brahe,  Kepler, 
Galileo  and  Gilbert,  had  methods  more  like  those  of  their 
modern  brethren.  Kepler  undertook  to  draw  a  curve 

2  [This  is  substantially  the  dictum  of  Harvey  to  John  Aubrey.  See 
the  latter's  Brief  Lives  (Oxford  ed.  1898)  I  299]. 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  9 

through  the  places  of  Mars;3  and  his  greatest  service  to 
science  was  in  impressing  on  men's  minds  that  this  was  the 
thing  to  be  done  if  they  wished  to  improve  astronomy; 
that  they  were  not  to  content  themselves  with  inquiring 
whether  one  system  of  epicycles  was  better  than  another 
but  that  they  were  to  sit  down  by  the  figures  and  find  out 
what  the  curve,  in  truth,  was.  He  accomplished  this  by  his 
incomparable  energy  and  courage,  blundering  along  in  the 
most  inconceivable  way  (to  us),  from  one  irrational  hy 
pothesis  to  another,  until,  after  trying  twenty-two  of  these, 
he  fell,  by  the  mere  exhaustion  of  his  invention,  upon  the 
orbit  which  a  mind  well  furnished  with  the  weapons  of 
modern  logic  would  have  tried  almost  at  the  outset.4 

In  the  same  way,  every  work  of  science  great  enough  to 
be  remembered  for  a  few  generations  affords  some 
exemplification  of  the  defective  state  of  the  art  of  reasoning 
of  the  time  when  it  was  written;  and  each  chief  step  in 
science  has  been  a  lesson  in  logic.  It  was  so  when  Lavoisier 
and  his  contemporaries  took  up  the  study  of  Chemistry. 
The  old  chemist's  maxim  had  been,  "  Lege,  lege,  lege, 
labora,  ora,  et  relege."  Lavoisier's  method  was  not  to  read 
and  pray,  not  to  dream  that  some  long  and  complicated 
chemical  process  would  have  a  certain  effect,  to  put  it  into 
practice  with  dull  patience,  after  its  inevitable  failure  to 
dream  that  with  some  modification  it  would  have  another 
result,  and  to  end  by  publishing  the  last  dream  as  a  fact: 
his  way  was  to  carry  his  mind  into  his  laboratory,  and  to 
make  of  his  alembics  and  cucurbits  instruments  of  thought, 

3  Not  quite  so,  but  as  nearly  so  as  can  be  told  in  a  few  words. 

4  [This  modern  logic,  however,  is  largely  the  outcome  of  Kepler's  work.] 


io  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

giving  a  new  conception  of  reasoning  as  something  which 
was  to  be  done  with  one's  eyes  open,  by  manipulating  real 
things  instead  of  words  and  fancies. 

The  Darwinian  controversy  is,  in  large  part,  a  question 
of  logic.  Mr.  Darwin  proposed  to  apply  the  statistical 
method  to  biology.  The  same  thing  has  been  done  in  a 
widely  different  branch  of  science,  the  theory  of  gases. 
Though  unable  to  say  what  the  movement  of  any  particular 
molecule  of  gas  would  be  on  a  certain  hypothesis  regarding 
the  constitution  of  this  class  of  bodies,  Clausius  and  Max 
well  were  yet  able,  by  the  application  of  the  doctrine  of 
probabilities,  to  predict  that  in  the  long  run  such  and  such 
a  proportion  of  the  molecules  would,  under  given  circum 
stances,  acquire  such  and  such  velocities;  that  there  would 
take  place,  every  second,  such  and  such  a  number  of  colli 
sions,  etc.;  and  from  these  propositions  they  were  able  to 
deduce  certain  properties  of  gases,  especially  in  regard  to 
their  heat-relations.  In  like  manner,  Darwin,  while  unable 
to  say  what  the  operation  of  variation  and  natural  selection 
in  every  individual  case  will  be,  demonstrates  that  in  the 
long  run  they  will  adapt  animals  to  their  circumstances. 
Whether  or  not  existing  animal  forms  are  due  to  such  ac 
tion,  or  what  position  the  theory  ought  to  take,  forms  the 
subject  of  a  discussion  in  which  questions  of  fact  and 
questions  of  logic  are  curiously  interlaced. 


ii 

The  object  of  reasoning  is  to  find  out,  from  the  considera 
tion  of  what  we  already  know,  something  else  which  we  do 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  u 

not  know.  Consequently,  reasoning  is  good  if  it  be  such 
as  to  give  a  true  conclusion  from  true  premises,  and  not 
otherwise.  Thus,  the  question  of  validity  is  purely  one  of 
fact  and  not  of  thinking.  A  being  the  premises  and  B  being 
the  conclusion,  the  question  is,  whether  these  facts  ar3 
really  so  related  that  if  A  is  B  is.  If  so,  the  inference  is 
valid;  if  not,  not.  It  is  not  in  the  least  the  question 
whether,  when  the  premises  are  accepted  by  the  mind,  we 
feel  an  impulse  to  accept  the  conclusion  also.  It  is  true 
that  we  do  generally  reason  correctly  by  nature.  But  that 
Js  an  accident;  the  true  conclusion  would  remain  true  if  we 
had  no  impulse  to  accept  it;  and  the  false  one  would  remain 
false,  though  we  could  not  resist  the  tendency  to  believe 
in  it. 

We  are,  doubtless,  in  the  main  logical  animals,  but  we 
are  not  perfectly  so.  Most  of  us,  for  example,  are  natur 
ally  more  sanguine  and  hopeful  than  logic  would  justify. 
We  seem  to  be  so  constituted  that  in  the  absence  of  any 
facts  to  go  upon  we  are  happy  and  self-satisfied;  so  that  the 
effect  of  experience  is  continually  to  counteract  our  hopes 
and  aspirations.  Yet  a  lifetime  of  the  application  of  this 
corrective  does  not  usually  eradicate  our  sanguine  disposi 
tion.  Where  hope  is  unchecked  by  any  experience,  it  is 
likely  that  our  optimism  is  extravagant.  Logicality  in  re 
gard  to  practical  matters  is  the  most  useful  quality  an  ani 
mal  can  possess,  and  might,  therefore,  result  from  the 
action  of  natural  selection;  but  outside  of  these  it  is  prob 
ably  of  more  advantage  to  the  animal  to  have  his  mind 
filled  with  pleasing  and  encouraging  visions,  independently 
of  their  truth;  and  thus,  upon  unpractical  subjects,  natural 


12  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

selection  might  occasion  a  fallacious  tendency  of  thought. 

That  which  determines  us,  from  given  premises,  to  draw 
one  inference  rather  than  another,  is  some  habit  of  mind, 
whether  it  be  constitutional  or  acquired.  The  habit  is  good 
or  otherwise,  according  as  it  produces  true  conclusions  from 
true  premises  or  not;  and  an  inference  is  regarded  as  valid 
or  not,  without  reference  to  the  truth  or  falsity  of  its  con 
clusion  specially,  but  according  as  the  habit  which  deter 
mines  it  is  such  as  to  produce  true  conclusions  in  general 
or  not.  The  particular  habit  of  mind  which  governs  this 
or  that  inference  may  be  formulated  in  a  proposition  whose 
truth  depends  on  the  validity  of  the  inferences  which  the 
habit  determines;  and  such  a  formula  is  called  a  guiding 
principle  of  inference.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  we  ob 
serve  that  a  rotating  disk  of  copper  quickly  comes  to  rest 
when  placed  between  the  poles  of  a  magnet,  and  we  infer 
that  this  will  happen  with  every  disk  of  copper.  The  guid 
ing  principle  is,  that  what  is  true  of  one  piece  of  copper  is 
true  of  another.  Such  a  guiding  principle  with  regard  to 
copper  would  be  much  safer  than  with  regard  to  many  other 
substances  —  brass,  for  example. 

A  book  might  be  written  to  signalize  all  the  most  im 
portant  of  these  guiding  principles  of  reasoning.  It  would 
probably  be,  we  must  confess,  of  no  service  to  a  person 
whose  thought  is  directed  wholly  to  practical  subjects,  and 
whose  activity  moves  along  thoroughly  beaten  paths.  The 
problems  which  present  themselves  to  such  a  mind  are 
matters  of  routine  which  he  has  learned  once  for  all  to 
handle  in  learning  his  business.  But  let  a  man  venture  into 
an  unfamiliar  field,  or  where  his  results  are  not  continually 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  13 

checked  by  experience,  and  all  history  shows  that  the  most 
masculine  intellect  will  ofttimes  lose  his  orientation  and 
waste  his  efforts  in  directions  which  bring  him  no  nearer  to 
his  goal,  or  even  carry  him  entirely  astray.  He  is  like  a 
ship  on  the  open  sea,  with  no  one  on  board  who  understands 
the  rules  of  navigation.  And  in  such  a  case  some  general 
study  of  the  guiding  principles  of  reasoning  would  be  sure 
to  be  found  useful. 

The  subject  could  hardly  be  treated,  however,  without 
being  first  limited;  since  almost  any  fact  may  serve  as  a 
guiding  principle.  But  it  so  happens  that  there  exists  a 
division  among  facts,  such  that  in  one  class  are  all  those 
which  are  absolutely  essential  as  guiding  principles,  while 
in  the  other  are  all  those  which  have  any  other  interest  as 
objects  of  research.  This  division  is  between  those  which 
are  necessarily  taken  for  granted  in  asking  whether  a  cer 
tain  conclusion  follows  from  certain  premises,  and  those 
which  are  not  implied  in  that  question.  A  moment's  thought 
will  show  that  a  variety  of  facts  are  already  assumed  when 
the  logical  question  is  first  asked.  It  is  implied,  for  in 
stance,  that  there  are  such  states  of  mind  as  doubt  and 
belief  —  that  a  passage  from  one  to  the  other  is  possible, 
the  object  of  thought  remaining  the  same,  and  that  this 
transition  is  subject  to  some  rules  which  all  minds  are  alike 
bound  by.  As  these  are  facts  which  we  must  already  know 
before  we  can  have  any  clear  conception  of  reasoning  at  all, 
it  cannot  be  supposed  to  be  any  longer  of  much  interest  to 
inquire  into  their  truth  or  falsity.  On  the  other  hand,  it 
is  easy  to  believe  that  those  rules  of  reasoning  which  are 
deduced  from  the  very  idea  of  the  process  are  the  ones 


14  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

which  are  the  most  essential;  and,  indeed,  that  so  long  as  it 
conforms  to  these  it  will,  at  least,  not  lead  to  false  conclu 
sions  from  true  premises.  In  point  of  fact,  the  importance 
of  what  may  be  deduced  from  the  assumptions  involved 
in  the  logical  question  turns  out  to  be  greater  than  might 
be  supposed,  and  this  for  reasons  which  it  is  difficult  to  ex 
hibit  at  the  outset.  The  only  one  which  I  shall  here  men 
tion  is,  that  conceptions  which  are  really  products  of  logical 
reflections,  without  being  readily  seen  to  be  so,  mingle  with 
our  ordinary  thoughts,  and  are  frequently  the  causes  of 
great  confusion.  This  is  the  case,  for  example,  with  the 
conception  of  quality.  A  quality  as  such  is  never  an  object 
of  observation.  We  can  see  that  a  thing  is  blue  or  green, 
but  the  quality  of  being  blue  and  the  quality  of  being  green, 
are  not  things  which  we  see;  they  are  products  of  logical 
reflections.  The  truth  is,  that  common-sense,  or  thought 
as  it  first  emerges  above  the  level  of  the  narrowly  practical, 
is  deeply  imbued  with  that  bad  logical  quality  to  which  the, 
epithet  metaphysical  is  commonly  applied;  and  nothing  can 
clear  it  up  but  a  severe  course  of  logic. 


in 

We  generally  know  when  we  wish  to  ask  a  question  and 
when  we  wish  to  pronounce  a  judgment,  for  there  is  a  dis 
similarity  between  the  sensation  of  doubting  and  that  of 
believing. 

But  this  is  not  all  which  distinguishes  doubt  from  belief. 
There  is  a  practical  difference.  Our  beliefs  guide  our  de 
sires  and  shape  our  actions.  The  Assassins,  or  followers 


THE    FIXATION1    OF    BELIEF  15 

of  the  Old  Man  of  the  Mountain,  used  to  rush  into  death  at 
his  least  command,  because  they  believed  that  obedience 
to  him  would  insure  everlasting  felicity.  Had  they  doubted 
this,  they  would  not  have  acted  as  they  did.  So  it  is  with 
every  belief,  according  to  its  degree.  The  feeling  of  be 
lieving  is  a  more  or  less  sure  indication  of  there  being  estab 
lished  in  our  nature  some  habit  which  will  determine  our 
actions.  Doubt  never  has  such  an  effect. 

Nor  must  we  overlook  a  third  point  of  difference.  Doubt 
is  an  uneasy  and  dissatisfied  state  from  which  we  struggle 
to  free  ourselves  and  pass  into  the  state  of  belief;  while  the 
latter  is  a  calm  and  satisfactory  state  which  we  do  not  wish 
to  avoid,  or  to  change  to  a  belief  in  anything  else.5  On 
the  contrary,  we  cling  tenaciously,  not  merely  to  believing, 
but  to  believing  just  what  we  do  believe. 

Thus,  both  doubt  and  belief  have  positive  effects  upon  us, 
though  very  different  ones.  Belief  does  not  make  us  act  at 
once,  but  puts  us  into  such  a  condition  that  we  shall  behave 
in  a  certain  way,  when  the  occasion  arises.  Doubt  has  not 
the  least  effect  of  this  sort,  but  stimulates  us  to  action  until 
itjs  destroyed.  This  reminds  us  of  the  irritation  of  a  nerve 
and  the  reflex  action  produced  thereby;  while  for  the  ana 
logue  of  belief,  in  the  nervous  system,  we  must  look  to  what 
are  called  nervous  associations  —  for  example,  to  that  habit 
of  the  nerves  in  consequence  of  which  the  smell  of  a  peach 
will  make  the  mouth  water. 


5  I  am  not  speaking  of  secondary  effects  occasionally  produced  by  the 
interference  of  other  impulses. 


1 6  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

IV 

The  irritation  of  doubt  causes  a  struggle  to  attain  a  state 
of  belief.  I  shall  term  this  struggle  inquiry,  though  it  must 
be  admitted  that  this  is  sometimes  not  a  very  apt 
designation. 

The  irritation  of  doubt  is  the  only  immediate  motive  for 
the  struggle  to  attain  belief.  It  is  certainly  best  for  us 
that  our  beliefs  should  be  such  as  may  truly  guide  our 
actions  so  as  to  satisfy  our  desires;  and  this  reflection  will 
make  us  reject  any  belief  which  does  not  seem  to  have  been 
so  formed  as  to  insure  this  result.  But  it  will  only  do  so 
by  creating  a  doubt  in  the  place  of  that  belief.  With  the 
doubt,  therefore,  the  struggle  begins,  and  with  the  cessation 
of  doubt  it  ends.  Hence,  \ the  sole  object  of  inquiry  is  the 
settlement  of  opinion.  \  We  may  fancy  that  this  is  not 
enough  for  us,  and  that  we  seek  not  merely  an  opinion, 
but  a  true  opinion.  But  put  this  fancy  to  the  test,  and  it 
proves  groundless;  for  as  soon  as  a  firm  belief  is  reached 
we  are  entirely  satisfied,  whether  the  belief  be  false  or  true. 
And  it  is  clear  that  nothing  out  of  the  sphere  of  our  knowl 
edge  can  be  our  object,  for  nothing  which  does  not  affect 
the  mind  can  be  a  motive  for  a  mental  effort.  The  most 
that  can  be  maintained  is,  that  we  seek  for  a  belief  that  we 
shall  think  to  be  true.  But  we  think  each  one  of  our  be 
liefs  to  be  true,  and,  indeed,  it  is  mere  tautology  to  say  so. 

That  the  settlement  of  opinion  is  the  sole  end  of  inquiry 
is  a  very  important  proposition.  It  sweeps  away,  at  once, 
various  vague  and  erroneous  conceptions  of  proof.  A  few 
of  these  may  be  noticed  here. 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  17 

1.  Some  philosophers  have  imagined  that  to  start  an  in 
quiry  it  was  only  necessary  to  utter  o^  question  or  set  it 
down  on  paper,  and  have  even  recommended  us  to  begin 
our  studies  with  questioning  everything!     But  the  mere 
putting  of  a  proposition  into  the  interrogative  form  does 
not  stimulate  the  mind  to  any  struggle  after  belief.    There 
must  be  a  real  and  living  doubt,  and  without  all  this  dis 
cussion  is  idle.      9^ 

2.  It  is  a  very  common  idea  that  a  demonstration  must 
rest  on  some  ultimate  and  absolutely  indubitable  proposi 
tions.    These,  according  to  one  school,  are  first  principles 
of  a  general  nature;  according  to  another,  are  first  sensa 
tions.     But,  in  point  of  fact,  an  inquiry,  to  have  that  com 
pletely  satisfactory  result  called  demonstration,  has  only 
to  start  with  propositions  perfectly  free  from  all  actual 
doubt.    If  the  premises  are  not  in  fact  doubted  at  all,  they 
cannot  be  more  satisfactory  than  they  are. 

3.  Some  people  seem  to  love  to  argue  a  point  after  all 
the  world  is  fully  convinced  of  it.     But  no  further  advance 
can  be  made.    When  doubt  ceases,  mental  action  on  the 
subject  comes  to  an  end;  and,  if  it  did  go  on,  it  would  be 
without  a  purpose. 


If  the  settlement  of  opinion  is  the  sole  object  of  inquiry, 
and  if  belief  is  of  the  nature  of  a  habit,  why  should  we  not 
attain  the  desired  end,  by  taking  any  answer  to  a  question, 
which  we  may  fancy,  and  constantly  reiterating  it  to  our 
selves,  dwelling  on  all  which  may  conduce  to  that  belief, 


1 8  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

and  learning  to  turn  with  contempt  and  hatred  from  any 
thing  which  might  disturb  it?  This  simple  and  direct 
method  is  really  pursued  by  many  men.  I  remember  once 
being  entreated  not  to  read  a  certain  newspaper  lest  it  might 
change  my  opinion  upon  free-trade.  "  Lest  I  might  be  en 
trapped  by  its  fallacies  and  misstatements,"  was  the  form  of 
expression.  "You  are  not,"  my  friend  said,  "a  special 
student  of  political  economy.  You  might,  therefore,  easily 
be  deceived  by  fallacious  arguments  upon  the  subject.  You 
might,  then,  if  you  read  this  paper,  be  led  to  believe  in 
protection.  But  you  admit  that  free-trade  is  the  true  doc 
trine;  and  you  do  not  wish  to  believe  what  is  not  true." 
I  have  often  known  this  system  to  be  deliberately  adopted. 
Still  oftener,  the  instinctive  dislike  of  an  undecided  state 
of  mind,  exaggerated  into  a  vague  dread  of  doubt,  makes 
men  cling  spasmodically  to  the  views  they  already  take. 
The  man  feels  that,  if  he  only  holds  to  his  belief  without 
wavering,  it  will  be  entirely  satisfactory.  Nor  can  it  be 
denied  that  a  steady  and  immovable  faith  yields  great  peace 
of  mind.  It  may,  indeed,  give  rise  to  inconveniences,  as  if 
a  man  should  resolutely  continue  to  believe  that  fire  would 
not  burn  him,  or  that  he  would  be  eternally  damned  if  he 
received  his  ingesta  otherwise  than  through  a  stomach- 
pump.  But  then  the  man  who  adopts  this  method  will  not 
allow  that  its  inconveniences  are  greater  than  its  advantages. 
He  will  say,  "  I  hold  steadfastly  to  the  truth  and  the  truth 
is  always  wholesome."  And  in  many  cases  it  may  very 
well  be  that  the  pleasure  he  derives  from  his  calm  faith 
overbalances  any  inconveniences  resulting  from  its  decep 
tive  character.  Thus,  if  it  be  true  that  death  is  annihila- 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  19 

tion,  then  the  man  who  believes  that  he  will  certainly  go 
straight  to  heaven  when  he  dies,  provided  he  have  fulfilled 
certain  simple  observances  in  this  life,  has  a  cheap  pleasure 
which  will  not  be  followed  by  the  least  disappointment. 
A  similar  consideration  seems  to  have  weight  with  many 
persons  in  religious  topics,  for  we  frequently  hear  it  said, 
"  Oh,  I  could  not  believe  so-and-so,  because  I  should  be 
wretched  if  I  did."  When  an  ostrich  buries  its  head  in  the 
sand  as  danger  approaches,  it  very  likely  takes  the  happiest 
course.  It  hides  the  danger,  and  then  calmly  says  there 
is  no  danger;  and,  if  it  feels  perfectly  sure  there  is  none, 
why  should  it  raise  its  head  to  see?  A  man  may  go  through 
life,  systematically  keeping  out  of  view  all  that  might  cause 
a  change  in  his  opinions,  and  if  he  only  succeeds  —  basing 
his  method,  as  he  does,  on  two  fundamental  psychological 
laws  —  I  do  not  see  what  can  be  said  against  his  doing  so. 
It  would  be  an  egotistical  impertinence  to  object  that  his 
procedure  is  irrational,  for  that  only  amounts  to  saying 
that  his  method  of  settling  belief  is  not  ours.  He  does  not 
propose  to  himself  to  be  rational,  and  indeed,  will  often 
talk  with  scorn  of  man's  weak  and  illusive  reason.  So  let 
him  think  as  he  pleases. 

But  this  method  of  fixing  belief,  which  may  be  called 
the  method  of  tenacity,  will  be  unable  to  hold  its  ground 
in  practice.  The  social  impulse  is  against  it.  The  man 
who  adopts  it  will  find  that  other  men  think  differently  from 
him,  and  it  will  be  apt  to  occur  to  him  in  some  saner  moment 
that  their  opinions  are  quite  as  good  as  his  own,  and  this 
will  shake  his  confidence  in  his  belief.  This  conception, 
that  another  man's  thought  or  sentiment  may  be  equivalent 


20  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

to  one's  own,  is  a  distinctly  new  step,  and  a  highly  important 
one.  It  arises  from  an  impulse  too  strong  in  man  to  be 
suppressed,  without  danger  of  destroying  the  human  species. 
Unless  we  make  ourselves  hermits,  we  shall  necessarily  in 
fluence  each  other's  opinions;  so  that  the  problem  becomes 
how  to  fix  belief,  not  in  the  individual  merely,  but  in  the 
community. 

Let  the  will  of  the  state  act,  then,  instead  of  that  of  the 
individual.  Let  an  institution  be  created  which  shall  have 
for  its  object  to  keep  correct  doctrines  before  the  attention 
of  the  people,  to  reiterate  them  perpetually,  and  to  teach 
them  to  the  young;  having  at  the  same  time  power  to  pre 
vent  contrary  doctrines  from  being  taught,  advocated,  or 
expressed.  Let  all  possible  causes  of  a  change  of  mind 
be  removed  from  men's  apprehensions.  Let  them  be  kept 
ignorant,  lest  they  should  learn  of  some  reason  to  think 
otherwise  than  they  do.  Let  their  passions  be  enlisted,  so 
that  they  may  regard  private  and  unusual  opinions  with 
hatred  and  horror.  Then,  let  all  men  who  reject  the  estab 
lished  belief  be  terrified  into  silence.  Let  the  people  turn 
out  and  tar-and-feather  such  men,  or  let  inquisitions  be 
made  into  the  manner  of  thinking  of  suspected  persons, 
and,  when  they  are  found  guilty  of  forbidden  beliefs,  let 
them  be  subjected  to  some  signal  punishment.  When  com 
plete  agreement  could  not  otherwise  be  reached,  a  general 
massacre  of  all  who  have  not  thought  in  a  certain  way  has 
proved  a  very  effective  means  of  settling  opinion  in  a 
country.  If  the  power  to  do  this  be  wanting,  let  a  list  of 
opinions  be  drawn  up,  to  which  no  man  of  the  least  inde 
pendence  of  thought  can  assent,  and  let  the  faithful  be  re- 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  ai 

quired  to  accept  all  these  propositions,  in  order  to  segregate 
them  as  radically  as  possible  from  the  influence  of  the  rest 
of  the  world. 

This  method  has,  from  the  earliest  times,  been  one  of 
the  chief  means  of  upholding  correct  theological  and  politi 
cal  doctrines,  and  of  preserving  their  universal  or  catholic  w 
character.  In  Rome,  especially,  it  has  been  practiced  from 
the  days  of  Numa  Pompilius  to  those  of  Pius  Nonus.  This 
is  the  most  perfect  example  in  history;  but  wherever  there 
is  a  priesthood  —  and  no  religion  has  been  without  one  — 
this  method  has  been  more  or  less  made  use  of.  Wherever 
there  is  aristocracy,  or  a  guild,  or  any  association  of  a  class 
of  men  whose  interests  depend  or  are  supposed  to  depend 
on  certain  propositions,  there  will  be  inevitably  found  some 
traces  of  this  natural  product  of  social  feeling.  Cruelties 
always  accompany  this  system;  and  when  it  is  consistently 
carried  out,  they  become  atrocities  of  the  most  horrible 
kind  in  the  eyes  of  any  rational  man.  Nor  should  this 
occasion  surprise,  for  the  officer  of  a  society  does  not  feel 
justified  in  surrendering  the  interests  of  that  society  for 
the  sake  of  mercy,  as  he  might  his  own  private  interests. 
It  is  natural,  therefore,  that  sympathy  and  fellowship  should 
thus  produce  a  most  ruthless  power. 

In  judging  this  method  of  fixing  belief,  which  may  be  N 
called  the  method  of  authority,  we  must  in  the  first  place, 
allow  its  immeasurable  mental  and  moral  superiority  to 
the  method  of  tenacity.  Its  success  is  proportionally 
greater;  and  in  fact  it  has  over  and  over  again  worked  the 
most  majestic  results.  The  mere  structures  of  stone  which 
it  has  caused  to  be  put  together  —  in  Siam,  for  example, 


22  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

in  Egypt,  and  in  Europe  —  have  many  of  them  a  sublimity 
hardly  more  than  rivaled  by  the  greatest  works  of  Nature. 
And,  except  the  geological  epochs,  there  are  no  periods  of 
time  so  vast  as  those  which  are  measured  by  some  of  these 
organized  faiths.  If  we  scrutinize  the  matter  closely,  we 
shall  find  that  there  has  not  been  one  of  their  creeds  which 
has  remained  always  the  same;  yet  the  change  is  so  slow 
as  to  be  imperceptible  during  one  person's  life,  so  that  in 
dividual  belief  remains  sensibly  fixed.  For  the  mass  of 
mankind,  then,  there  is  perhaps  no  better  method  than  this. 
If  it  is  their  highest  impulse  to  be  intellectual  slaves,  then 
slaves  they  ought  to  remain. 

But  no  institution  can  undertake  to  regulate  opinions 
upon  every  subject.  Only  the  most  important  ones  can  be 
attended  to,  and  on  the  rest  men's  minds  must  be  left  to 
the  action  of  natural  causes.  This  imperfection  will  be 
no  source  of  weakness  so  long  as  men  are  in  such  a  state 
of  culture  that  one  opinion  does  not  influence  another  — 
that  is,  so  long  as  they  cannot  put  two  and  two  together. 
But  in  the  most  priest-ridden  states  some  individuals  will 
be  found  who  are  raised  above  that  condition.  These  men 
possess  a  wider  sort  of  social  feeling;  they  see  that  men  in 
other  countries  and  in  other  ages  have  held  to  very  different 
doctrines  from  those  which  they  themselves  have  been 
brought  up  to  believe;  and  they  cannot  help  seeing  that  it 
is  the  mere  accident  of  their  having  been  taught  as  they 
have,  and  of  their  having  been  surrounded  with  the  manners 
and  associations  they  have,  that  has  caused  them  to  believe 
as  they  do  and  not  far  differently.  And  their  candor  can 
not  resist  the  reflection  that  there  is  no  reason  to  rate  their 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  23 

own  views  at  a  higher  value  than  those  of  other  nations 
and  other  centuries;  and  this  gives  rise  to  doubts  in  their 
minds. 

They  will  further  perceive  that  such  doubts  as  these 
must  exist  in  their  minds  with  reference  to  every  belief 
which  seems  to  be  determined  by  the  caprice  either  of 
themselves  or  of  those  who  originated  the  popular  opinions. 
The  willful  adherence  to  a  belief,  and  the  arbitrary  forcing 
of  it  upon  others,  must,  therefore,  both  be  given  up  and  a 
new  method  of  settling  opinions  must  be  adopted,  which 
shall  not  only  produce  an  impulse  to  believe,  but  shall  also 
decide  what  proposition  it  is  which  is  to  be  believed.  Let 
the  action  of  natural  preferences  be  unimpeded,  then,  and 
under  their  influence  let  men  conversing  together  and  re 
garding  matters  in  different  lights,  gradually  develop  beliefs 
in  harmony  with  natural  causes.  This  method  resembles 
that  by  which  conceptions  of  art  have  been  brought  to 
maturity.  The  most  perfect  example  of  it  is  to  be  found 
in  the  history  of  metaphysical  philosophy.  Systems  of  this 
sort  have  not  usually  rested  upon  observed  facts,  at  least 
not  in  any  great  degree.  They  have  been  chiefly  adopted 
because  their  fundamental  propositions  seemed  "  agreeable 
to  reason."  This  is  an  apt  expression;  it  does  not  mean 
that  which  agrees  with  experience,  but  that  which  we  find 
ourselves  inclined  to  believe.  Plato,  for  example,  finds  it 
agreeable  to  reason  that  the  distances  of  the  celestial  spheres 
from  one  another  should  be  proportional  to  the  different 
lengths  of  strings  which  produce  harmonious  chords.  Many 
philosophers  have  been  led  to  their  main  conclusions  by 
considerations  like  this;  but  this  is  the  lowest  and  least 


24  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

developed  form  which  the  method  takes,  for  it  is  clear  that 
another  man  might  find  Kepler's  [earlier]  theory,  that  the 
celestial  spheres  are  proportional  to  the  inscribed  and  cir 
cumscribed  spheres  of  the  different  regular  solids,  more 
agreeable  to  his  reason.  But  the  shock  of  opinions  will  soon 
lead  men  to  rest  on  preferences  of  a  far  more  universal 
nature.  Take,  for  example,  the  doctrine  that  man  only 
acts  selfishly  —  that  is,  from  the  consideration  that  acting 
in  one  way  will  afford  him  more  pleasure  than  acting  in 
another.  This  rests  on  no  fact  in  the  world,  but  it  has  had 
a  wide  acceptance  as  being  the  only  reasonable  theory. 

This  method  is  far  more  intellectual  and  respectable 
from  the  point  of  view  of  reason  than  either  of  the  others 
which  we  have  noticed.  But  its  failure  has  been  the  most 
manifest.  It  makes  of  inquiry  something  similar  to  the 
development  of  taste;  but  taste,  unfortunately,  is  always 
more  or  less  a  matter  of  fashion,  and  accordingly,  meta 
physicians  have  never  come  to  any  fixed  agreement,  but 
the  pendulum  has  swung  backward  and  forward  between 
a  more  material  and  a  more  spiritual  philosophy,  from  the 
earliest  times  to  the  latest.  And  so  from  this,  which  has 
been  called  the  a  priori  method,  we  are  driven,  in  Lord 
Bacon's  phrase,  to  a  true  induction.  We  have  examined 
into  this  a  priori  method  as  something  which  promised  to 
deliver  our  opinions  from  their  accidental  and  capricious 
element.  But  development,  while  it  is  a  process  which 
eliminates  the  effect  of  some  casual  circumstances,  only 
magnifies  that  of  others.  This  method,  therefore,  does  not 
differ  in  a  very  essential  way  from  that  of  authority.  The 
government  may  not  have  lifted  its  finger  to  influence  my 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  a$ 

convictions;  I  may  have  been  left  outwardly  quite  free  to 
choose,  we  will  say,  between  monogamy  and  polygamy, 
and  appealing  to  my  conscience  only,  I  may  have  concluded 
that  the  latter  practice  is  in  itself  licentious.  But  when  I 
come  to  see  that  the  chief  obstacle  to  the  spread  of  Chris 
tianity  among  a  people  of  as  high  culture  as  the  Hindoos 
has  been  a  conviction  of  the  immorality  of  our  way  of 
treating  women,  I  cannot  help  seeing  that,  though  govern 
ments  do  not  interfere,  sentiments  in  their  development 
will  be  very  greatly  determined  by  accidental  causes.  Now, 
there  are  some  people,  among  whom  I  must  suppose  that 
my  reader  is  to  be  found,  who,  when  they  see  that  any  be 
lief  of  theirs  is  determined  by  any  circumstance  extraneous 
to  the  facts,  will  from  that  moment  not  merely  admit  in 
words  that  that  belief  is  doubtful,  but  will  experience  a  real 
doubt  of  it,  so  that  it  ceases  to  be  a  belief. 

To  satisfy  our  doubts,  therefore,  it  is  necessary  that  a 
method  should  be  found  by  which  our  beliefs  may  be  caused 
by  nothing  human,  but  by  some  external  permanency  — 
by  something  upon  which  our  thinking  has  no  effect.  Some 
mystics  imagine  that  they  have  such  a  method  in  a  private 
inspiration  from  on  high.  But  that  is  only  a  form  of  the 
method  of  tenacity,  in  which  the  conception  of  truth  as 
something  public  is  not  yet  developed.  Our  External  per-  "^ 
manency  would  not  be  external,  in  our  sense,  if  it  was  re 
stricted  in  its  influence  to  one  individual.  It  must  be  some 
thing  which  affects,  or  might  affect,  every  man.  And, 
though  these  affections  are  necessarily  as  various  as  are 
individual  conditions,  yet  the  method  must  be  such  that 
the  ultimate  conclusion  of  every  man  shall  be  the  same. 


26  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

Such  is  the  method  of  science.  Its  fundamental  hypothesis, 
restated  in  more  familiar  language,  is  this:  There  are  real 
things;  whose  characters  are  entirely  independent  of  our 
opinions  about  them;  whose  realities  affect  our  senses  ac 
cording  to  regular  laws,  and,  though  our  sensations  are 
as  different  as  our  relations  to  the  objects,  yet,  by  taking 
advantage  of  the  laws  of  perception,  we  can  ascertain  by 
reasoning  how  things  really  are,  and  any  man,  if  he  have  suf 
ficient  experience  and  reason  enough  about  it,  will  be  led  to 
the  one  true  conclusion.  The  new  conception  here  involved 
is  that  of  reality.  It  may  be  asked  how  I  know  that  there 
are  any  realities.  If  this  hypothesis  is  the  sole  support  of 
my  method  of  inquiry,  my  method  of  inquiry  must  not  be 
used  to  support  my  hypothesis.  The  reply  is  this:  i.  If 
investigation  cannot  be  regarded  as  proving  that  there  are 
real  things,  it  at  least  does  not  lead  to  a  contrary  conclu 
sion;  but  the  method  and  the  conception  on  which  it  is 
based  remain  ever  in  harmony.  No  doubts  of  the  method, 
therefore,  necessarily  arise  from  its  practice,  as  is  the  case 
with  all  the  others.  2.  The  feeling  which  gives  rise  to  any 
method  of  fixing  belief  is  a  dissatisfaction  at  two  repugnant 
propositions.  But  here  already  is  a  vague  concession  that 
there  is  some  one  thing  to  which  a  proposition  should  con 
form.  Nobody,  therefore,  can  really  doubt  that  there  are 
realities,  or,  if  he  did,  doubt  would  not  be  a  source  of  dis 
satisfaction.  The  hypothesis,  therefore,  is  one  which  every 
mind  admits.  So  that  the  social  impulse  does  not  cause 
me  to  doubt  it.  3.  Everybody  uses  the  scientific  method 
about  a  great  many  things,  and  only  ceases  to  use  it  when 
he  does  not  know  how  to  apply  it.  4.  Experience  of  the 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  27 

method  has  not  led  me  to  doubt  it,  but,  on  the  contrary, 
scientific  investigation  has  had  the  most  wonderful  triumphs 
in  the  way  of  settling  opinion.  These  afford  the  explana 
tion  of  my  not  doubting  the  method  or  the  hypothesis  which 
it  supposes;  and  not  having  any  doubt,  nor  believing  that 
anybody  else  whom  I  could  influence  has,  it  would  be  the 
merest  babble  for  me  to  say  more  about  it.  If  there  be 
anybody  with  a  living  doubt  upon  the  subject,  let  him 
consider  it. 

To  describe  the  method  of  scientific  investigation  is  the 
object  of  this  series  of  papers.  At  present  I  have  only  room 
to  notice  some  points  of  contrast  between  it  and  other 
methods  of  fixing  belief. 

This  is  the  only  one  of  the  four  methods  which  presents 
any  distinction  of  a  right  and  a  wrong  way.  If  I  adopt  the 
method  of  tenacity  and  shut  myself  out  from  all  influences, 
whatever  I  think  necessary  to  doing  this  is  necessary  accord 
ing  to  that  method.  So  with  the  method  of  authority:  the 
state  may  try  to  put  down  heresy  by  means  which,  from  a 
scientific  point  of  view,  seems  very  ill-calculated  to  ac 
complish  its  purposes;  but  the  only  test  on  that  method  is 
what  the  state  thinks,  so  that  it  cannot  pursue  the  method 
wrongly.  So  with  the  a  priori  method.  The  very  essence  of 
it  is  to  think  as  one  is  inclined  to  think.  All  metaphysicians 
will  be  sure  to  do  that,  however  they  may  be  inclined  to 
judge  each  other  to  be  perversely  wrong.  The  Hegelian 
system  recognizes  every  natural  tendency  of  thought  as 
logical,  although  it  is  certain  to  be  abolished  by  counter- 
tendencies.  Hegel  thinks  there  is  a  regular  system  in  the 
succession  of  these  tendencies,  in  consequence  of  which, 


3S  CHANCE   AND    LOGIC 

after  drifting  one  way  and  the  other  for  a  long  time,  opinion 
will  at  last  go  right.  And  it  is  true  that  metaphysicians  get 
the  right  ideas  at  last;  Hegel's  system  of  Nature  represents 
tolerably  the  science  of  that  day;  and  one  may  be  sure  that 
whatever  scientific  investigation  has  put  out  of  doubt  will 
presently  receive  a  priori  demonstration  on  the  part  of  the 
metaphysicians.  But  with  the  scientific  method  the  case 
is  different.  I  may  start  with  known  and  observed  facts 
to  proceed  to  the  unknown;  and  yet  the  rules  which  I  follow 
in  doing  so  may  not  be  such  as  investigation  would  ap 
prove.  The  test  af  whether  I  am  truly  following  the 
method  is  not  an  immediate  appeal  to  my  feelings  and  pur 
poses,  but,  on  the  contrary,  itself  involves  the  application 
of  the  method.  Hence  it  is  that  bad  reasoning  as  well  as 
good  reasoning  is  possible;  and  this  fact  is  the  foundation 
of  the  practical  side  of  logic. 

It  is  not  to  be  supposed  that  the  first  three  methods  of 
settling  opinion  present  no  advantage  whatever  over  the 
scientific  method.  On  the  contrary,  each  has  some  peculiar 
convenience  of  its  own.  The  a  priori  method  is  distin 
guished  for  its  comfortable  conclusions.  It  is  the  nature 
of  the  process  to  adopt  whatever  belief  we  are  inclined  to, 
and  there  are  certain  flatteries  to  one's  vanities  which  we 
all  believe  by  nature,  until  we  are  awakened  from  our  pleas 
ing  dream  by  rough  facts.  The  method  of  authority  will 
always  govern  the  mass  of  mankind;  and  those  who  wield 
the  various  forms  of  organized  force  in  the  state  will  never 
be  convinced  that  dangerous  reasoning  ought  not  to  be 
suppressed  in  some  way.  If  liberty  of  speech  is  to  be  un- 
trammeled  from  the  grosser  forms  of  constraint,  then  uni- 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  29 

formity  of  opinion  will  be  secured  by  a  moral  terrorism  to 
which  the  respectability  of  society  will  give  its  thorough 
approval.  Following  the  method  of  authority  is  the  path 
of  peace.  Certain  non-conformities  are  permitted;  certain 
others  (considered  unsafe)  are  forbidden.  These  are  dif 
ferent  in  different  countries  and  in  different  ages;  but, 
wherever  you  are  let  it  be  known  that  you  seriously  hold 
a  tabooed  belief,  and  you  may  be  perfectly  sure  of  being 
treated  with  a  cruelty  no  less  brutal  but  more  refined  than 
hunting  you  like  a  wolf.  Thus,  the  greatest  intellectual 
benefactors  of  mankind  have  never  dared,  and  dare  not 
now,  to  utter  the  whole  of  their  thought;  and  thus  a  shade 
of  prima  jade  doubt  is  cast  upon  every  proposition  which 
is  considered  essential  to  the  security  of  society.  Singu 
larly  enough,  the  persecution  does  not  all  come  from  with 
out;  but  a  man  torments  himself  and  is  oftentimes  most 
distressed  at  finding  himself  believing  propositions  which 
he  has  been  brought  up  to  regard  with  aversion.  The 
peaceful  and  sympathetic  man  will,  therefore,  find  it  hard 
to  resist  the  temptation  to  submit  his  opinions  to  authority. 
But  most  of  all  I  admire  the  method  of  tenacity  for  its 
strength,  simplicity,  and  directness.  Men  who  pursue  it 
are  distinguished  for  their  decision  of  character,  which  be 
comes  very  easy  with  such  a  mental  rule.  They  do  not 
waste  time  in  trying  to  make  up  their  minds  to  what  they 
want,  but,  fastening  like  lightning  upon  whatever  alterna 
tive  comes  first,  they  hold  to  it  to  the  end,  whatever 
happens,  without  an  instant's  irresolution.  This  is  one  of 
the  splendid  qualities  which  generally  accompany  brilliant, 
unlasting  success.  It  is  impossible  not  to  envy  the  man  who 


30  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

can  dismiss  reason,  although  we  know  how  it  must  turn  out 
at  last. 

Such  are  the  advantages  which  the  other  methods  of 
settling  opinions  have  over  scientific  investigation.  A  man 
should  consider  well  of  them;  and  then  he  should  consider 
that,  after  all,  he  wishes  his  opinions  to  coincide  with  the 
fact,  and  that  there  is  no  reason  why  the  results  of  these 
three  methods  should  do  so.  To  bring  about  this  effect  is  the 
prerogative  of  the  method  of  science.  Upon  such  considera 
tions  he  has  to  make  his  choice  —  a  choice  which  is  far 
more  than  the  adoption  of  any  intellectual  opinion,  which 
is  one  of  the  ruling  decisions  of  his  life,  to  which  when  once 
made  he  is  bound  to  adhere.  The  force  of  habit  will  some 
times  cause  a  man  to  hold  on  to  old  beliefs,  after  he  is  in 
a  condition  to  see  that  they  have  no  sound  basis.  But  re 
flection  upon  the  state  of  the  case  will  overcome  these 
habits,  and  he  ought  to  allow  reflection  full  weight.  People 
sometimes  shrink  from  doing  this,  having  an  idea  that  be 
liefs  are  wholesome  which  they  cannot  help  feeling  rest  on 
nothing.  But  let  such  persons  suppose  an  analogous  though 
different  case  from  their  own.  Let  them  ask  themselves 
what  they  would  say  to  a  reformed  Mussulman  who  should 
hesitate  to  give  up  his  old  notions  in  regard  to  the  relations 
of  the  sexes;  or  to  a  reformed  Catholic  who  should  still 
shrink  from  the  Bible.  Would  they  not  say  that  these 
persons  ought  to  consider  the  matter  fully,  and  clearly 
understand  the  new  doctrine,  and  then  ought  to  embrace  it 
in  its  entirety?  But,  above  all,  let  it  be  considered  that 
what  is  more  wholesome  than  any  particular  belief,  is  in 
tegrity  of  belief;  and  that  to  avoid  looking  into  the  support 


THE    FIXATION    OF    BELIEF  31 

of  any  belief  from  a  fear  that  it  may  turn  out  rotten  is 
quite  as  immoral  as  it  is  disadvantageous.  The  person  who 
confesses  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as  truth,  which  is  dis 
tinguished  from  falsehood  simply  by  this,  that  if  acted  on 
it  will  carry  us  to  the  point  we  aim  at  and  not  astray,  and 
then  though  convinced  of  this,  dares  not  know  the  truth 
and  seeks  to  avoid  it,  is  in  a  sorry  state  of  mind,  indeed. 

Yes,  the  other  methods  do  have  their  merits:  a  clear 
logical  conscience  does  cost  something  —  just  as  any  virtue, 
just  as  all  that  we  cherish,  costs  us  dear.  But,  we  should 
not  desire  it  to  be  otherwise.  The  genius  of  a  man's  logical 
method  should  be  loved  and  reverenced  as  his  bride,  whom 
he  has  chosen  from  all  the  world.  He  need  not  condemn 
the  others;  on  the  contrary,  he  may  honor  them  deeply, 
and  in  doing  so  he  only  honors  her  the  more.  But  she  is 
the  one  that  he  has  chosen,  and  he  knows  that  he  was  right 
in  making  that  choice.  And  having  made  it,  he  will  work 
and  fight  for  her,  and  will  not  complain  that  there  are  blows 
to  take,  hoping  that  there  may  be  as  many  and  as  hard  to 
give,  and  will  strive  to  be  the  worthy  knight  and  champion 
of  her  from  the  blaze  of  whose  splendors  he  draws  his 
inspiration  and  his  courage. 


A  ffkrn 


SECOND    PAPER 
HOW   TO    MAKE   OUR   IDEAS   CLEAR1 


WHOEVER  has  looked  into  a  modern  treatise  on  logic  of  the 
common  sort,  will  doubtless  remember  the  two  distinctions 
between  clear  and  obscure  conceptions,  and  between  dis 
tinct  and  confused  conceptions.  They  have  lain  in  the 
books  now  for  nigh  two  centuries,  unimproved  and  un 
modified,  and  are  generally  reckoned  by  logicians  as  among 
the  gems  of  their  doctrine. 

A  clear  idea  is  defined  as  one  which  is  so  apprehended 
that  it  will  be  recognized  wherever  it  is  met  with,  and  so 
that  no  other  will  be  mistaken  for  it.^  If  it  fails  of  this 
clearness,  it  is  said  to  be  obscure. 

This  is  rather  a  neat  bit  of  philosophical  terminology; 
yet,  since  it  is  clearness  that  they  were  defining,  I  wish  the 
logicians  had  made  their  definition  a  little  more  plain. 
Never  to  fail  to  recognize  an  idea,  and  under  no  circum 
stances  to  mistake  another  for  it,  let  it  come  in  how  rec 
ondite  a  form  it  may,  would  indeed  imply  such  prodigious 
force  and  clearness  of  intellect  as  is  seldom  met  with  in  this 
world.  On  the  other  hand,  merely  to  have  such  an  ac 
quaintance  with  the  idea  as  to  have  become  familiar  with  it, 
and  to  have  lost  all  hesitancy  in  recognizing  it  in  ordinary 


1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  January,  1878. 

32 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  33 

cases,  hardly  seems  to  deserve  the  name  of  clearness  of 
apprehension,  since  after  all  it  only  amounts  to  a  subjective 
feeling  of  mastery  which  may  be  entirely  mistaken.  I  take 
it,  however,  that  when  the  logicians  speak  of  "  clearness," 
they  mean  nothing  more  than  such  a  familiarity  with  an 
idea,  since  they  regard  the  quality  as  but  a  small  merit, 
which  needs  to  be  supplemented  by  another,  which  they  call 
distinctness. 

A  distinct  idea  is  defined  as  one  which  contains  nothing 
which  is  not  clear.  This  is  technical  language;  by  the 
contents  of  an  idea  logicians  understand  whatever  is  con 
tained  in  its  definition.  So  that  an  idea  is  distinctly  appre 
hended,  according  to  them,  when  we  can  give  a  precise 
definition  of  it,  in  abstract  terms.  Here  the  professional 
logicians  leave  the  subject;  and  I  would  not  have  troubled 
the  reader  with  what  they  have  to  say,  if  it  were  not  such 
a  striking  example  of  how  they  have  been  slumbering 
through  ages  of  intellectual  activity,  listlessly  disregarding 
the  enginery  of  modern  thought,  and  never  dreaming  of 
applying  its  lessons  to  the  improvement  of  logic.  It  is  easy 
to  show  that  the  doctrine  that  familiar  use  and  abstract 
distinctness  make  the  perfection  of  apprehension,  has  its 
only  true  place  in  philosophies  which  have  long  been  ex 
tinct;  and  it  is  now  time  to  formulate  the  method  of  attain-, 
ing  to  a  more  perfect  clearness  of  thought,  such  as  we  see 
and  admire  in  the  thinkers  of  our  own  time. 

When  Descartes  set  about  the  reconstruction  of  philoso 
phy,  his  first  step  was  to  (theoretically)  permit  skepticism 
and  to  discard  the  practice  of  the  schoolmen  of  looking  to 
authority  as  the  ultimate  source  of  truth.  That  done,  he 


34  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

sought  a  more  natural  fountain  of  true  principles,  and  pro 
fessed  to  find  it  in  the  human  mind;  thus  passing,  in  the 
directest  way,  from  the  method  of  authority  to  that  of 
apriority,  as  described  in  my  first  paper.  Self -conscious 
ness  was  to  furnish  us  with  our  fundamental  truths,  and  to 
decide  what  was  agreeable  to  reason.  But  since,  evidently, 
not  all  ideas  are  true,  he  was  led  to  note,  as  the  first  condi 
tion  of  infallibility,  that  they  must  be  clear. ,  The  distinc 
tion  between  an  idea  seeming  clear  and  really  being  so, 
never  occurred  to  him.  Trusting  to  introspection,  as  he 
did,  even  for  a  knowledge  of  external  things,  why  should 
he  question  its  testimony  in  respect  to  the  contents  of  our 
own  minds?  But  then,  I  suppose,  seeing  men,  who  seemed 
to  be  quite  clear  and  positive,  holding  opposite  opinions 
upon  fundamental  principles,  he  was  further  led  to  say  that 
clearness  of  ideas  is  not  sufficient,  but  that  they  need  also 
to  be  distinct,  i.e.,  to  have  nothing  unclear  about  them. 
What  he  probably  meant  by  this  (for  he  did  not  explain 
himself  with  precision)  was,  that  they  must  sustain  the  test 
of  dialectkal  examination;  that  they  must  not  only  seem 
clear  at  the  outset,  but  that  discussion  must  never  be  able 
to  bring  to  light  points  of  obscurity  connected  with  them. 
Such  was  the  distinction  of  Descartes,  and  one  sees  that 
it  was  precisely  on  the  level  of  his  philosophy.  It  was 
somewhat  developed  by  Leibnitz.  This  great  and  singular 
genius  was  as  remarkable  for  what  he  failed  to  see  as  for 
what  he  saw.  That  a  piece  of  mechanism  could  not  do 
work  perpetually  without  being  fed  with  power  in  some 
form,  was  a  thing  perfectly  apparent  to  him;  yet  he  did  not 
understand  that  the  machinery  of  the  mind  can  only  trans- 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  35 

I  form  knowledge,  but  never  originate  it,  unless  it  be  fed 
V  with  facts  of  observation.  He  thus  missed  the  most  essen 
tial  point  of  the  Cartesian  philosophy,  which  is,  that  to 
accept  propositions  which  seem  perfectly  evident  to  us  is 
a  thing  which,  whether  it  be  logical  or  illogical,  we  cannot 
help  doing.  Instead  of  regarding  the  matter  in  this  way, 
he  sought  to  reduce  the  first  principles  of  science  to  formulas 
which  cannot  be  denied  without  self-contradiction,  and  was 
apparently  unaware  of  the  great  difference  between  his 
position  and  that  of  Descartes.  So  he  reverted  to  the  old 
formalities  of  logic,  and,  above  all,  abstract  definitions 
played  a  great  part  in  his  philosophy.  It  was  quite  natural, 
therefore,  that  on  observing  that  the  method  of  Descartes 
labored  under  the  difficulty  that  we  may  seem  to  ourselves 
to  have  clear  apprehensions  of  ideas  which  in  truth  are 
very  hazy,  no  better  remedy  occurred  to  him  than  to  re 
quire  an  abstract  definition  of  every  important  term.  Ac 
cordingly,  in  adopting  the  distinction  of  clear  and  distinct 
notions,  he  described  the  latter  quality  as  the  clear  appre 
hension  of  everything  contained  in  the  definition;  and  the 
books  have  ever  since  copied  his  words.  There  is  no  danger 
that  his  chimerical  scheme  will  ever  again  be  over-valued. 
V  Nothing  new  can  ever  be  learned  by  analyzing  definitions. 
-  Nevertheless,  our  existing  beliefs  can  be  set  in  order  by  this 
process,  and  order  is  an  essential  element  of  intellectual 
economy,  as  of  every  other.  It  may  be  acknowledged, 
therefore,  that  the  books  are  right  in  making  familiarity 
with  a  notion  the  first  step  toward  clearness  of  apprehen 
sion,  and  the  denning  of  it  the  second.  But  in  omitting 
all  mention  of  any  higher  perspicuity  of  thought,  they 


36  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

simply  mirror  a  philosophy  which  was  exploded  a  hundred 
years  ago.  That  much-admired  "  ornament  of  logic  "  — 
the  doctrine  of  clearness  and  distinctness  —  may  be  pretty 
enough,  but  it  is  high  time  to  relegate  to  our  cabinet  of 
curiosities  the  antique  bijou,  and  to  wear  about  us  some 
thing  better  adapted  to  modern  uses. 

The  very  first  lesson  that  we  have  a  right  to  demand 
V  that  logic  shall  teach  us  is,  how  to  make  our  ideas  clear; 
and  a  most  important  one  it  is,  depreciated  only  by  minds 
who  stand  in  need  of  it.  To  know  what  we  think,  to  be 
\masters  of  our  own  meaning,  will  make  a  solid  foundation 
s  for  great  and  weighty  thought.  It  is  most  easily  learned 
by  those  whose  ideas  are  meagre  and  restricted;  and  far 
happier  they  than  such  as  wallow  helplessly  in  a  rich  mud 
of  conceptions.  A  nation,  it  is  true,  may,  in  the  course  of 
generations,  overcome  the  disadvantage  of  an  excessive 
wealth  of  language  and  its  natural  concomitant,  a  vast, 
unfathomable  deep  of  ideas.  We  may  see  it  in  history, 
slowly  perfecting  its  literary  forms,  sloughing  at  length  its 
metaphysics,  and,  by  virtue  of  the  untirable  patience  which 
is  often  a  compensation,  attaining  great  excellence  in  every 
branch  of  mental  acquirement.  The  page  of  history  is  not 
yet  unrolled  which  is  to  tell  us  whether  such  a  people  will 
or  will  not  in  the  long  run  prevail  over  one  whose  ideas 
(like  the  words  of  their  language)  are  few,  but  which  pos 
sesses  a  wonderful  mastery  over  those  which  it  has.  For 
an  individual,  however,  there  can  be  no  question  that  a 
few  clear  ideas  are  worth  more  than  many  confused  ones. 
A  young  man  would  hardly  be  persuaded  to  sacrifice  the 
greater  part  of  his  thoughts  to  save  the  rest;  and  the 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  37 

muddled  head  is  the  least  apt  to  see  the  necessity  of  such 
a  sacrifice.  Him  we  can  usually  only  commiserate,  as  a 
person  with  a  congenital  defect.  Time  will  help  him,  but 
intellectual  maturity  with  regard  to  clearness  comes  rather 
late,  an  unfortunate  arrangement  of  Nature,  inasmuch  as 
clearness  is  of  less  use  to  a  man  settled  in  life,  whose  errors 
have  in  great  measure  had  their  effect,  than  it  would  be 
to  one  whose  path  lies  before  him.  It  is  terrible  to  see  how 
a  single  unclear  idea,  a  single  formula  without  meaning, 
lurking  in  a  young  man's  head,  will  sometimes  act  like  an 
obstruction  of  inert  matter  in  an  artery,  hindering  the  nu 
trition  of  the  brain,  and  condemning  its  victim  to  pine  away 
in  the  fullness  of  his  intellectual  vigor  and  in  the  midst  of 
intellectual  plenty.  Many  a  man  has  cherished  for  years 
as  his  hobby  some  vague  shadow  of  an  idea,  too  meaning 
less  to  be  positively  false;  he  has,  nevertheless,  passionately 
loved  it,  has  made  it  his  companion  by  day  and  by  night, 
and  has  given  to  it  his  strength  and  his  life,  leaving  all  other 
occupations  for  its  sake,  and  in  short  has  lived  with  it  and 
for  it,  until  it  has  become,  as  it  were,  flesh  of  his  flesh  and 
bone  of  his  bone;  and  then  he  has  waked  up  some  bright 
morning  to  find  it  gone,  clean  vanished  away  like  the  beauti 
ful  Melusina  of  the  fable,  and  the  essence  of  his  life  gone 
with  it.  I  have  myself  known  such  a  man;  and  who  can 
tell  how  many  histories  of  circle-squarers,  metaphysicians, 
astrologers,  and  what  not,  may  not  be  told  in  the  old  German 
story? 


; 


38  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

II 

The  principles  set  forth  in  the  first  of  these  papers  lead, 
at  once,  to  a  method  of  reaching  a  clearness  of  thought  of 
a  far  higher  grade  than  the  "  distinctness  "  of  the  logicians. 
We  have  there  found  that  the  action  of  thought  is  excited 
by  the  irritation  of  doubt,  and  ceases  when  belief  is  at- 
tained^so  that  the  production  of  belief  is  the  sole  function 
of  thought.  All  these  words,  however,  are  too  strong  for 
my  purpose.  It  is  as  if  I  had  described  the  phenomena 
as  they  appear  under  a  mental  microscope.  Doubt  and 
Belief,  as  the  words  are  commonly  employed,  relate  to 
religious  or  other  grave  discussions.  But  here  I  use  them 
to  designate  the  starting  of  any  question,  no  matter  how 
small  or  how  great,  and  the  resolution  of  it.  If,  for  in 
stance,  in  a  horse-car,  I  pull  out  my  purse  and  find  a  five- 
cent  nickel  and  five  coppers,  I  decide,  while  my  hand  is 
going  to  the  purse,  in  which  way  I  will  pay  my  fare.  To 
call  such  a  question  Doubt,  and  my  decision  Belief,  is  cer 
tainly  to  use  words  very  disproportionate  to  the  occasion. 
To  speak  of  such  a  doubt  as  causing  an  irritation  which 
needs  to  be  appeased,  suggests  a  temper  which  is  uncom 
fortable  to  the  verge  of  insanity.  Yet,  looking  at  the  matter 
minutely,  it  must  be  admitted  that,  if  there  is  the  least 
hesitation  as  to  whether  I  shall  pay  the  five  coppers  or  the 
nickel  (as  there  will  be  sure  to  be,  unless  I  act  from  some 
previously  contracted  habit  in  the  matter),  though  irritation 
is  too  strong  a  word,  yet  I  am  excited  to  such  small  mental 
activity  as  may  be  necessary  to  deciding  how  I  shall  act. 
V  Most  frequently  doubts  arise  from  some  indecision,  however 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  39 

momentary,  in  our  action.  Sometimes  it  is  not  so.  I  have, 
for  example,  to  wait  in  a  railway-station,  and  to  pass  the 
time  I  read  the  advertisements  on  the  walls,  I  compare  the 
advantages  of  different  trains  and  different  routes  which 
I  never  expect  to  take,  merely  fancying  myself  to  be  in  a 
state  of  hesitancy,  because  I  am  bored  with  having  nothing 
to  trouble  me.  feigned  hesitancy,  whether  feigned  for 
mere  amusement  or  with  a  lofty  purpose,  plays  a  great  part 
in  the  production  of  scientific  inquiry.!/  However  the  doubt 
may  originate,  it  stimulates  the  mind  to  an  activity  which 
may  be  slight  or  energetic,  calm  or  turbulent.  Images  pass 
rapidly  through  consciousness,  one  incessantly  melting  into 
another,  until  at  last,  when  all  is  over  —  it  may  be  in  a 
fraction  of  a  second,  in  an  hour,  or  after  long  years  —  we 
find  ourselves  decided  as  to  how  we  should  act  under  such 
circumstances  as  those  which  occasioned  our  hesitation. 
In  other  words,  we  have  attained  belief. 

In  this  process  we  observe  two  sorts  of  elements  of  con 
sciousness,  the  distinction  between  which  may  best  be  made 
clear  by  means  of  an  illustration.  In  a  piece  of  music 
there  are  the  separate  notes,  and  there  is  the  air.  A  single 
tone  may  be  prolonged  for  an  hour  or  a  day,  and  it  exists 
as  perfectly  in  each  second  of  that  time  as  in  the  whole 
taken  together;  so  that,  as  long  as  it  is  sounding,  it  might 
be  present  to  a  sense  from  which  everything  in  the  past  was 
as  completely  absent  as  the  future  itself.  But  it  is  different 
with  the  air,  the  performance  of  which  occupies  a  certain 
time,  during  the  portions  of  which  only  portions  of  it  are 
played.  It  consists  in  an  orderliness  in  the  succession  of 
sounds  which  strike  the  ear  at  different  times;  and  to  per- 


40  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

ceive  it  there  must  be  some  continuity  of  consciousness 
which  makes  the  events  of  a  lapse  of  time  present  to  us. 
We  certainly  only  perceive  the  air  by  hearing  the  separate 
notes;  yet  we  cannot  be  said  to  directly  hear  it,  for  we  hear 
only  what  is  present  at  the  instant,  and  an  orderliness  of 
succession  cannot  exist  in  an  instant.  \These  two  sorts  of 
objects,  what  we  are  immediately  conscious  of  and  what 
we  are  mediately  conscious  of,  are  found  in  all  conscious 
ness.  Some  elements  (the  sensations)  are  completely  pres 
ent  at  every  instant  so  long  as  they  last,  while  others  (like 
thought)  are  actions  having  beginning,  middle,  and  end, 
and  consist  in  a  congruence  in  the  succession  of  sensations 
which  flow  through  the  mind.  They  cannot  be  immediately 
present  to  us,  but  must  cover  some  portion  of  the  past  or 
future.  Thought  is  a  thread  of  melody  running  through 
the  succession  of  our  sensations. 

We  may  add  that  just  as  a  piece  of  music  may  be  written 
in  parts,  each  part  having  its  own  air,  so  various  systems 
of  relationship  of  succession  subsist  together  between  the 
same  sensations.  These  different  systems  are  distinguished 
by  having  different  motives,  ideas,  or  functions.  Thought 
is  only  one  such  system;  for  its  sole  motive,  idea,  and  func- 
tion  is  to  produce  belief,  and  whatever  does  not  concern 
that  purpose  belongs  to  some  other  system  of  relations. 
The  action  of  thinking  may  incidentally  have  other  results. 
It  may  serve  to  amuse  us,  for  example,  and  among  dilettanti 
it  is  not  rare  to  find  those  who  have  so  perverted  thought 
to  the  purposes  of  pleasure  that  it  seems  to  vex  them  to 
think  that  the  questions  upon  which  they  delight  to  exercise 
it  may  ever  get  finally  settled;  and  a  positive  discovery 


HOW   TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  41 

which  takes  a  favorite  subject  out  of  the  arena  of  literary 
debate  is  met  with  ill-concealed  dislike.  This  disposition 
is  the  very  debauchery  of  thought.  But  the  soul  and  mean 
ing  of  thought,  abstracted  from  the  other  elements  which 
accompany  it,  though  it  may  be  voluntarily  thwarted,  can 
never  be  made  to  direct  itself  toward  anything  but  the  pro 
duction  of  belief.  Thought  in  action  has  for  its  only  pos- 

L  sible  motive  the  attainment  of  thought  at  rest;  and  whatever 
does  not  refer  to  belief  is  no  part  of  the  thought  itself. 

And  what,  then,  is  belief?  It  is  the  demi-cadence  which 
closes  a  musical  phrase  in  the  symphony  of  our  intellectual 
life.  We  have  seen  that  it  has  just  three  properties:  First, 

i  it  is  something  that  we  are  aware  of;  second,  it  appeases 
the  irritation  of  doubt;  and,  third,  it  involves  the  establish 
ment  in  our  nature  of  a  rule  of  action,  or,  say  for  short,  a 
habit.  As  it  appeases  the  irritation  of  doubt,  which  is  the 
motive  for  thinking,  thought  relaxes,  and  comes  to  rest  for 
a  moment  when  belief  is  reached.  But,  since  belief  is  a 
rule  for  action,  the  application  of  which  involves  further 
doubt  and  further  thought,  at  the  same  time  that  it  is  a 
stopping-place,  it  is  also  a  new  starting-place  for  thought.  ^ 
That  is  why  I  have  permitted  myself  to  call  it  thought  at 
rest,  although  thought  is  essentially  an  action.  The  final 
upshot  of  thinking  is  the  exercise  of  volition,  and  of  this 
thought  no  longer  forms  a  part;  but  belief  is  only  a  stadium 
of  mental  action,  an  effect  upon  our  nature  due  to  thought, 
which  will  influence  future  thinking. 

^  The  essence  of  belief  is  the  establishment  of  a  habit,, 
and  different  beliefs  are  distinguished  by  the  different  modes 
\of  action  to  which  they  give  rise.    If  beliefs  do  not  differ 


i 


42  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

in  this  respect,  if  they  appease  the  same  doubt  by  producing 
the  same  rule  of  action,  then  no  mere  differences  in  the 
manner  of  consciousness  of  them  can  make  them  different 
beliefs,  any  more  than  playing  a  tune  in  different  keys  is 
playing  different  tunes.  Imaginary  distinctions  are  often 
drawn  between  beliefs  which  differ  only  in  their  mode  of 
expression;  — the  wrangling  which  ensues  is  real  enough, 
however.  To  believe  that  any  objects  are  arranged  as  in 
Fig.  i,  and  to  believe  that  they  are  arranged  as  in  Fig.  2,  are 


Fig.  i  Fig.  2 

one  and  the  same  belief;  yet  it  is  conceivable  that  a  man 
should  assert  one  proposition  and  deny  the  other.  *  Such 
false  distinctions  do  as  much  harm  as  the  confusion  of  be 
liefs  really  different,  and  are  among  the  pitfalls  of  which  we 
ought  constantly  to  beware,  especially  when  we  are  upon 
metaphysical  ground.  One  singular  deception  of  this  sort, 
which  often  occurs,  is  to  mistake  the  sensation  produced 
by  our  own  unclearness  of  thought  for  a  character  of  the 
object  we  are  thinking.  Instead  of  perceiving  that  the 
obscurity  is  purely  subjective,  we  fancy  that  we  contem- 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  43 

plate  a  quality  of  the  object  which  is  essentially  mysterious; 
and  i£  our  conception  be  afterward  presented  to  us  in  a 
clear  form  we  do  not  recognize  it  as  the  same,  owing  to 
the  absence  of  the  feeling  of  unintelligibility.  So  long  as 
this  deception  lasts,  it  obviously  puts  an  impassable  barrier 
in  the  way  of  perspicuous  thinking;  so  that  it  equally  in 
terests  the  opponents  of  rational  thought  to  perpetuate  it, 
and  its  adherents  to  guard  against  it. 

Another  such  deception  is  to  mistake  a  mere  difference 
in  the  grammatical  construction  of  two  words  for  a  dis 
tinction  between  the  ideas  they  express.  In  this  pedantic 
age,  when  the  general  mob  of  writers  attend  so  much  more 
to  words  than  to  things,  this  error  is  common  enough.  When 
I  just  said  that  thought  is  an  action,  and  that  it  consists 
in  a  relation,  although  a  person  performs  an  action  but  not 
a  relation,  which  can  only  be  the  result  of  an  action,  yet 
there  was  no  inconsistency  in  what  I  said,  but  only  a  gram 
matical  vagueness. 

From  all  these  sophisms  we  shall  be  perfectly  safe  so  long 

as  we  reflect  that  the  whole  function  of  thought  is  to  pro- 

\j  duce  habits  of  action;  and  that  whatever  there  is  connected 

with  a  thought,  but  irrelevant  to  its  purpose,  is  an  accre- 

,-^on  to  it,  but  no  part  of  it.  If  there  be  a  unity  among  our 
sensations  which  has  no  reference  to  how  we  shall  act  on 
a  given  occasion,  as  when  we  listen  to  a  piece  of  music, 
why  we  do  not  call  that  thinking.  To  develop  its  meaning, 
we  have,  therefore,  simply  to  determine  what  habits  it  pro- 

v  duces,  for  what  a  thing  means  is  simply  what  habits  it  in 
volves.  Now,  the  identity  of  a  habit  depends  on  how  it 

\s  i 

might  lead  us  to  act,  not  merely  under  such  circumstances 


44  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

as  are  likely  to  arise,  but  under  such  as  might  possibly 
occur,  no  matter  how  improbable  they  may  be.  •  What  the 
habit  is  depends  on  when  and  how  it  causes  us  to  act.  \  As 
for  the  when,  every  stimulus  to  action  is  derived  from  per 
ception;  as  for  the  how,  every  purpose  of  action  is  to  pro 
duce  some  sensible  result.  Thus,  we  come  down  to  what  is 
tangible  and  practical,  as  the  root  of  every  real  distinction 
of  thought,  no  matter  how  subtile  it  may  be;  and  there  is 
no  distinction  of  meaning  so  fine  as  to  consist  in  anything 
but  a  possible  difference  of  practice/ 

To  see  what  this  principle  leads  to,  consider  in  the  light 
of  it  such  a  doctrine  as  that  of  transubstantiation.  The 
Protestant  churches  generally  hold  that  the  elements  of  the 
sacrament  are  flesh  and  blood  only  in  a  tropical  sense;  they 
nourish  our  souls  as  meat  and  the  juice  of  it  would  our 
bodies.  But  the  Catholics  maintain  that  they  are  literally 
just  that;  although  they  possess  all  the  sensible  qualities  of 
wafer-cakes  and  diluted  wine.  But  we  can  have  no  con 
ception  of  wine  except  what  may  enter  into  a  belief, 
either  — 

1.  That  this,  that,  or  the  other,  is  wine;  or, 

2.  That  wine  possesses  certain  properties. 

Such  beliefs  are  nothing  but  self-notifications  that  we 
should,  upon  occasion,  act  in  regard  to  such  things  as  we 
believe  to  be  wine  according  to  the  qualities  which  we  be 
lieve  wine  to  possess.  The  occasion  of  such  action  would 
be  some  sensible  perception,  the  motive  of  it  to  produce 
some  sensible  result.  Thus  our  action  has  exclusive  refer- 
i  ence  to  what  affects  the  senses,  our  habit  has  the  same  bear 
ing  as  our  action,  our  belief  the  same  as  our  habit,  our 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  45 

conception  the  same  as  our  belief;  and  we  can  consequently 
mean  nothing  by  wine  but  what  has  certain  effects,  direct^ 
or  indirect,  upon  our  senses;  and  to  talk  of  something  as 
having  all  the  sensible  characters  of  wine,  yet  being  in 
reality  blood,  is  senseless  jargon.  Now,  it  is  not  my  object 
to  pursue  the  theological  question;  and  having  used  it  as 
a  logical  example  I  drop  it,  without  caring  to  anticipate 
the  theologian's  reply.  I_pnly  desire  to  point  out  how  im 
possible  it  is  that  we  should  have  an  idea  in  our  minds 
which  relates  to  anything  but  conceived  sensible  effects  of 
things.  Our  idea  of  anything  is  our  idea  of  its  sensible 
effects;  and  if  we  fancy  that  we  have  any  other  we  deceive 
ourselves,  and  mistake  a  mere  sensation  accompanying  the 
thought  for  a  part  of  the  thought  itself.  It  is  absurd  to  say 
that  thought  has  any  meaning  unrelated  to  its  only  func 
tion.  It  is  foolish  for  Catholics  and  Protestants  to  fancy 
themselves  in  disagreement  about  the  elements  of  the  sacra 
ment,  if  they  agree  in  regard  to  all  their  sensible  effects, 
here  or  hereafter. 

It  appears,  then,  that  the  rule  for  attaining  the  third 
grade  of  clearness  of  apprehension  is  as  follows:  Consider 
what  effects,  which  might  conceivably  have  practical  bear 
ings,  we  conceive  the  object  of  our  conception  to  have. 
Then,  our  conception  of  these  effects  is  the  whole  of  our 
conception  of  the  object.  \f 

in 

Let  us  illustrate  this  rule  by  some  examples;  and,  to 
begin  with  the  simplest  one  possible,  let  us  ask  what  we 
mean  by  calling  a  thing  hard.  Evidently  that  it  will  not 


46  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

be  scratched  by  many  other  substances.  The  whole  con 
ception  of  this  quality,  as  of  every  other,  lies  in  its  con 
ceived  effects.  There  is  absolutely  no  difference  between 
a  hard  thing  and  a  soft  thing  so  long  as  they  are  not  brought 
to  the  test.  Suppose,  then,  that  a  diamond  could  be  crys 
tallized  in  the  midst  of  a  cushion  of  soft  cotton,  and  should 
remain  there  until  it  was  finally  burned  up.  Would  it  be 
false  to  say  that  that  diamond  was  soft?  This  seems  a 
foolish  question,  and  would  be  so,  in  fact,  except  in  the 
realm  of  logic.  There  such  questions  are  often  of  the 
greatest  utility  as  serving  to  bring  logical  principles  into 
sharper  relief  than  real  discussions  ever  could.  In  study 
ing  logic  we  must  not  put  them  aside  with  hasty  answers, 
but  must  consider  them  with  attentive  care,  in  order  to 
make  out  the  principles  involved.  We  may,  in  the  present 
case,  modify  our  question,  and  ask  what  prevents  us  from 
saying  that  all  hard  bodies  remain  perfectly  soft  until  they 
are  touched,  when  their  hardness  increases  with  the  pressure 
until  they  are  scratched.  Reflection  will  show  that  the 
reply  is  this:  there  would  be  no  falsity  in  such  modes  of 
speech.  They  would  involve  a  modification  of  our  present 
usage  of  speech  with  regard  to  the  words  hard  and  soft, 
but  not  of  their  meanings.  For  they  represent  no  fact  to 
be  different  from  what  it  is;  only  they  involve  arrange 
ments  of  facts  which  would  be  exceedingly  maladroit.  This 
leads  us  to  remark  that  the  question  of  what  would  occur 
under  circumstances  which  do  not  actually  arise  is  not  a 
question  of  fact,  but  only  of  the  most  perspicuous  arrange 
ment  of  them.  For  example,  the  question  of  free-will  and 
fate  in  its  simplest  form,  stripped  of  verbiage,  is  something 


HOW    TO   MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  47 

like  this:  I  have  done  something  of  which  I  am  ashamed; 
could  I,  by  an  effort  of  the  will,  have  resisted  the  tempta 
tion,  and  done  otherwise?  The  philosophical  reply  is,  that 
this  is  not  a  question  of  fact,  but  only  of  the  arrangement 
of  facts.  Arranging  them  so  as  to  exhibit  what  is  par 
ticularly  pertinent  to  my  question  —  namely,  that  I  ought 
to  blame  myself  for  having  done  wrong  —  it  is  perfectly 
true  to  say  that,  if  I  had  willed  to  do  otherwise  than  I  did, 
I  should  have  done  otherwise.  On  the  other  hand,  arrang 
ing  the  facts  so  as  to  exhibit  another  important  considera 
tion,  it  is  equally  true  that,  when  a  temptation  has  once 
been  allowed  to  work,  it  will,  if  it  has  a  certain  force,  pro 
duce  its  effect,  let  me  struggle  how  I  may.  There  is  no 
objection  to  a  contradiction  in  what  would  result  from  a 
false  supposition.  The  reductio  ad  absurdum  consists  in 
showing  that  contradictory  results  would  follow  from  a 
hypothesis  which  is  consequently  judged  to  be  false.  Many 
questions  are  involved  in  the  free-will  discussion,  and  I  am 
far  from  desiring  to  say  that  both  sides  are  equally  right. 
On  the  contrary,  I  am  of  opinion  that  one  side  denies  im 
portant  facts,  and  that  the  other  does  not.  But  what  I  do 
say  is,  that  the  above  single  question  was  the  origin  of  the 
whole  doubt;  that,  had  it  not  been  for  this  question,  the 
controversy  would  never  have  arisen;  and  that  this  question 
is  perfectly  solved  in  the  manner  which  I  have  indicated. 
Let  us  next  seek  a  clear  idea  of  Weight.  This  is  another 
very  easy  case.  To  say  that  a  body  is  heavy  means  simply 
that,  in  the  absence  of  opposing  force,  it  will  fall.  This 
(neglecting  certain  specifications  of  how  it  will  fall,  etc., 
which  exist  in  the  mind  of  the  physicist  who  uses  the  word) 


48  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

is  evidently  the  whole  conception  of  weight.  It  is  a  fair 
question  whether  some  particular  facts  may  not  account 
for  gravity;  but  what  we  mean  by  the  force  itself  is  com 
pletely  involved  in  its  effects. 

This  leads  us  to  undertake  an  account  of  the  idea  of 
Force  in  general.  This  is  the  great  conception  which, 
developed  in  the  early  part  of  the  seventeenth  century 
from  the  rude  idea  of  a  cause,  and  constantly  improved 
upon  since,  has  shown  us  how  to  explain  all  the  changes 
of  motion  which  bodies  experience,  and  how  to  think  about 
all  physical  phenomena;  which  has  given  birth  to  modern 
science,  and  changed  the  face  of  the  globe;  and  which, 
aside  from  its  more  special  uses,  has  played  a  principal 
part  in  directing  the  course  of  modern  thought,  and  in 
furthering  modern  social  development.  It  is,  therefore, 
worth  some  pains  to  comprehend  it.  According  to  our 
rule,  we  must  begin  by  asking  what  is  the  immediate  use 
of  thinking  about  force;  and  the  answer  is,  that  we  thus 
account  for  changes  of  motion.  If  bodies  were  left  to 
themselves,  without  the  intervention  of  forces,  every 
motion  would  continue  unchanged  both  in  velocity  and  in 
direction.  Furthermore,  change  of  motion  never  takes 
place  abruptly;  if  its  direction  is  changed,  it  is  always 
through  a  curve  without  angles;  if  its  velocity  alters,  it  is 
by  degrees.  The  gradual  changes  which  are  constantly 
taking  place  are  conceived  by  geometers  to  be  compounded 
together  according  to  the  rules  of  the  parallelogram  of 
forces.  If  the  reader  does  not  already  know  what  this  is, 
he  will  find  it,  I  hope,  to  his  advantage  to  endeavor  to 
follow  the  following  explanation;  but  if  mathematics  are 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR 


49 


insupportable  to  him,  pray  let  him  skip  three  paragraphs 
rather  than  that  we  should  part  company  here. 

A  path  is  a  line  whose  beginning  and  end  are  distin 
guished.  Two  paths  are  considered  to  be  equivalent,  which, 
beginning  at  the  same  point,  lead  to  the  same  point.  Thus 
the  two  paths,  ABCDEandAFGHE  (Fig.  3),  are 
equivalent.  Paths  which  do  not  begin  at  the  same  point  are 
considered  to  be  equivalent,  provided  that,  on  moving  either 
of  them  without  turning  it,  but  keeping  it  always  parallel  to 
its  original  position,  [so  that]  when  its  beginning  coincides 
with  that  of  the  other  path,  the  ends  also  coincide.  Paths  are 
considered  as  geometrically  added  together,  when  one  be 
gins  where  the  other  ends ;  thus  the  path  A  E  is  conceived  to 
be  a  sum  of  A  B,  B  C,  C  D,  and  D  E.  In  the  parallelogram 
of  Fig.  4  the  diagonal  A  C  is  the  sum  of  A  B  and  B  C; 
or,  since  A  D  is  geometrically  equivalent  to  B  C,  A  C  is 
the  geometrical  sum  of  A  B  and  A  D. 


~G        H 
CT-  D 

Fig.  3  Fig.  4 

All  this  is  purely  conventional.  It  simply  amounts  to 
this:  that  we  choose  to  call  paths  having  the  relations  I 
have  described  equal  or  added.  But,  though  it  is  a  con 
vention,  it  is  a  convention  with  a  good  reason.  The  rule 
for  geometrical  addition  may  be  applied  not  only  to  paths, 
but  to  any  other  things  which  can  be  represented  by  paths. 
Now,  as  a  path  is  determined  by  the  varying  direction  and 


50  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

distance  of  the  point  which  moves  over  it  from  the  starting- 
point,  it  follows  that  anything  which  from  its  beginning  to 
its  end  is  determined  by  a  varying  direction  and  a  varying 
magnitude  is  capable  of  being  represented  by  a  line. 
Accordingly,  velocities  may  be  represented  by  lines,  for 
they  have  only  directions  and  rates.  The  same  thing  is 
true  of  accelerations,  or  changes  of  velocities.  This  is 
evident  enough  in  the  case  of  velocities;  and  it  becomes 
evident  for  accelerations  if  we  consider  that  precisely  what 
velocities  are  to  positions  —  namely,  states  of  change  of 
them  —  that  accelerations  are  to  velocities. 

The  so-called  "  parallelogram  of  forces "  is  simply  a 
rule  for  compounding  accelerations.  The  rule  is,  to 
represent  the  accelerations  by  paths,  and  then  to  geo 
metrically  add  the  paths.  The  geometers,  however,  not 
only  use  the  "  parallelogram  of  forces  "  to  compound  dif 
ferent  accelerations,  but  also  to  resolve  one  acceleration 
into  a  sum  of  several.  Let  A  B  (Fig.  5)  be  the  path 

which  represents  a  certain 
acceleration  —  say,  such  a 
change  in  the  motion  of  a 
body  that  at  the  end  of 
one  second  the  body  will, 
under  the  influence  of  that 
change,  be  in  a  position 
different  from  what  it 
would  have  had  if  its  motion  had  continued  unchanged,  such 
that  a  path  equivalent  to  A  B  would  lead  from  the  latter 
position  to  the  former.  This  acceleration  may  be  considered 
as  the  sum  of  the  accelerations  represented  by  A  C  and  C  B. 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  51 

It  may  also  be  considered  as  the  sum  of  the  very  different 
accelerations  represented  by  A  D  and  D  B,  where  A  D  is 
almost  the  opposite  of  A  C.  And  it  is  clear  that  there  is 
an  immense  variety  of  ways  in  which  A  B  might  be  resolved 
into  the  sum  of  two  accelerations. 

After  this  tedious  explanation,  which  I  hope,  in  view  of 
the  extraordinary  interest  of  the  conception  of  force,  may 
not  have  exhausted  the  reader's  patience,  we  are  prepared 
at  last  to  state  the  grand  fact  which  this  conception  em 
bodies.  This  fact  is  that  if  the  actual  changes  of  motion 
which  the  different  particles  of  bodies  experience  are  each 
resolved  in  its  appropriate  way,  each  component  accelera 
tion  is  precisely  such  as  is  prescribed  by  a  certain  law  of 
Nature,  according  to  which  bodies  in  the  relative  positions 
which  the  bodies  in  question  actually  have  at  the  moment,2 
always  receive  certain  accelerations,  which,  being  com 
pounded  by  geometrical  addition,  give  the  acceleration 
which  the  body  actually  experiences. 

This  is  the  only  fact  which  the  idea  of  force  represents, 
and  whoever  will  take  the  trouble  clearly  to  apprehend 
what  this  fact  is,  perfectly  comprehends  what  force  is. 
Whether  we  ought  to  say  that  a  force  is  an  acceleration, 
or  that  it  causes  an  acceleration,  is  a  mere  question  of  pro 
priety  of  language,  which  has  no  more  to  do  with  our  real 
meaning  than  the  difference  between  the  French  idiom  "  // 
fait  froid"  and  its  English  equivalent  "It  is  cold.">  Yet 
it  is  surprising  to  see  how  this  simple  affair  has  muddled 
men's  minds.  In  how  many  profound  treatises  is  not  force 
spoken  of  as  a  "  mysterious  entity,"  which  seems  to  be 

2  Possibly  the  velocities  also  have  to  be  taken  into  account. 


52  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

only  a  way  of  confessing  that  the  author  despairs  of  ever 
getting  a  clear  notion  of  what  the  word  means!  In  a  re 
cent  admired  work  on  Analytic  Mechanics  it  is  stated 
that  we  understand  precisely  the  effect  of  force,  but  what 
force  itself  is  we  do  not  understand!  This  is  simply  a  self- 
contradiction.  The  idea  which  the  word  force  excites  in 
our  minds  has  no  other  function  than  to  affect  our  actions, 
and  these  actions  can  have  no  reference  to  force  otherwise 
than  through  its  effects.  Consequently,  if  we  know  what 
the  effects  of  force  are,  we  are  acquainted  with  every  fact 
which  is  implied  in  saying  that  a  force  exists,  and  there  is 
nothing  more  to  know.  The  truth  is,  there  is  some  vague 
notion  afloat  that  a  question  may  mean  something  which  the 
mind  cannot  conceive;  and  when  some  hair-splitting 
philosophers  have  been  confronted  with  the  absurdity  of 
such  a  view,  they  have  invented  an  empty  distinction  be 
tween  positive  and  negative  conceptions,  in  the  attempt  to 
give  their  non-idea  a  form  not  obviously  nonsensical.  The 
nullity  of  it  is  sufficiently  plain  from  the  considerations 
given  a  few  pages  back;  and,  apart  from  those  considera 
tions,  the  quibbling  character  of  the  distinction  must  have 
struck  every  mind  accustomed  to  real  thinking. 


IV 

Let  us  now  approach  the  subject  of  logic,  and  consider 
a  conception  which  particularly  concerns  it,  that  of  reality. 
Taking  clearness  in  the  sense  of  familiarity,  no  idea  could 
be  clearer  than  this.  Every  child  uses  it  with  perfect  con 
fidence,  never  dreaming  that  he  does  not  understand  it. 


HOW   TO   MAKE   OUR   IDEAS   CLEAR  53 

As  for  clearness  in  its  second  grade,  however,  it  would 
probably  puzzle  most  men,  even  among  those  of  a  reflective 
turn  of  mind,  to  give  an  abstract  definition  of  the  real. 
Yet  such  a  definition  may  perhaps  be  reached  by  consider 
ing  the  points  of  difference  between  reality  and  its  opposite, 
fiction.  A  figment  is  a  product  of  somebody's  imagination; 
it  has  such  characters  as  his  thought  impresses  upon  it. 
That  those  characters  are  independent  of  how  you  or  I 
think  is  an  external  reality.  There  are,  however,  phe 
nomena  within  our  own  minds,  dependent  upon  our  thought, 
which  are  at  the  same  time  real  in  the  sense  that  we  really 
think  them.  But  though  their  characters  depend  on  how 
we  think,  they  do  not  depend  on  what  we  think  those  char 
acters  to  be.  Thus,  a  dream  has  a  real  existence  as  a 
mental  phenomenon,  if  somebody  has  really  dreamt  it; 
that  he  dreamt  so  and  so,  does  not  depend  on  what  anybody 
thinks  was  dreamt,  but  is  completely  independent  of  all 
opinion  on  the  subject.  On  the  other  hand,  considering, 
not  the  fact  of  dreaming,  but  the  thing  dreamt,  it  retains 
its  peculiarities  by  virtue  of  no  other  fact  than  that  it  was 
dreamt  to  possess  them.  Thus  we  may  define  the  real  as 
that  whose  characters  are  independent  of  what  anybody 
may  think  them  to  be.j 

But,  however  satisfactory  such  a  definition  may  be  found, 
it  would  be  a  great  mistake  to  suppose  that  it  makes  the 
idea  of  reality  perfectly  clear.  Here,  then,  let  us  apply 
our  rules.  According  to  them,  reality,  like  every  other 
quality,  consists  in  the  peculiar  sensible  effects  which  things 
partaking  of  it  produce.  The  only  effect  which  real  things 
have  is  to  cause  belief,  for  all  the  sensations  which  they 


54.  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

excite  emerge  into  consciousness  in  the  form  of  beliefs. 
The  question,  therefore,  is,  how  is  true  belief  (or  belief  in 
the  real)  distinguished  from  false  belief  (or  belief  in  fic 
tion).  Now,  as  we  have  seen  in  the  former  paper,  the 
ideas  of  truth  and  falsehood,  in  their  full  development, 
appertain  exclusively  to  the  scientific  method  of  settling 
opinion.  A  person  who  arbitrarily  chooses  the  propositions 
which  he  will  adopt  can  use  the  word  truth  only  to  empha 
size  the  expression  of  his  determination  to  hold  on  to  his 
choice.  Of  course,  the  method  of  tenacity  never  prevailed 
exclusively;  reason  is  too  natural  to  men  for  that.  But  in 
the  literature  of  the  dark  ages  we  find  some  fine  examples 
of  it.  When  Scotus  Erigena  is  commenting  upon  a  poetical 
passage  in  which  hellebore  is  spoken  of  as  having  caused 
the  death  of  Socrates,  he  does  not  hesitate  to  inform  the 
inquiring  reader  that  Helleborus  and  Socrates  were  two 
eminent  Greek  philosophers,  and  that  the  latter  having  been 
overcome  in  argument  by  the  former  took  the  matter  to 
heart  and  died  of  it!  What  sort  of  an  idea  of  truth  could 
a  man  have  who  could  adopt  and  teach,  without  the  quali 
fication  of  a  perhaps,  an  opinion  taken  so  entirely  at  ran 
dom?  The  real  spirit  of  Socrates,  who  I  hope  would  have 
been  delighted  to  have  been  "  overcome  in  argument,"  be 
cause  he  would  have  learned  something  by  it,  is  in  curious 
contrast  with  the  naive  idea  of  the  glossist,  for  whom  dis 
cussion  would  seem  to  have  been  simply  a  struggle.  When 
philosophy  began  to  awake  from  its  long  slumber,  and 
before  theology  completely  dominated  it,  the  practice  seems 
to  have  been  for  each  professor  to  seize  upon  any  philoso 
phical  position  he  found  unoccupied  and  which  seemed  a 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  55 

strong  one,  to  intrench  himself  in  it,  and  to  sally  forth  from 
time  to  time  to  give  battle  to  the  others.  Thus,  even  the 
scanty  records  we  possess  of  those  disputes  enable  us  to 
make  out  a  dozen  or  more  opinions  held  by  different  teachers 
at  one  time  concerning  the  question  of  nominalism  and 
realism.  Read  the  opening  part  of  the  Historic,  Calami- 
tatum  of  Abelard,  who  was  certainly  as  philosophical  as 
any  of  his  contemporaries,  and  see  the  spirit  of  combat 
which  it  breathes.  For  him,  the  truth  is  simply  his  par-, 
ticular  stronghold.  When  the  method  of  authority  pre 
vailed,  the  truth  meant  little  more  than  the  Catholic  faith. 
All  the  efforts  of  the  scholastic  doctors  are  directed  toward 
harmonizing  their  faith  in  Aristotle  and  their  faith  in  the 
Church,  and  one  may  search  their  ponderous  folios  through 
without  finding  an  argument  which  goes  any  further.  It  is 
noticeable  that  where  different  faiths  flourish  side  by  side, 
renegades  are  looked  upon  with  contempt  even  by  the  party 
whose  belief  they  adopt;  so  completely  has  the  idea  of  » 
loyalty  replaced  that  of  truth-seeking.  Since  the  time  of 
Descartes,  the  defect  in  the  conception  of  truth  has  been ' 
less  apparent.  Still,  it  will  sometimes  strike  a  scientific 
man  that  the  philosophers  have  been  less  intent  on  finding 
out  what  the  facts  are,  than  on  inquiring  what  belief  is  ' 
most  in  harmony  with  their  system.  It  is  hard  to  convince 
a  follower  of  the  a  priori  method  by  adducing  facts;  but 
show  him  that  an  opinion  he  is  defending  is  inconsistent 
with  what  he  has  laid  down  elsewhere,  and  he  will  be  very 
apt  to  retract  it.  These  minds  do  not  seem  to  believe  that 
disputation  is  ever  to  cease;  they  seem  to  think  that  the 
opinion  which  is  natural  for  one  man  is  not  so  for  another, 


5  6  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

and  that  belief  will,  consequently,  never  be  settled.  In 
contenting  themselves  with  fixing  their  own  opinions  by  a 
method  which  would  lead  another  man  to  a  different  result, 
they  betray  their  feeble  hold  of  the  conception  of  what 
truth  is. 

On  the  other  hand,  all  the  followers  of  science  are  fully 
persuaded  that  the  processes  of  investigation,  if  only  pushed 
far  enough,  will  give  one  certain  solution  to  every  question 
to  which  they  can  be  applied.  One  man  may  investigate 
the  velocity  of  light  by  studying  the  transits  of  Venus  and 
the  aberration  of  the  stars;  another  by  the  oppositions  of 
Mars  and  the  eclipses  of  Jupiter's  satellites ;  a  third  by  the 
method  of  Fizeau;  a  fourth  by  that  of  Foucault;  a  fifth 
by  the  motions  of  the  curves  of  Lissajoux;  a  sixth,  a  seventh, 
an  eighth,  and  a  ninth,  may  follow  the  different  methods 
of  comparing  the  measures  of  statical  and  dynamical  elec 
tricity.  They  may  at  first  obtain  different  results,  but, 
as  each  perfects  his  method  and  his  processes,  the  results 
will  move  steadily  together  toward  a  destined  center.  So* 
with  all  scientific  research.  Different  minds  may  set  out 
with  the  most  antagonistic  views,  but  the  progress  of  in 
vestigation  carries  them  by  a  force  outside  of  themselves 
to  one  and  the  same  conclusion.  This  activity  of  thought 
by  which  we  are  carried,  not  where  we  wish,  but  to  a  fore 
ordained  goal,  is  like  the  operation  of  destiny.  No  modi 
fication  of  the  point  of  view  taken,  no  selection  of  other 
facts  for  study,  no  natural  bent  of  mind  even,  can  enable 
a  man  to  escape  the  predestinate  opinion.  This  great  law 
is  embodied  in  the  conception  of  truth  and  reality.  The 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  57 

opinion  which  is  fated 3  to  be  ultimately  agreed  to  by  all*, 
who  investigate,  is  what  we  mean  by  the  truth,  and  the  ob 
ject  represented  in  this  opinion  is  the  real.    That  is  the  way 
I  would  explain  reality. 

But  it  may  be  said  that  this  view  is  directly  opposed 
to  the  abstract  definition  which  we  have  given  of  reality, 
inasmuch  as  it  makes  the  characters  of  the  real  depend, 
on  what  is  ultimately  thought  about  them.     But  the  answer 
to  this  is  that,  on  the  one  hand,  \reality  is  independent,  not 
necessarily  of  thought  in  general,  but  only  of  what  you  or  * 
I  or  any  finite  number  of  men  may  think  about  it;  and  that, 
on  the  other  hand,  though  the  object  of  the  final  opinion 
depends  on  what  that  opinion  is,  yet  what  that  opinion  is  * 
does  not  depend  on  what  you  or  I  or  any  man  thinks.    Our 
perversity  and  that  of  others  may  indefinitely  postpone  the 
settlement  of  opinion;  it  might  even  conceivably  cause  an 
arbitrary  proposition  to  be  universally  accepted  as  long  as 
the  human  race  should  last.   Yet  even  that  would  not  change  ( 
the  nature  of  the  belief,  which  alone  could  be  the  result  of 
investigation  carried  sufficiently  far;  and  if,  after  the  ex 
tinction  of  our  race,  another  should  arise  with  faculties  and 
disposition  for  investigation,  that  true  opinion  must  be  the  v 
one  which  they  would  ultimately  come  to.    "  Truth  crushed 
to  earth  shall  rise  again,"  and  the  opinion  which  would 
finally  result  from  investigation  does  not  depend  on  how 
anybody  may  actually  think.     But  the  reality  of  that  which 
is  real  does  depend  on  the  real  fact  that  investigation  is 

3  Fate  means  merely  that  which  is  sure  to  come  true,  and  can  nohow 
be  avoided.  It  is  a  superstition  to  suppose  that  a  certain  sort  of  events 
are  ever  fated,  and  it  is  another  to  suppose  that  the  word  fate  can  never 
be  freed  from  its  superstitious  taint.  We  are  all  fated  to  die. 


58  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

destined  to  lead,  at  last,  if  continued  long  enough,  to  a 
belief  in  it. 

But  I  may  be  asked  what  I  have  to  say  to  all  the  minute 
facts  of  history,  forgotten  never  to  be  recovered,  to  the  lost 
books  of  the  ancients,  to  the  buried  secrets. 

"  Full  many  a  gem  of  purest  ray  serene 

The  dark,  unfathomed  caves  of  ocean  bear; 
Full  many  a  flower  is  born  to  blush  unseen, 
And  waste  its  sweetness  on  the  desert  air." 

Do  these  things  not  really  exist  because  they  are  hopelessly 
beyond  the  reach  of  our  knowledge?  And  then,  after  the 
universe  is  dead  (according  to  the  prediction  of  some  scien 
tists),  and  all  life  has  ceased  forever,  will  not  the  shock 
of  atoms  continue  though  there  will  be  no  mind  to  know  it? 
To  this  I  reply  that,  though  in  no  possible  state  of  knowl 
edge  can  any  number  be  great  enough  to  express  the  rela 
tion  between  the  amount  of  what  rests  unknown  to  the 
amount  of  the  known,  yet  it  is  unphilosophical  to  suppose 
that,  with  regard  to  any  given  question  (which  has  any 
clear  meaning),  investigation  would  not  bring  forth  a  solu 
tion  of  it,  if  it  were  carried  far  enough.  Who  would  have 
said,  a  few  years  ago,  that  we  could  ever  know  of  what 
substances  stars  are  made  whose  light  may  have  been  longer 
in  reaching  us  than  the  human  race  has  existed?  Who  can 
be  sure  of  what  we  shall  not  know  in  a  few  hundred  years? 
Who  can  guess  what  would  be  the  result  of  continuing  the 
pursuit  of  science  for  ten  thousand  years,  with  the  activity 
of  the  last  hundred?  And  if  it  were  to  go  on  for  a  million, 
or  a  billion,  or  any  number  of  years  you  please,  how  is  it 


HOW    TO    MAKE    OUR    IDEAS    CLEAR  59 

possible  to  say  that  there  is  any  question  which  might  not 
ultimately  be  solved? 

But  it  may  be  objected,  "  Why  make  so  much  of  these 
remote  considerations,  especially  when  it  is  your  principle 
that  only  practical  distinctions  have  a  meaning?  "  Well, 
I  must  confess  that  it  makes  very  little  difference  whether 
we  say  that  a  stone  on  the  bottom  of  the  ocean,  in  complete 
darkness,  is  brilliant  or  not  —  that  is  to  say,  that  it  probably 
makes  no  difference,  remembering  always  that  that  stone 
may  be  fished  up  to-morrow.  But  that  there  are  gems  at 
the  bottom  of  the  sea,  flowers  in  the  untraveled  desert,  etc., 
are  propositions  which,  like  that  about  a  diamond  being 
hard  when  it  is  not  pressed,  concern  much  more  the  arrange 
ment  of  our  language  than  they  do  the  meaning  of  our  ideas. 

It  seems  to  me,  however,  that  we  have,  by  the  application 
of  our  rule,  reached  so  clear  an  apprehension  of  what  we 
mean  by  reality,  and  of  the  fact  which  the  idea  rests  on, 
that  we  should  not,  perhaps,  be  making  a  pretension  so  pre 
sumptuous  as  it  would  be  singular,  if  we  were  to  offer  a 
metaphysical  theory  of  existence  for  universal  acceptance 
among  those  who  employ  the  scientific  method  of  fixing  be 
lief.  However,  as  metaphysics  is  a  subject  much  more 
curious  than  useful,  the  knowledge  of  which,  like  that  of  a 
sunken  reef,  serves  chiefly  to  enable  us  to  keep  clear  of  it, 
I  will  not  trouble  the  reader  with  any  more  Ontology  at 
this  moment.  I  have  already  been  led  much  further  into 
that  path  than  I  should  have  desired;  and  I  have  given  the 
reader  such  a  dose  of  mathematics,  psychology,  and  all 
that  is  most  abstruse,  that  I  fear  he  may  already  have  left 
me,  and  that  what  I  am  now  writing  is  for  the  compositor 


6o  CHANCE   AND    LOGIC 

and  proofreader  exclusively.  I  trusted  to  the  importance 
of  the  subject.  There  is  no  royal  road  to  logic,  and  really 
valuable  ideas  can  only  be  had  at  the  price  of  close  atten 
tion.  But  I  know  that  in  the  matter  of  ideas  the  public 
prefer  the  cheap  and  nasty;  and  in  my  next  paper  I  am 
going  to  return  to  the  easily  intelligible,  and  not  wander 
from  it  again.  The  reader  who  has  been  at  the  pains  of 
wading  through  this  paper,  shall  be  rewarded  in  the  next 
one  by  seeing  how  beautifully  what  has  been  developed 
in  this  tedious  way  can  be  applied  to  the  ascertainment  of 
the  rules  of  scientific  reasoning. 

We  have,  hitherto,  not  crossed  the  threshold  of  scientific 
logic.  It  is  certainly  important  to  know  how  to  make  our 
ideas  clear,  but  they  may  be  ever  so  clear  without  being 
true.  How  to  make  them  so,  we  have  next  to  study.  How 
to  give  birth  to  those  vital  and  procreative  ideas  which 
multiply  into  a  thousand  forms  and  diffuse  themselves 
everywhere,  advancing  civilization  and  making  the  dignity 
of  man,  is  an  art  not  yet  reduced  to  rules,  but  of  the  secret 
of  which  the  history  of  science  affords  some  hints. 


THIRD    PAPER 
THE   DOCTRINE   OF   CHANCES1 


IT  is  a  common  observation  that  a  science  first  begins  to  be 
exact  when  it  is  quantitatively  treated.  What  are  called 
the  exact  sciences  are  no  others  than  the  mathematical  ones. 
Chemists  reasoned  vaguely  until  Lavoisier  showed  them 
how  to  apply  the  balance  to  the  verification  of  their  theories, 
when  chemistry  leaped  suddenly  into  the  position  of  the 
most  perfect  of  the  classificatory  sciences.  It  has  thus 
become  so  precise  and  certain  that  we  usually  think  of  it 
along  with  optics,  thermotics,  and  electrics.  But  these  are 
studies  of  general  laws,  while  chemistry  considers  merely 
the  relations  and  classification  of  certain  objects;  and  be 
longs,  in  reality,  in  the  same  category  as  systematic  botany 
and  zoology.  Compare  it  with  these  last,  however,  and 
the  advantage  that  it  derives  from  its  quantitative  treatment 
is  very  evident. 

The  rudest  numerical  scales,  such  as  that  by  which  the 
mineralogists  distinguish  the  different  degrees  of  hardness, 
are  found  useful.  The  mere  counting  of  pistils  and  sta 
mens  sufficed  to  bring  botany  out  of  total  chaos  into  some 
kind  of  form.  It  is  not,  however,  so  much  from  counting 
as  from  measuring,  not  so  much  from  the  conception  of 

1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  March,  1878. 

61 


62  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

number  as  from  that  of  continuous  quantity,  that  the  advan 
tage  of  mathematical  treatment  comes.  Number,  after  all, 
only  serves  to  pin  us  down  to  a  precision  in  our  thoughts 
which,  however  beneficial,  can  seldom  lead  to  lofty  concep 
tions,  and  frequently  descends  to  pettiness.  Of  those  two 
faculties  of  which  Bacon  speaks,  that  which  marks  differ 
ences  and  that  which  notes  resemblances,  the  employment  of 
number  can  only  aid  the  lesser  one;  and  the  excessive  use 
of  it  must  tend  to  narrow  the  powers  of  the  mind.  But  the 
conception  of  continuous  quantity  has  a  great  office  to  ful 
fill,  independently  of  any  attempt  at  precision.  Far  from 
tending  to  the  exaggeration  of  differences,  it  is  the  direct 
instrument  of  the  finest  generalizations.  When  a  naturalist 
wishes  to  study  a  species,  he  collects  a  considerable  num 
ber  of  specimens  more  or  less  similar.  In  contemplating 
them,  he  observes  certain  ones  which  are  more  or  less  alike 
in  some  particular  respect.  They  all  have,  for  instance, 
a  certain  S-shaped  marking.  He  observes  that  they  are 
not  precisely  alike,  in  this  respect;  the  S  has  not  precisely 
the  same  shape,  but  the  differences  are  such  as  to  lead  him 
to  believe  that  forms  could  be  found  intermediate  between 
any  two  of  those  he  possesses.  He,  now,  finds  other  forms 
apparently  quite  dissimilar  —  say  a  marking  in  the  form 
of  a  C  —  and  the  question  is,  whether  he  can  find  inter 
mediate  ones  which  will  connect  these  latter  with  the  others. 
This  he  often  succeeds  in  doing  in  cases  where  it  would  at 
first  be  thought  impossible;  whereas,  he  sometimes  finds 
those  which  differ,  at  first  glance,  much  less,  to  be  separated 
in  Nature  by  the  non-occurrence  of  intermediaries.  In 
this  way,  he  builds  up  from  the  study  of  Nature  a  new  gen- 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  63 

cral  conception  of  the  character  in  question.  He  obtains, 
for  example,  an  idea  of  a  leaf  which  includes  every  part 
of  the  flower,  and  an  idea  of  a  vertebra  which  includes  the 
skull.  I  surely  need  not  say  much  to  show  what  a  logical 
engine  there  is  here.  It  is  the  essence  of  the  method  of  the 
naturalist.2  How  he  applies  it  first  to  one  character,  and 
then  to  another,  and  finally  obtains  a  notion  of  a  species 
of  animals,  the  differences  between  whose  members,  however 
great,  are  confined  within  limits,  is  a  matter  which  does  not 
here  concern  us.  The  whole  method  of  classification  must 
be  considered  later;  but,  at  present,  I  only  desire  to  point 
out  that  it  is  by  taking  advantage  of  the  idea  of  continuity, 
or  the  passage  from  one  form  to  another  by  insensible  de 
grees,  that  the  naturalist  builds  his  conceptions.  Now,  the 
naturalists  are  the  great  builders  of  conceptions;  there  is 
no  bther  branch  of  science  where  so  much  of  this  work  is 
done  as  in  theirs;  and  we  must,  in  great  measure,  take  them 
for  our  teachers  in  this  important  part  of  logic.  And  it  will 
be  found  everywhere  that  the  idea  of  continuity  is  a  power 
ful  aid  to  the  formation  of  true  and  fruitful  conceptions. 
By  means  of  it,  the  greatest  differences  are  broken  down 
and  resolved  into  differences  of  degree,  and  the  incessant 
application  of  it  is  of  the  greatest  value  in  broadening  our 
conceptions.  I  propose  to  make  a  great  use  of  this  idea  in 
the  present  series  of  papers;  and  the  particular  series  of 
important  fallacies,  which,  arising  from  a  neglect  of  it,  have 
desolated  philosophy,  must  further  on  be  closely  studied. 


2  [Later,  pp.  170  ff.  and  215  ff.,  it  is  shown  that  continuity  is  also  at 
the  basis  of  mathematical  generalization.  See  also  article  on  Synechism 
in  Baldwin's  Dictionary  of  Philosophy.} 


64  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

At  present,  I  simply  call  the  reader's  attention  to  the  utility 
of  this  conception. 

In  studies  of  numbers,  the  idea  of  continuity  is  so  in 
dispensable,  that  it  is  perpetually  introduced  even  where 
there  is  no  continuity  in  fact,  as  where  we  say  that  there 
are  in  the  United  States  10.7  inhabitants  per  square  mile,  or 
that  in  New  York  14.72  persons  live  in  the  average  house.3 
Another  example  is  that  law  of  the  distribution  of  errors 
which  Quetelet,  Galton,  and  others,  have  applied  with  so 
much  success  to  the  study  of  biological  and  social  matters. 
This  application  of  continuity  to  cases  where  it  does  not 
really  exist  illustrates,  also,  another  point  which  will  here 
after  demand  a  separate  study,  namely,  the  great  utility 
which  fictions  sometimes  have  in  science. 


ii 

The  theory  of  probabilities  is  simply  the  science  of  logic 
quantitatively  treated.  There  are  two  conceivable  cer 
tainties  with  reference  to  any  hypothesis,  the  certainty  of 
its  truth  and  the  certainty  of  its  falsity.  The  numbers  one 
and  zero  are  appropriated,  in  this  calculus,  to  marking  these 
extremes  of  knowledge;  while  fractions  having  values  inter 
mediate  between  them  indicate,  as  we  may  vaguely  say,  the 
degrees  in  which  the  evidence  leans  toward  one  or  the  other. 
The  general  problem  of  probabilities  is,  from  a  given  state 

3  This  mode  of  thought  is  so  familiarly  associated  with  all  exact  nu 
merical  consideration,  that  the  phrase  appropriate  to  it  is  imitated  by 
shallow  writers  in  order  to  produce  the  appearance  of  exactitude  where 
none  exists.  Certain  newspapers  which  affect  a  learned  tone  talk  of  "  the 
average  man,"  when  they  simply  mean  most  men,  and  have  no  idea  of 
striking  an  average. 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF   CHANCES  65 

of  facts,  to  determine  the  numerical  probability  of  a  pos 
sible  fact.  This  is  the  same  as  to  inquire  how  much  the 
given  facts  are  worth,  considered  as  evidence  to  prove  the 
possible  fact.  Thus  the  problem  of  probabilities  is  simply 
the  general  problem  of  logic. 

Probability  is  a  continuous  quantity,  so  that  great  ad 
vantages  may  be  expected  from  this  mode  of  studying  logic. 
Some  writers  have  gone  so  far  as  to  maintain  that,  by  means 
of  the  calculus  of  chances,  every  solid  inference  may  be 
represented  by  legitimate  arithmetical  operations  upon  the 
numbers  given  in  the  premises.  If  this  be,  indeed,  true, 
the  great  problem  of  logic,  how  it  is  that  the  observation 
of  one  fact  can  give  us  knowledge  of  another  independent 
fact,  is  reduced  to  a  mere  question  of  arithmetic.  It  seems 
proper  to  examine  this  pretension  before  undertaking  any 
more  recondite  solution  of  the  paradox. 

But,  unfortunately,  writers  on  probabilities  are  not  agreed 
in  regard  to  this  result.  This  branch  of  mathematics  is  the 
only  one,  I  believe,  in  which  good  writers  frequently  get 
results  entirely  erroneous.  In  elementary  geometry  the 
reasoning  is  frequently  fallacious,  but  erroneous  conclusions 
are  avoided;  but  it  may  be  doubted  if  there  is  a  single  ex 
tensive  treatise  on  probabilities  in  existence  which  does  not 
contain  solutions  absolutely  indefensible.  This  is  partly 
owing  to  the  want  of  any  regular  method  of  procedure;  for 
the  subject  involves  too  many  subtilties  to  make  it  easy  to 
put  its  problems  into  equations  without  such  an  aid.  But, 
beyond  this,  the  fundamental  principles  of  its  calculus  are 
more  or  less  in  dispute.  In  regard  to  that  class  of  questions 
to  which  it  is  chiefly  applied  for  practical  purposes,  there 


66  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

is  comparatively  little  doubt;  but  in  regard  to  others  to 
which  it  has  been  sought  to  extend  it,  opinion  is  somewhat 
unsettled. 

This  last  class  of  difficulties  can  only  be  entirely  over 
come  by  making  the  idea  of  probability  perfectly  clear  in 
our  minds  in  the  way  set  forth  in  our  last  paper. 


in 

To  get  a  clear  idea  of  what  we  mean  by  probability,  we 
have  to  consider  what  real  and  sensible  difference  there  is 
between  one  degree  of  probability  and  another. 

The  character  of  probability  belongs  primarily,  without 
doubt,  to  certain  inferences.  Locke  explains  it  as  follows: 
After  remarking  that  the  mathematician  positively  knows 
that  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  is  equal  to 
two  right  angles  because  he  apprehends  the  geometrical 
proof,  he  thus  continues:  "  But  another  man  who  never  took 
the  pains  to  observe  the  demonstration,  hearing  a  mathe 
matician,  a  man  of  credit,  affirm  the  three  angles  of  a  tri 
angle  to  be  equal  to  two  right  ones,  assents  to  it;  i.e.,  re 
ceives  it  for  true.  In  which  case  the  foundation  of  his  as 
sent  is  the  probability  of  the  thing,  the  proof  being  such  as, 
for  the  most  part,  carries  truth  with  it;  the  man  on  whose 
testimony  he  receives  it  not  being  wont  to  affirm  anything 
contrary  to,  or  besides  his  knowledge,  especially  in  matters 
of  this  kind."  The  celebrated  Essay  concerning  Human 
Understanding  contains  many  passages  which,  like  this 
one,  make  the  first  steps  in  profound  analyses  which  are  not 
further  developed.  It  was  shown  in  the  first  of  these  papers 


THE  DOCTRINE  OF  CHANCES         67 

that  the  validity  of  an  inference  does  not  depend  on  any 
tendency  of  the  mind  to  accept  it,  however  strong  such  ten 
dency  may  be;  but  consists  in  the  real  fact  that,  when 
premises  like  those  of  the  argument  in  question  are  true, 
conclusions  related  to  them  like  that  of  this  argument  are 
also  true.  It  was  remarked  that  in  a  logical  mind  an  argu 
ment  is  always  conceived  as  a  member  of  a  genus  of 
arguments  all  constructed  in  the  same  way,  and  such  that, 
when  their  premises  are  real  facts,  their  conclusions  are  so 
also.  If  the  argument  is  demonstrative,  then  this  is  always 
so;  if  it  is  only  probable,  then  it  is  for  the  most  part  so. 
As  Locke  says,  the  probable  argument  is  "  such  as  for  the 
most  part  carries  truth  with  it." 

According  to  this,  that  real  and  sensible  difference  be 
tween  one  degree  of  probability  and  another,  in  which  the 
meaning  of  the  distinction  lies,  is  that  in  the  frequent  em 
ployment  of  two  different  modes  of  inference,  one  will  carry 
truth  with  it  oftener  than  the  other.  It  is  evident  that  this 
is  the  only  difference  there  is  in  the  existing  fact.  Having 
certain  premises,  a  man  draws  a  certain  conclusion,  and  as 
far  as  this  inference  alone  is  concerned  the  only  possible 
practical  question  is  whether  that  conclusion  is  true  or  not, 
and  between  existence  and  non-existence  there  is  no  middle 
term.  "  Being  only  is  and  nothing  is  altogether  not,"  said 
Parmenides;  and  this  is  in  strict  accordance  with  the  analy 
sis  of  the  conception  of  reality  given  in  the  last  paper.  For 
we  found  that  the  distinction  of  reality  and  fiction  depends 
on  the  supposition  that  sufficient  investigation  would  cause 
one  opinion  to  be  universally  received  and  all  others  to  be 
rejected.  That  presupposition,  involved  in  the  very  con- 


68  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

ceptions  of  reality  and  figment,  involves  a  complete  sunder 
ing  of  the  two.  It  is  the  heaven-and-hell  idea  in  the  do 
main  of  thought.  But,  in  the  long  run,  there  is  a  real  fact 
which  corresponds  to  the  idea  of  probability,  and  it  is  that 
a  given  mode  of  inference  sometimes  proves  successful  and 
sometimes  not,  and  that  in  a  ratio  ultimately  fixed.  As  we 
go  on  drawing  inference  after  inference  of  the  given  kind, 
during  the  first  ten  or  hundred  cases  the  ratio  of  successes 
may  be  expected  to  show  considerable  fluctuations;  but 
when  we  come  into  the  thousands  and  millions,  these  fluc 
tuations  become  less  and  less;  and  if  we  continue  long 
enough,  the  ratio  will  approximate  toward  a  fixed  limit. 
We  may,  therefore,  define  the  probability  of  a  mode  of 
argument  as  the  proportion  of  cases  in  which  it  carries  truth 
with  it. 

The  inference  from  the  premise,  A,  to  the  conclusion,  B, 
depends,  as  we  have  seen,  on  the  guiding  principle,  that  if 
a  fact  of  the  class  A  is  true,  a  fact  of  the  class  B  is  true. 
The  probability  consists  of  the  fraction  whose  numerator 
is  the  number  of  times  in  which  both  A  and  B  are  true, 
and  whose  denominator  is  the  total  number  of  times  in 
which  A  is  true,  whether  B  is  so  or  not.  Instead  of  speak 
ing  of  this  as  the  probability  of  the  inference,  there  is  not 
the  slightest  objection  to  calling  it  the  probability  that,  if 
A  happens,  B  happens.  But  to  speak  of  the  probability 
of  the  event  B,  without  naming  the  condition,  really  has  no 
meaning  at  all.  It  is  true  that  when  it  is  perfectly  obvious 
what  condition  is  meant,  the  ellipsis  may  be  permitted.  But 
we  should  avoid  contracting  the  habit  of  using  language  in 
this  way  (universal  as  the  habit  is),  because  it  gives  rise 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  69 

to  a  vague  way  of  thinking,  as  if  the  action  of  causation 
might  either  determine  an  event  to  happen  or  determine  it 
not  to  happen,  or  leave  it  more  or  less  free  to  happen  or 
not,  so  as  to  give  rise  to  an  inherent  chance  in  regard  to  its 
occurrence.4  It  is  quite  clear  to  me  that  some  of  the  worst 
and  most  persistent  errors  in  the  use  of  the  doctrine  of 
chances  have  arisen  from  this  vicious  mode  of  expression.5 


IV 

But  there  remains  an  important  point  to  be  cleared  up. 
According  to  what  has  been  said,  the  idea  of  probability 
essentially  belongs  to  a  kind  of  inference  which  is  repeated 
indefinitely.  An  individual  inference  must  be  either  true 
or  false,  and  can  show  no  effect  of  probability;  and,  there 
fore,  in  reference  to  a  single  case  considered  in  itself,  prob 
ability  can  have  no  meaning.  Yet  if  a  man  had  to  choose 
between  drawing  a  card  from  a  pack  containing  twenty- 
five  red  cards  and  a  black  one,  or  from  a  pack  containing 
twenty-five  black  cards  and  a  red  one,  and  if  the  drawing 
of  a  red  card  were  destined  to  transport  him  to  eternal 
felicity,  and  that  of  a  black  one  to  consign  him  to  everlasting 
woe,  it  would  be  folly  to  deny  that  he  ought  to  prefer  the 
pack  containing  the  larger  portion  of  red  cards,  although, 
from  the  nature  of  the  risk,  it  could  not  be  repeated.  It  is 
not  easy  to  reconcile  this  with  our  analysis  of  the  conception 

4  Cf.  pp.  179  ff.  below. 

5  The  conception  of  probability  here  set  forth  is  substantially  that  first 
developed  by  Mr.  Venn,  in   his  Logic  of   Chance.    Of   course,   a  vague 
apprehension  of  the  idea  had  always  existed,  but  the  problem  was  to  make 
it  perfectly  clear,  and  to  him  belongs  the  credit  of  first  doing  this. 


70  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

of  chance.  But  suppose  he  should  choose  the  red  pack, 
and  should  draw  the  wrong  card,  what  consolation  would  he 
have?  He  might  say  that  he  had  acted  in  accordance  with 
reason,  but  that  would  only  show  that  his  reason  was  abso 
lutely  worthless.  And  if  he  should  choose  the  right  card, 
how  could  he  regard  it  as  anything  but  a  happy  accident? 
He  could  not  say  that  if  he  had  drawn  from  the  other  pack, 
he  might  have  drawn  the  wrong  one,  because  an  hypotheti 
cal  proposition  such  as,  "  if  A,  then  B,"  means  nothing  with 
reference  to  a  single  case.  Truth  consists  in  the  existence 
of  a  real  fact  corresponding  to  the  true  proposition.  Corre 
sponding  to  the  proposition, "if  A,  then  B,"  there  may  be 
the  fact  that  whenever  such  an  event  as  A  happens  such  an 
event  as  B  happens.  But  in  the  case  supposed,  which  has 
no  parallel  as  far  as  this  man  is  concerned,  there  would  be 
no  real  fact  whose  existence  could  give  any  truth  to  the 
statement  that,  if  he  had  drawn  from  the  other  pack,  he 
might  have  drawn  a  black  card.  Indeed,  since  the  validity 
of  an  inference  consists  in  the  truth  of  the  hypothetical 
proposition  that  */  the  premises  be  true  the  conclusion  will 
also  be  true,  and  since  the  only  real  fact  which  can  corre 
spond  to  such  a  proposition  is  that  whenever  the  antecedent 
is  true  the  consequent  is  so  also,  it  follows  that  there  can 
be  no  sense  in  reasoning  in  an  isolated  case,  at  all. 

These  considerations  appear,  at  first  sight,  to  dispose  of 
the  difficulty  mentioned.  Yet  the  case  of  the  other  side  is 
not  yet  exhausted.  Although  probability  will  probably 
manifest  its  effect  in,  say,  a  thousand  risks,  by  a  certain 
proportion  between  the  numbers  of  successes  and  failures, 
yet  this,  as  we  have  seen,  is  only  to  say  that  it  certainly  will, 


THE   DOCTRINE   OF   CHANCES  71 

at  length,  do  so.  Now  the  number  of  risks,  the  number  of 
probable  inferences,  which  a  man  draws  in  his  whole  life, 
is  a  finite  one,  and  he  cannot  be  absolutely  certain  that  the 
mean  result  will  accord  with  the  probabilities  at  all.  Tak 
ing  all  his  risks  collectively,  then,  it  cannot  be  certain  that 
they  will  not  fail,  and  his  case  does  not  differ,  except  in  de 
gree,  from  the  one  last  supposed.  It  is  an  indubitable  re 
sult  of  the  theory  of  probabilities  that  every  gambler,  if  he 
continues  long  enough,  must  ultimately  be  ruined.  Suppose 
he  tries  the  martingale,  which  some  believe  infallible,  and 
which  is,  as  I  am  informed,  disallowed  in  the  gambling- 
houses.  In  this  method  of  playing,  he  first  bets  say  $i; 
if  he  loses  it  he  bets  $2;  if  he  loses  that  he  bets  $4;  if  he 
loses  that  he  bets  $8;  if  he  then  gains  he  has  lost 
1  +  2+4=7,  and  he  has  gained  $i  more;  and  no  matter 
how  many  bets  he  loses,  the  first  one  he  gains  will  make 
him  $i  richer  than  he  was  in  the  beginning.  In  that  way, 
he  will  probably  gain  at  first;  but,  at  last,  the  time  will 
come  when  the  run  of  luck  is  so  against  him  that  he  will  not 
have  money  enough  to  double,  and  must,  therefore,  let  his 
bet  go.  This  will  probably  happen  before  he  has  won  as 
much  as  he  had  in  the  first  place,  so  that  this  run  against 
him  will  leave  him  poorer  than  he  began;  some  time  or  other 
it  will  be  sure  to  happen.  It  is  true  that  there  is  always  a 
possibility  of  his  winning  any  sum  the  bank  can  pay,  and 
we  thus  come  upon  a  celebrated  paradox  that,  though  he  is 
certain  to  be  ruined,  the  value  of  his  expectation  calculated 
according  to  the  usual  rules  (which  omit  this  consideration) 
is  large.  But,  whether  a  gambler  plays  in  this  way  or  any 
other,  the  same  thing  is  true,  namely,  that  if  he  plays  long 


72  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

enough  he  will  be  sure  some  time  to  have  such  a  run  against 
him  as  to  exhaust  his  entire  fortune.  The  same  thing  is 
true  of  an  insurance  company.  Let  the  directors  take  the 
utmost  pains  to  be  independent  of  great  conflagrations  and 
pestilences,  their  actuaries  can  tell  them  that,  according 
to  the  doctrine  of  chances,  the  time  must  come,  at  last,  when 
their  losses  will  bring  them  to  a  stop.  They  may  tide  over 
such  a  crisis  by  extraordinary  means,  but  then  they  will 
start  again  in  a  weakened  state,  and  the  same  thing  will 
happen  again  all  the  sooner.  An  actuary  might  be  inclined 
to  deny  this,  because  he  knows  that  the  expectation  of  his 
company  is  large,  or  perhaps  (neglecting  the  interest  upon 
money)  is  infinite.  But  calculations  of  expectations  leave 
out  of  account  the  circumstance  now  under  consideration, 
which  reverses  the  whole  thing.  However,  I  must  not  be 
understood  as  saying  that  insurance  is  on  this  account  un 
sound,  more  than  other  kinds  of  business.  All  human  af 
fairs  rest  upon  probabilities,  and  the  same  thing  is  true 
everywhere.  If  man  were  immortal  he  could  be  perfectly 
sure  of  seeing  the  day  when  everything  in  which  he  had 
trusted  should  betray  his  trust,  and,  in  short,  of  coming 
eventually  to  hopeless  misery.  He  would  break  down,  at 
last,  as  every  good  fortune,  as  every  dynasty,  as  every 
civilization  does.  In  place  of  this  we  have  death. 

But  what,  without  death,  would  happen  to  every  man, 
with  death  must  happen  to  some  man.  At  the  same  time, 
death  makes  the  number  of  our  risks,  of  our  inferences, 
finite,  and  so  makes  their  mean  result  uncertain.  The  very 
idea  of  probability  and  of  reasoning  rests  on  the  assumption 
that  this  number  is  indefinitely  great.  We  are  thus  landed 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  73 

in  the  same  difficulty  as  before,  and  I  can  see  but  one  solu 
tion  of  it.  It  seems  to  me  that  we  are  driven  to  this,  that 
logicality  inexorably  requires  that  our  interests  shall  not 
be  limited.  They  must  not  stop  at  our  own  fate,  but  must 
embrace  the  whole  community.  This  community,  again, 
must  not  be  limited,  but  must  extend  to  all  races  of  beings 
with  whom  we  can  come  into  immediate  or  mediate  intel 
lectual  relation.  It  must  reach,  however  vaguely,  beyond 
this  geological  epoch,  beyond  all  bounds.  He  who  would 
not  sacrifice  his  own  soul  to  save  the  whole  world,  is,  as  it 
seems  to  me,  illogical  in  all  his  inferences,  collectively. 
Logic  is  rooted  in  the  social  principle. 

To  be  logical  men  should  not  be  selfish;  and,  in  point  of 
fact,  they  are  not  so  selfish  as  they  are  thought.  The  will 
ful  prosecution  of  one's  desires  is  a  different  thing  from 
selfishness.  The  miser  is  not  selfish;  his  money  does  him 
no  good,  and  he  cares  for  what  shall  become  of  it  after  his 
death.  We  are  constantly  speaking  of  our  possessions  on 
the  Pacific,  and  of  our  destiny  as  a  republic,  where  no  per 
sonal  interests  are  involved,  in  a  way  which  shows  that  we 
have  wider  ones.  We  discuss  with  anxiety  the  possible  ex 
haustion  of  coal  in  some  hundreds  of  years,  or  the  cooling- 
off  of  the  sun  in  some  millions,  and  show  in  the  most  popular 
of  all  religious  tenets  that  we  can  conceive  the  possibility  of 
a  man's  descending  into  hell  for  the  salvation  of  his  fellows. 

Now,  it  is  not  necessary  for  logicality  that  a  man  should 
himself  be  capable  of  the  heroism  of  self-sacrifice.  It  is 
sufficient  that  he  should  recognize  the  possibility  of  it, 
should  perceive  that  only  that  man's  inferences  who  has  it 
are  really  logical,  and  should  consequently  regard  his  own 


74  CHANCE   AND    LOGIC 

as  being  only  so  far  valid  as  they  would  be  accepted  by 
the  hero.  So  far  as  he  thus  refers  his  inferences  to  that 
standard,  he  becomes  identified  with  such  a  mind. 

This  makes  logicality  attainable  enough.  Sometimes  we 
can  personally  attain  to  heroism.  The  soldier  who  runs  to 
scale  a  wall  knows  that  he  will  probably  be  shot,  but  that 
is  not  all  he  cares  for.  He  also  knows  that  if  all  the  regi 
ment,  with  whom  in  feeling  he  identifies  himself,  rush  for 
ward  at  once,  the  fort  will  be  taken.  In  other  cases  we 
can  only  imitate  the  virtue.  The  man  whom  we  have  sup 
posed  as  having  to  draw  from  the  two  packs,  who  if  he  is 
not  a  logician  will  draw  from  the  red  pack  from  mere, 
habit,  will  see,  if  he  is  logician  enough,  that  he  cannot  be 
logical  so  long  as  he  is  concerned  only  with  his  own  fate, 
but  that  that  man  who  should  care  equally  for  what  was 
to  happen  in  all  possible  cases  of  the  sort  could  act  logi 
cally,  and  would  draw  from  the  pack  with  the  most  red 
cards,  and  thus,  though  incapable  himself  of  such  sub 
limity,  our  logician  would  imitate  the  effect  of  that  man's 
courage  in  order  to  share  his  logicality. 

But  all  this  requires  a  conceived  identification  of  one's 
interests  with  those  of  an  unlimited  community.  Now, 
there  exist  no  reasons,  and  a  later  discussion  will  show  that 
there  can  be  no  reasons,  for  thinking  that  the  human  race, 
or  any  intellectual  race,  will  exist  forever.  On  the  other 
hand,  there  can  be  no  reason  against  it;  6  and,  fortunately, 
as  the  whole  requirement  is  that  we  should  have  certain 

6  I  do  not  here  admit  an  absolutely  unknowable.  Evidence  could  show 
us  what  would  probably  be  the  case  after  any  given  lapse  of  time;  and 
though  a  subsequent  time  might  be  assigned  which  that  evidence  might 
not  cover,  yet  further  evidence  would  cover  it. 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  75 

sentiments,  there  is  nothing  in  the  facts  to  forbid  our  having 
a  hope,  or  calm  and  cheerful  wish,  that  the  community  may 
last  beyond  any  assignable  date. 

It  may  seem  strange  that  I  should  put  forward  three 
sentiments,  namely,  interest  in  an  indefinite  community, 
recognition  of  the  possibility  of  this  interest  being  made 
supreme,  and  hope  in  the  unlimited  continuance  of  intellec 
tual  activity,  as  indispensable  requirements  of  logic.  Yet, 
when  we  consider  that  logic  depends  on  a  mere  struggle  to 
escape  doubt,  which,  as  it  terminates  in  action,  must  begin 
in  emotion,  and  that,  furthermore,  the  only  cause  of  our 
planting  ourselves  on  reason  is  that  other  methods  of  escap 
ing  doubt  fail  on  account  of  the  social  impulse,  why  should 
we  wonder  to  find  social  sentiment  presupposed  in 
reasoning?  As  for  the  other  two  sentiments  which  I  find 
necessary,  they  are  so  only  as  supports  and  accessories  of 
that.  It  interests  me  to  notice  that  these  three  sentiments 
seem  to  be  pretty  much  the  same  as  that  famous  trio  of 
Charity,  Faith,  and  Hope,  which,  in  the  estimation  of  St. 
Paul,  are  the  finest  and  greatest  of  spiritual  gifts.  Neither 
Old  nor  New  Testament  is  a  textbook  of  the  logic  of  science, 
but  the  latter  is  certainly  the  highest  existing  authority  in 
regard  to  the  dispositions  of  heart  which  a  man  ought 
to  have. 


Such  average  statistical  numbers  as  the  number  of  in 
habitants  per  square  mile,  the  average  number  of  deaths 
per  week,  trie  number  of  convictions  per  indictment,  or, 
generally  speaking,  the  numbers  of  x's  per  y,  where  the  x's 


76  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

are  a  class  of  things  some  or  all  of  which  are  connected  with 
another  class  of  things,  their  ys,  I  term  relative  numbers. 
Of  the  two  classes  of  things  to  which  a  relative  number 
refers,  that  one  of  which  it  is  a  number  may  be  called  its 
relate,  and  that  one  per  which  the  numeration  is  made  may 
be  called  its  correlate. 

Probability  is  a  kind  of  relative  number;  namely,  it  is 
the  ratio  of  the  number  of  arguments  of  a  certain  genus 
which  carry  truth  with  them  to  the  total  number  of  argu 
ments  of  that  genus,  and  the  rules  for  the  calculation  of 
probabilities  are  very  easily  derived  from  this  considera 
tion.  They  may  all  be  given  here,  since  they  are  extremely 
simple,  and  it  is  sometimes  convenient  to  know  something 
of  the  elementary  rules  of  calculation  of  chances. 

RULE  I.  Direct  Calculation.  —  To  calculate,  directly, 
any  relative  number,  say  for  instance  the  number  of  pas 
sengers  in  the  average  trip  of  a  street-car,  we  must  proceed 
as  follows: 

Count  the  number  of  passengers  for  each  trip;  add  all 
these  numbers,  and  divide  by  the  number  of  trips.  There 
are  cases  in  which  this  rule  may  be  simplified.  Suppose 
we  wish  to  know  the  number  of  inhabitants  to  a  dwelling 
in  New  York.  The  same  person  cannot  inhabit  two  dwell 
ings.  If  he  divide  his  time  between  two  dwellings  he  ought 
to  be  counted  a  half-inhabitant  of  each.  In  this  case  we 
have  only  to  divide  the  total  number  of  the  inhabitants  of 
New  York  by  the  number  of  their  dwellings,  without  the 
necessity  of  counting  separately  those  which  inhabit  each 
one.  A  similar  proceeding  will  apply  wherever  each  in 
dividual  relate  belongs  to  one  individual  correlate  exclu- 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  77 

sively.  If  we  want  the  number  of  jc's  per  y,  and  no  x  be 
longs  to  more  than  one  y,  we  have  only  to  divide  the  whole 
number  of  x's  of  y's  by  the  number  of  y's.  Such  a  method 
would,  of  course,  fail  if  applied  to  finding  the  average  num 
ber  of  street-car  passengers  per  trip.  We  could  not  divide 
the  total  number  of  travelers  by  the  number  of  trips,  since 
many  of  them  would  have  made  many  passages. 

To  find  the  probability  that  from  a  given  class  of  prem 
ises,  A,  a  given  class  of  conclusions,  B,  follow,  it  is  simply 
necessary  to  ascertain  what  proportion  of  the  times  in  which 
premises  of  that  class  are  true,  the  appropriate  conclusions 
are  also  true.  In  other  words,  it  is  the  number  of  cases 
of  the  occurrence  of  both  the  events  A  and  B,  divided  by 
the  total  number  of  cases  of  the  occurrence  of  the  event  A. 

RULE  II.  Addition  of  Relative  Numbers.  —  Given  two 
relative  numbers  having  the  same  correlate,  say  the  num 
ber  of  x's  per  y,  and  the  number  of  z's  per  y;  it  is  required 
to  find  the  number  of  a's  and  z's  together  per  y.  If  there 
is  nothing  which  is  at  once  an  x  and  a  z  to  the  same  y,  the 
sum  of  the  two  given  numbers  would  give  the  required 
number.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  we  had  given  the  aver 
age  number  of  friends  that  men  have,  and  the  average 
number  of  enemies,  the  sum  of  these  two  is  the  average 
number  of  persons  interested  in  a  man.  On  the  other  hand, 
it  plainly  would  not  do  to  add  the  average  number  of 
persons  having  constitutional  diseases  and  over  military 
age,  to  the  average  number  exempted  by  each  special  cause 
from  military  service,  in  order  to  get  the  average  number 
exempt  in  any  way,  since  many  are  exempt  in  two  or  more 
ways  at  once. 


78  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

This  rule  applies  directly  to  probabilities,  given  the 
probability  that  two  different  and  mutually  exclusive  events 
will  happen  under  the  same  supposed  set  of  circumstances. 
Given,  for  instance,  the  probability  that  if  A  then  B,  and 
also  the  probability  that  if  A  then  C,  then  the  sum  of  these 
two  probabilities  is  the  probability  that  if  A  then  either  B 
or  C,  so  long  as  there  is  no  event  which  belongs  at  once  to 
the  two  classes  B  and  C. 

RULE  III.  Multiplication  of  Relative  Numbers.  —  Sup 
pose  that  we  have  given  the  relative  number  of  x's  per  y; 
also  the  relative  number  of  z's  per  x  oi  y;  or,  to  take  a 
concrete  example,  suppose  that  we  have  given,  first,  the 
average  number  of  children  in  families  living  in  New  York; 
and,  second,  the  average  number  of  teeth  in  the  head  of  a 
New  York  child  —  then  the  product  of  these  two  numbers 
would  give  the  average  number  of  children's  teeth  in  a 
New  York  family.  But  this  mode  of  reckoning  will  only 
apply  in  general  under  two  restrictions.  In  the  first  place, 
it  would  not  be  true  if  the  same  child  could  belong  to  dif 
ferent  families,  for  in  that  case  those  children  who  belonged 
to  several  different  families  might  have  an  exceptionally 
large  or  small  number  of  teeth,  which  would  affect  the 
average  number  of  children's  teeth  in  a  family  more  than 
it  would  affect  the  average  number  of  teeth  in  a  child's  head. 
In  the  second  place,  the  rule  would  not  be  true  if  different 
children  could  share  the  same  teeth,  the  average  number 
of  children's  teeth  being  in  that  case  evidently  something 
different  from  the  average  number  of  teeth  belonging  to 
a  child. 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  79 

In  order  to  apply  this  rule  to  probabilities,  we  must  pro 
ceed  as  follows:  Suppose  that  we  have  given  the  proba 
bility  that  the  conclusion  B  follows  from  the  premise  A,  B 
and  A  representing  as  usual  certain  classes  of  propositions. 
Suppose  that  we  also  knew  the  probability  of  an  inference 
in  which  B  should  be  the  premise,  and  a  proposition  of  a 
third  kind,  C,  the  conclusion.  Here,  then,  we  have  the 
materials  for  the  application  of  this  rule.  We  have,  first, 
the  relative  number  of  B's  per  A.  We  next  should  have 
the  relative  number  of  C's  per  B  following  from  A.  But 
the  classes  of  propositions  being  so  selected  that  the  prob 
ability  of  C  following  from  any  B  in  general  is  just  the  same 
as  the  probability  of  C's  following  from  one  of  those  B's 
which  is  deducible  from  an  A,  the  two  probabilities  may 
be  multiplied  together,  in  order  to  give  the  probability  of 
C  following  from  A.  The  same  restrictions  exist  as  before. 
It  might  happen  that  the  probability  that  B  follows  from  A 
was  affected  by  certain  propositions  of  the  class  B  follow 
ing  from  several  different  propositions  of  the  class  A.  But, 
practically  speaking,  all  these  restrictions  are  of  very  little 
consequence,  and  it  is  usually  recognized  as  a  principle 
universally  true  that  the  probability  that,  if  A  is  true,  B  is, 
multiplied  by  the  probability  that,  if  B  is  true,  C  is,  gives 
the  probability  that,  if  A  is  true,  C  is. 

There  is  a  rule  supplementary  to  this,  of  which  great  use 
is  made.  It  is  not  universally  valid,  and  the  greatest  cau 
tion  has  to  be  exercised  in  making  use  of  it  —  a  double  care, 
first,  never  to  use  it  when  it  will  involve  serious  error;  and, 
second,  never  to  fail  to  take  advantage  of  it  in  cases  in 
which  it  can  be  employed.  This  rule  depends  upon  the  fact 


8o  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

that  in  very  many  cases  the  probability  that  C  is  true  if 
B  is,  is  substantially  the  same  as  the  probability  that  C  is 
true  if  A  is.  Suppose,  for  example,  we  have  the  average 
number  of  males  among  the  children  born  in  New  York; 
suppose  that  we  also  have  the  average  number  of  children 
born  in  the  winter  months  among  those  born  in  New  York. 
Now,  we  may  assume  without  doubt,  at  least  as  a  closely 
approximate  proposition  (and  no  very  nice  calculation 
would  be  in  place  in  regard  to  probabilities),  that  the  pro 
portion  of  males  among  all  the  children  born  in  New  York 
is  the  same  as  the  proportion  of  males  born  in  summer  in 
New  York;  and,  therefore,  if  the  names  of  all  the  children 
born  during  a  year  were  put  into  an  urn,  we  might  multiply 
the  probability  that  any  name  drawn  would  be  the  name 
of  a  male  child  by  the  probability  that  it  would  be  the  name 
of  a  child  born  in  summer,  in  order  to  obtain  the  prob 
ability  that  it  would  be  the  name  of  a  male  child  born  in 
summer.  The  questions  of  probability,  in  the  treatises 
upon  the  subject,  have  usually  been  such  as  relate  to  balls 
drawn  from  urns,  and  games  of  cards,  and  so  on,  in  which 
the  question  of  the  independence  of  events,  as  it  is  called  — 
that  is  to  say,  the  question  of  whether  the  probability  of  C, 
under  the  hypothesis  B,  is  the  same  as  its  probability  under 
the  hypothesis  A,  has  been  very  simple;  but,  in  the  appli 
cation  of  probabilities  to  the  ordinary  questions  of  life,  it 
is  often  an  exceedingly  nice  question  whether  two  events 
may  be  considered  as  independent  with  sufficient  accuracy 
or  not.  In  all  calculations  about  cards  it  is  assumed  that 
the  cards  are  thoroughly  shuffled,  which  makes  one  deal 
quite  independent  of  another.  In  point  of  fact  the  cards 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    CHANCES  81 

seldom  are,  in  practice,  shuffled  sufficiently  to  make  this 
true;  thus,  in  a  game  of  whist,  in  which  the  cards  have 
fallen  in  suits  of  four  of  the  same  suit,  and  are  so  gathered 
up,  they  will  lie  more  or  less  in  sets  of  four  of  the  same  suit, 
and  this  will  be  true  even  after  they  are  shuffled.  At  least 
some  traces  of  this  arrangement  will  remain,  in  consequence 
of  which  the  number  of  "  short  suits/'  as  they  are  called 
—  that  is  to  say,  the  number  of  hands  in  which  the  cards 
are  very  unequally  divided  in  regard  to  suits  —  is  smaller 
than  the  calculation  would  make  it  to  be;  so  that,  when 
there  is  a  misdeal,  where  the  cards,  being  thrown  about  the 
table,  get  very  thoroughly  shuffled,  it  is  a  common  saying 
that  in  the  hands  next  dealt  out  there  are  generally  short 
suits.  A  few  years  ago  a  friend  of  mine,  who  plays  whist 
a  great  deal,  was  so  good  as  to  count  the  number  of  spades 
dealt  to  him  in  165  hands,  in  which  the  cards  had  been,  if 
anything,  shuffled  better  than  usual.  According  to  calcula 
tion,  there  should  have  been  85  of  these  hands  in  which  my 
friend  held  either  three  or  four  spades,  but  in  point  of  fact 
there  were  94,  showing  the  influence  of  imperfect  shuffling. 
According  to  the  view  here  taken,  these  are  the  only 
fundamental  rules  for  the  calculation  of  chances.  An  addi 
tional  one,  derived  from  a  different  conception  of  prob 
ability,  is  given  in  some  treatises,  which  if  it  be  sound  might 
be  made  the  basis  of  a  theory  of  reasoning.  Being,  as  I 
believe  it  is,  absolutely  absurd,  the  consideration  of  it  serves 
to  bring  us  to  the  true  theory;  and  it  is  for  the  sake  of  this 
discussion,  which  must  be  postponed  to  the  next  number, 
that  I  have  brought  the  doctrine  of  chances  to  the  reader's 
attention  at  this  early  stage  of  our  studies  of  the  logic  of 
science. 


FOURTH   PAPER 
THE   PROBABILITY   OF   INDUCTION1 


WE  have  found  mat  every  argument  derives  its  force  from 
the  general  truth  of  the  class  of  inferences  to  which  it  be 
longs;  and  that  probability  is  the  proportion  of  arguments 
carrying  truth  with  them  among  those  of  any  genus.  This 
is  most  conveniently  expressed  in  the  nomenclature  of  the 
medieval  logicians.  They  called  the  fact  expressed  by  a 
premise  an  antecedent,  and  that  which  follows  from  it  its 
consequent;  while  the  leading  principle,  that  every  (or 
almost  every)  such  antecedent  is  followed  by  such  a  con 
sequent,  they  termed  the  consequence.  Using  this  lan 
guage,  we  may  say  that  probability  belongs  exclusively  to 
consequences,  and  the  probability  of  any  consequence  is 
the  number  of  times  in  which  antecedent  and  consequent 
both  occur  divided  by  the  number  of  all  the  times  in  which 
the  antecedent  occurs.  From  this  definition  are  deduced 
the  following  rules  for  the  addition  and  multiplication  of 
probabilities : 

Rule  for  the  Addition  of  Probabilities.  —  Given  the  sepa 
rate  probabilities  of  two  consequences  having  the  same  ante 
cedent  and  incompatible  consequents.  Then  the  sum  of 
these  two  numbers  is  the  probability  of  the  consequence, 

1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  April,  1878. 

82 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  83 

that  from  the  same  antecedent  one  or  other  of  those  con 
sequents  follows. 

Rule  for  the  Multiplication  of  Probabilities.  —  Given  the 
separate  probabilities  of  the  two  consequences,  "  If  A  then 
B,"  and  "  If  both  A  and  B,  then  C."  Then  the  product 
of  the  these  two  numbers  is  the  probability  of  the  conse 
quence,  "  If  A,  then  both  B  and  C." 

Special  Rule  for  the  Multiplication  of  Independent  Prob 
abilities.  —  Given  the  separate  probabilities  of  two  conse 
quences  having  the  same  antecedents,  "  If  A,  then  B,"  and 
"  If  A,  then  C."  Suppose  that  these  consequences  are  such 
that  the  probability  of  the  second  is  equal  to  the  probability 
of  the  consequence,  "  If  both  A  and  B,  then  C."  Then  the 
product  of  the  two  given  numbers  is  equal  to  the  probability 
of  the  consequence,  "  If  A,  then  both  B  and  C." 

To  show  the  working  of  these  rules  we  may  examine  the 
probabilities  in  regard  to  throwing  dice.  What  is  the  prob 
ability  of  throwing  a  six  with  one  die?  The  antecedent 
here  is  the  event  of  throwing  a  die;  the  consequent,  its 
turning  up  a  six.  As  the  die  has  six  sides,  all  of  which  are 
turned  up  with  equal  frequency,  the  probability  of  turning 
up  any  one  is  £.  Suppose  two  dice  are  thrown,  what  is 
the  probability  of  throwing  sixes?  The  probability  of  either 
coming  up  six  is  obviously  the  same  when  both  are  thrown 
as  when  one  is  thrown  —  namely,  -£.  The  probability  that 
either  will  come  up  six  when  the  other  does  is  also  the  same 
as  that  of  its  coming  up  six  whether  the  other  does  or  not. 
The  probabilities  are,  therefore,  independent;  and,  by  our 
rule,  the  probability  that  both  events  will  happen  together 
is  the  product  of  their  several  probabilities,  or  £  X  £.  What 


84  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

is  the  probability  of  throwing  deuce-ace?  The  probability 
that  the  first  die  will  turn  up  ace  and  the  second  deuce  is 
the  same  as  the  probability  that  both  will  turn  up  sixes  — 
namely,  ^;  the  probability  that  the  second  will  turn  up 
ace  and  the  first  deuce  is  likewise  ^g-;  these  two  events  — 
first,  ace;  second,  deuce;  and,  second,  ace;  first,  deuce  — 
are  incompatible.  Hence  the  rule  for  addition  holds,  and 
the  probability  that  either  will  come  up  ace  and  the  other 
deuce  is  &  +  ^,  or  ^  . 

In  this  way  all  problems  about  dice,  etc.,  may  be  solved. 
When  the  number  of  dice  thrown  is  supposed  very  large, 
mathematics  (which  may  be  defined  as  the  art  of  making 
groups  to  facilitate  numeration)  comes  to  our  aid  with 
certain  devices  to  reduce  the  difficulties. 


n 

The  conception  of  probability  as  a  matter  of  fact,  i.e.,  as 
the  proportion  of  times  in  which  an  occurrence  of  one  kind 
is  accompanied  by  an  occurrence  of  another  kind,  is  termed 
by  Mr.  Venn  the  materialistic  view  of  the  subject.  But 
probability  has  often  been  regarded  as  being  simply  the 
degree  of  belief  which  ought  to  attach  to  a  proposition,  and 
this  mode  of  explaining  the  idea  is  termed  by  Venn  the 
conceptualistic  view.  Most  writers  have  mixed  the  two 
conceptions  together.  They,  first,  define  the  probability  of 
an  event  as  the  reason  we  have  to  believe  that  it  has  taken 
place,  which  is  conceptualistic;  but  shortly  after  they  state 
that  it  is  the  ratio  of  the  number  of  cases  favorable  to  the 
event  to  the  total  number  of  cases  favorable  or  contrary, 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  85 

and  all  equally  possible.  Except  that  this  introduces  the 
thoroughly  unclear  idea  of  cases  equally  possible  in  place 
of  cases  equally  frequent,  this  is  a  tolerable  statement  of 
the  materialistic  view.  The  pure  conceptualistic  theory  has 
been  best  expounded  by  Mr.  De  Morgan  in  his  Formal 
Logic:  or,  the  Calculus  of  Inference,  Necessary  and 
Probable. 

The  great  difference  between  the  two  analyses  is,  that 
the  conceptualists  refer  probability  to  an  event,  while  the 
materialists  make  it  the  ratio  of  frequency  of  events  of  a 
species  to  those  of  a  genus  over  that  species,  thus  giving  it 
two  terms  instead  of  one.  The  opposition  may  be  made  to 
appear  as  follows: 

Suppose  that  we  have  two  rules  of  inference,  such  that, 
of  all  the  questions  to  the  solution  of  which  both  can  be 
applied,  the  first  yields  correct  answers  to  3%,  and  in 
correct  answers  to  the  remaining  T-&;  while  the  second 
yields  correct  answers  to  -ffa,  and  incorrect  answers  to  the 
remaining  -^.  Suppose,  further,  that  the  two  rules  are 
entirely  independent  as  to  their  truth,  so  that  the  second 
answers  correctly  A3o  of  the  questions  which  the  first  an 
swers  correctly,  and  also  -ffa  of  the  questions  which  the 
first  answers  incorrectly,  and  answers  incorrectly  the  re 
maining  y^-g-  of  the  questions  which  the  first  answers 
correctly,  and  also  the  remaining  TJ0-  of  the  questions  which 
the  first  answers  incorrectly.  Then,  of  all  the  questions  to 
the  solution  of  which  both  rules  can  be  applied  — 


86  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

both  answer  correctly .  .-^  of  —  or   93  X   8l; 

100         100         100  X  100' 

the  second  answers  correctly  and  the  first  incorrectly   —  of  —  or  — — : 

100      100      100  x  100 

the  second  answers  incorrectly  and  the  first  correctly  —  of  —  or  — — ; 

100         100        100  X  100 

and  both  answer  incorrectly  . .  .   —  of  —  or   7   X  *9  : 

100         100         100  X  100 

Suppose,  now,  that,  in  reference  to  any  question,  both 
give  the  same  answer.  Then  (the  questions  being  always 
such  as  are  to  be  answered  by  yes  or  no),  those  in  reference 
to  which  their  answers  agree  are  the  same  as  those  which 
both  answer  correctly  together  with  those  which  both  an 
swer  falsely,  or  93  x  8l  +  7  x  *9  of  all.  The 
ioo  X  100  100  X  100 

proportion  of  those  which  both  answer  correctly  out  of  those 
their  answers  to  which  agree  is,  therefore  — 

93  X8i 

IOQX  ioo  93  X8i 

93  X  81            7  x  19  >f  (93  X  81)  +  (7  X  19). 
ioo  X  ioo      ioo  X  ioo 

This  is,  therefore,  the  probability  that,  if  both  modes  of 
inference  yield  the  same  result,  that  result  is  correct.  We 
may  here  conveniently  make  use  of  another  mode  of  ex 
pression.  Probability  is  the  ratio  of  the  favorable  cases  to 
all  the  cases.  Instead  of  expressing  our  result  in  terms  of 
this  ratio,  we  may  make  use  of  another  —  the  ratio  of 
favorable  to  unfavorable  cases.  This  last  ratio  may  be 
called  the  chance  of  an  event.  Then  the  chance  of  a  true 
answer  by  the  first  mode  of  inference  is  f£  and  by  the 
second  is  ^ ;  and  the  chance  of  a  correct  answer  from  both, 
when  they  agree,  is  — 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  87 

?LX_*L  or  81  x  93 
19  X   7          19         7 

or  the  product  of  the  chances  of  each  singly  yielding  a  true 
answer. 

It  will  be  seen  that  a  chance  is  a  quantity  which  may  have 
any  magnitude,  however  great.  An  event  in  whose  favor 
there  is  an  even  chance,  or  f ,  has  a  probability  of  ^.  An 
argument  having  an  even  chance  can  do  nothing  toward  re- 
enforcing  others,  since  according  to  the  rule  its  combination 
with  another  would  only  multiply  the  chance  of  the  latter 
by  i. 

Probability  and  chance  undoubtedly  belong  primarily  to 
consequences,  and  are  relative  to  premises;  but  we  may, 
nevertheless,  speak  of  the  chance  of  an  event  absolutely, 
meaning  by  that  the  chance  of  the  combination  of  all  argu 
ments  in  reference  to  it  which  exist  for  us  in  the  given  state 
of  our  knowledge.  Taken  in  this  sense  it  is  incontestable 
that  the  chance  of  an  event  has  an  intimate  connection  with 
the  degree  of  our  belief  in  it.  Belief  is  certainly  something 
more  than  a  mere  feeling;  yet  there  is  a  feeling  of  believing, 
and  this  feeling  does  and  ought  to  vary  with  the  chance  of 
the  thing  believed,  as  deduced  from  all  the  arguments. 
Any  quantity  which  varies  with  the  chance  might,  therefore, 
it  would  seem,  serve  as  a  thermometer  for  the  proper  in 
tensity  of  belief.  Among  all  such  quantities  there  is  one 
which  is  peculiarly  appropriate.  When  there  is  a  very  great 
chance,  the  feeling  of  belief  ought  to  be  very  intense.  Ab 
solute  certainty,  or  an  infinite  chance,  can  never  be  attained 
by  mortals,  and  this  may  be  represented  appropriately  by 
an  infinite  belief.  As  the  chance  diminishes  the  feeling  of 


88  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

believing  should  diminish,  until  an  even  chance  is  reached, 
where  it  should  completely  vanish  and  not  incline  either 
toward  or  away  from  the  proposition.  When  the  chance 
becomes  less,  then  a  contrary  belief  should  spring  up  and 
should  increase  in  intensity  as  the  chance  diminishes,  and 
as  the  chance  almost  vanishes  (which  it  can  never  quite  do) 
the  contrary  belief  should  tend  toward  an  infinite  intensity. 
Now,  there  is  one  quantity  which,  more  simply  than  any 
other,  fulfills  these  conditions;  it  is  the  logarithm  of  the 
chance.  But  there  is  another  consideration  which  must, 
if  admitted,  fix  us  to  this  choice  for  our  thermometer.  It 
is  that  our  belief  ought  to  be  proportional  to  the  weight  of 
evidence,  in  this  sense,  that  two  arguments  which  are  en 
tirely  independent,  neither  weakening  nor  strengthening 
each  other,  ought,  when  they  concur,  to  produce  a  belief 
equal  to  the  sum  of  the  intensities  of  belief  which  either 
would  produce  separately.  Now,  we  have  seen  that  the 
chances  of  independent  concurrent  arguments  are  to  be 
multiplied  together  to  get  the  chance  of  their  combination, 
and,  therefore,  the  quantities  which  best  express  the  in 
tensities  of  belief  should  be  such  that  they  are  to  be  added 
when  the  chances  are  multiplied  in  order  to  produce  the 
quantity  which  corresponds  to  the  combined  chance.  Now, 
the  logarithm  is  the  only  quantity  which  fulfills  this  condi 
tion.  There  is  a  general  law  of  sensibility,  called  Fechner's 
psychophysical  law.  It  is  that  the  intensity  of  any  sensa 
tion  is  proportional  to  the  logarithm  of  the  external  force 
which  produces  it.  It  is  entirely  in  harmony  with  this  law 
that  the  feeling  of  belief  should  be  as  the  logarithm  of  the 
chance,  this  latter  being  the  expression  of  the  state  of  facts 
which  produces  the  belief. 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  89 

The  rule  for  the  combination  of  independent  concurrent 
arguments  takes  a  very  simple  form  when  expressed  in 
terms  of  the  intensity  of  belief,  measured  in  the  proposed 
way.  It  is  this:  Take  the  sum  of  all  the  feelings  of  belief 
which  would  be  produced  separately  by  all  the  arguments 
pro,  subtract  from  that  the  similar  sum  for  arguments  con, 
and  the  remainder  is  the  feeling  of  belief  which  we  ought 
to  have  on  the  whole.  This  is  a  proceeding  which  men 
often  resort  to,  under  the  name  of  balancing  reasons. 

These  considerations  constitute  an  argument  in  favor  of 
the  conceptualistic  view.  The  kernel  of  it  is  that  the  con 
joint  probability  of  all  the  arguments  in  our  possession, 
with  reference  to  any  fact,  must  be  intimately  connected 
with  the  just  degree  of  our  belief  in  that  fact;  and  this  point 
is  supplemented  by  various  others  showing  the  consistency 
of  the  theory  with  itself  and  with  the  rest  of  our  knowledge. 

But  probability,  to  have  any  value  at  all,  must  express  a 
fact.  It  is,  therefore,  a  thing  to  be  inferred  upon  evidence. 
Let  us,  then,  consider  for  a  moment  the  formation  of  a  be 
lief  of  probability.  Suppose  we  have  a  large  bag  of  beans 
from  which  one  has  been  secretly  taken  at  random  and 
hidden  under  a  thimble.  We  are  now  to  form  a  probable 
judgment  of  the  color  of  that  bean,  by  drawing  others  singly 
from  the  bag  and  looking  at  them,  each  one  to  be  thrown 
back,  and  the  whole  well  mixed  up  after  each  drawing. 
Suppose  the  first  drawing  is  white  and  the  next  black.  We 
conclude  that  there  is  not  an  immense  preponderance  of 
either  color,  and  that  there  is  something  like  an  even  chance 
that  the  bean  under  the  thimble  is  black.  But  this  judg 
ment  may  be  altered  by  the  next  few  drawings.  When  we 


90  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

have  drawn  ten  times,  if  4,  5,  or  6,  are  white,  we  have  more 
confidence  that  the  chance  is  even.  When  we  have  drawn 
a  thousand  times,  if  about  half  have  been  white,  we  have 
great  confidence  in  this  result.  We  now  feel  pretty  sure 
that,  if  we  were  to  make  a  large  number  of  bets  upon  the 
color  of  single  beans  drawn  from  the  bag,  we  could  approxi 
mately  insure  ourselves  in  the  long  run  by  betting  each  time 
upon  the  white,  a  confidence  which  would  be  entirely  want 
ing  if,  instead  of  sampling  the  bag  by  1,000  drawings,  we 
had  done  so  by  only  two.  Now,  as  the  whole  utility  of 
probability  is  to  insure  us  in  the  long  run,  and  as  that  assur 
ance  depends,  not  merely  on  the  value  of  the  chance,  but 
also  on  the  accuracy  of  the  evaluation,  it  follows  that  we 
ought  not  to  have  the  same  feeling  of  belief  in  reference 
to  all  events  of  which  the  chance  is  even.  In  short,  to  ex 
press  the  proper  state  of  our  belief,  not  one  number  but  two 
are  requisite,  the  first  depending  on  the  inferred  proba 
bility,  the  second  on  the  amount  of  knowledge  on  which 
that  probability  is  based.2  It  is  true  that  when  our  knowl 
edge  is  very  precise,  when  we  have  made  many  drawings 
from  the  bag,  or,  as  in  most  of  the  examples  in  the  books, 
when  the  total  contents  of  the  bag  are  absolutely  known, 
the  number  which  expresses  the  uncertainty  of  the  assumed 
probability  and  its  liability  to  be  changed  by  further  ex 
perience  may  become  insignificant,  or  utterly  vanish.  But, 
when  our  knowledge  is  very  slight,  this  number  may  be  even 
more  important  than  the  probability  itself;  and  when  we 
have  no  knowledge  at  all  this  completely  overwhelms  the 

2  Strictly  we  should  need  an  infinite  series  of  numbers  each  depending 
on  the  probable  error  of  the  last. 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  91 

other,  so  that  there  is  no  sense  in  saying  that  the  chance 
of  the  totally  unknown  event  is  even  (for  what  expresses 
absolutely  no  fact  has  absolutely  no  meaning),  and  what 
ought  to  be  said  is  that  the  chance  is  entirely  indefinite. 
We  thus  perceive  that  the  conceptualistic  view,  though 
answering  well  enough  in  some  cases,  is  quite  inadequate. 

Suppose  that  the  first  bean  which  we  drew  from  our 
bag  were  black.  That  would  constitute  an  argument,  no 
matter  how  slender,  that  the  bean  under  the  thimble  was 
also  black.  If  the  second  bean  were  also  to  turn  out  black, 
that  would  be  a  second  independent  argument  reenforcing 
the  first.  If  the  whole  of  the  first  twenty  beans  drawn 
should  prove  black,  our  confidence  that  the  hidden  bean 
was  black  would  justly  attain  considerable  strength.  But 
suppose  the  twenty-first  bean  were  to  be  white  and  that 
we  were  to  go  on  drawing  until  we  found  that  we  had  drawn 
1,010  black  beans  and  990  white  ones.  We  should  conclude 
that  our  first  twenty  beans  being  black  was  simply  an 
extraordinary  accident,  and  that  in  fact  the  proportion  of 
white  beans  to  black  was  sensibly  equal,  and  that  it  was  an 
even  chance  that  the  hidden  bean  was  black.  Yet  accord 
ing  to  the  rule  of  balancing  reasons,  since  all  the  drawings 
of  black  beans  are  so  many  independent  arguments  in  favor 
of  the  one  under  the  thimble  being  black,  and  all  the  white 
drawings  so  many  against  it,  an  excess  of  twenty  black 
beans  ought  to  produce  the  same  degree  of  belief  that  the 
hidden  bean  was  black,  whatever  the  total  number  drawn. 

In  the  conceptualistic  view  of  probability,  complete  igno 
rance,  where  the  judgment  ought  not  to  swerve  either  toward 
or  away  from  the  hypothesis,  is  represented  by  the  prob 
ability  ^ 

3  "Perfect  indecision,  belief  inclining  neither  way,  an  even  chance."  — 
DE  MORGAN,  p.  182. 


92  CHANCE   AND    LOGIC 

But  let  us  suppose  that  we  are  totally  ignorant  what 
colored  hair  the  inhabitants  of  Saturn  have.  Let  us,  then, 
take  a  color-chart  in  which  all  possible  colors  are  shown 
shading  into  one  another  by  imperceptible  degrees.  In 
such  a  chart  the  relative  areas  occupied  by  different  classes 
of  colors  are  perfectly  arbitrary.  Let  us  inclose  such  an 
area  with  a  closed  line,  and  ask  what  is  the  chance  on  con- 
ceptualistic  principles  that  the  color  of  the  hair  of  the 
inhabitants  of  Saturn  falls  within  that  area?  The  answer 
cannot  be  indeterminate  because  we  must  be  in  some  state 
of  belief;  and,  indeed,  conceptualistic  writers  do  not  admit 
indeterminate  probabilities.  As  there  is  no  certainty  in 
the  matter,  the  answer  lies  between  zero  and  unity.  As  no 
numerical  value  is  afforded  by  the  data,  the  number  must 
be  determined  by  the  nature  of  the  scale  of  probability 
itself,  and  not  by  calculation  from  the  data.  The  answer 
can,  therefore,  only  be  one-half,  since  the  judgment  should 
neither  favor  nor  oppose  the  hypothesis.  What  is  true  of 
this  area  is  true  of  any  other  one;  and  it  will  equally  be 
true  of  a  third  area  which  embraces  the  other  two.  But 
the  probability  for  each  of  the  smaller  areas  being  one-half, 
that  for  the  larger  should  be  at  least  unity,  which  is  absurd. 


in 

All  our  reasonings  are  of  two  kinds:  i.  Explicative,  ana 
lytic,  or  deductive;  2.  Amplifiative,  synthetic,  or  (loosely 
speaking)  inductive.  In  explicative  reasoning,  certain  facts 
are  first  laid  down  in  the  premises.  These  facts  are,  in 
every  case,  an  inexhaustible  multitude,  but  they  may  often 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  93 

be  summed  up  in  one  simple  proposition  by  means  of  some 
regularity  which  runs  through  them  all.  Thus,  take  the 
proposition  that  Socrates  was  a  man;  this  implies  (to  go  no 
further)  that  during  every  fraction  of  a  second  of  his  whole 
life  (or,  if  you  please,  during  the  greater  part  of  them)  he 
was  a  man.  He  did  not  at  one  instant  appear  as  a  tree 
and  at  another  as  a  dog;  he  did  not  flow  into  water,  or  ap 
pear  in  two  places  at  once;  you  could  not  put  your  finger 
through  him  as  if  he  were  an  optical  image,  etc.  Now, 
the  facts  being  thus  laid  down,  some  order  among  some  of 
them,  not  particularly  made  use  of  for  the  purpose  of  stat 
ing  them,  may  perhaps  be  discovered;  and  this  will  enable 
us  to  throw  part  or  all  of  them  into  a  new  statement,  the 
possibility  of  which  might  have  escaped  attention.  Such 
a  statement  will  be  the  conclusion  of  an  analytic  inference. 
Of  this  sort  are  all  mathematical  demonstrations.  But  syn 
thetic  reasoning  is  of  another  kind.  In  this  case  the  facts 
summed  up  in  the  conclusion  are  not  among  those  stated 
in  the  premises.  They  are  different  facts,  as  when  one 
sees  that  the  tide  rises  m  times  and  concludes  that  it  will 
rise  the  next  time.  These  are  the  only  inferences  which 
increase  our  real  knowledge,  however  useful  the  others 
may  be. 

In  any  problem  in  probabilities,  we  have  given  the  rela 
tive  frequency  of  certain  events,  and  we  perceive  that  in 
these  facts  the  relative  frequency  of  another  event  is  given 
in  a  hidden  way.  This  being  stated  makes  the  solution. 
This  is,  therefore,  mere  explicative  reasoning,  and  is  evi 
dently  entirely  inadequate  to  the  representation  of  synthetic 
reasoning,  which  goes  out  beyond  the  facts  given  in  the 


94  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

premises.  There  is,  therefore,  a  manifest  impossibility  in 
so  tracing  out  any  probability  for  a  synthetic  conclusion. 

Most  treatises  on  probability  contain  a  very  different 
doctrine.  They  state,  for  example,  that  if  one  of  the 
ancient  denizens  of  the  shores  of  the  Mediterranean,  who 
had  never  heard  of  tides,  had  gone  to  the  bay  of  Biscay, 
and  had  there  seen  the  tide  rise;  say  m  times,  he  could  know 
that  there  was  a  probability  equal  to 

m  +  i 
m  +  2 

that  it  would  rise  the  next  time.  In  a  well-known  work 
by  Quetelet,  much  stress  is  laid  on  this,  and  it  is  made  the 
foundation  of  a  theory  of  inductive  reasoning. 

But  this  solution  betrays  its  origin  if  we  apply  it  to  the 
case  in  which  the  man  has  never  seen  the  tide  rise  at  all; 
that  is,  if  we  put  m  =  o.  In  this  case,  the  probability  that 
it  will  rise  the  next  time  comes  out  ^,  or,  in  other  words, 
the  solution  involves  the  conceptualistic  principle  that  there 
is  an  even  chance  of  a  totally  unknown  event.  The  manner 
in  which  it  has  been  reached  has  been  by  considering  a 
number  of  urns  all  containing  the  same  number  of  balls, 
part  white  and  part  black.  One  urn  contains  all  white 
balls,  another  one  black  and  the  rest  white,  a  third  two 
black  and  the  rest  white,  and  so  on,  one  urn  for  each  pro 
portion,  until  an  urn  is  reached  containing  only  black  balls. 
But  the  only  possible  reason  for  drawing  any  analogy  be 
tween  such  an  arrangement  and  that  of  Nature  is  the  prin 
ciple  that  alternatives  of  which  we  know  nothing  must  be 
considered  as  equally  probable.  But  this  principle  is  ab 
surd.  There  is  an  indefinite  variety  of  ways  of  enumerat- 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION 


95 


ing  the  different  possibilities,  which,  on  the  application  of 
this  principle,  would  give  different  results.  If  there  be  any 
way  of  enumerating  the  possibilities  so  as  to  make  them 
all  equal,  it  is  not  that  from  which  this  solution  is  derived, 
but  is  the  following:  Suppose  we  had  an  immense  granary 
filled  with  black  and  white  balls  well  mixed  up;  and  sup 
pose  each  urn  were  filled  by  taking  a  fixed  number  of  balls 
from  this  granary  quite  at  random.  The  relative  number 
of  white  balls  in  the  granary  might  be  anything,  say  one  in 
three.  Then  in  one-third  of  the  urns  the  first  ball  would 
be  white,  and  in  two-thirds  black.  In  one-third  of  those 
urns  of  which  the  first  ball  was  white,  and  also  in  one-third 
of  those  in  which  the  first  ball  was  black,  the  second  ball 
would  be  white.  In  this  way,  we  should  have  a  distribu 
tion  like  that  shown  in  the  following  table,  where  w  stands 
for  a  white  ball  and  b  for  a  black  one.  The  reader  can, 
if  he  chooses,  verify  the  table  for  himself. 

wwww. 

wwwb.   wwbw.  wbww.  bwww. 
wwwb.   wwbw.  wbww.  bwww. 


wwbb. 

wbwb. 

bwwb. 

wbbw. 

bwbw. 

bbww. 

wwbb. 

wbwb. 

bwwb. 

wbbw. 

bwbw. 

bbww. 

wwbb. 

wbwb. 

bwwb. 

wbbw. 

bwbw. 

bbww. 

wwbb. 

wbwb. 

bwwb. 

wbbw. 

bwbw. 

bbww. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

, 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

96 

CHANCE 

AND  L< 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

wbbb. 

bwbb. 

bbwb. 

bbbw. 

bbbb.  In  the  second  group,  where  there  is  one  b,  there 
bbbb.  are  two  sets  just  alike;  in  the  third  there  are  4,  in 
bbbb.  the  fourth  8,  and  in  the  fifth  16,  doubling  every 
bbbb.  time.  This  is  because  we  have  supposed  twice  as 
bbbb.  many  black  balls  in  the  granary  as  white  ones;  had 
bbbb.  we  supposed  10  times  as  many,  instead  of 
bbbb. 

bbbb.  i,       2,      4,       8,       16 

bbbb. 

bbbb.    sets  we  should  have  had 
bbbb. 

bbbb.  i,      10,       100,      1000,      10000 

bbbb. 

bbbb.  sets;  on  the  other  hand,  had  the  numbers  of  black 
bbbb.  and  white  balls  in  the  granary  been  even,  there 
bbbb.  would  have  been  but  one  set  in  each  group.  Now 
suppose  two  balls  were  drawn  from  one  of  these  urns  and 
were  found  to  be  both  white,  what  would  be  the  probability 
of  the  next  one  being  white?  If  the  two  drawn  out  were 
the  first  two  put  into  the  urns,  and  the  next  to  be  drawn 
out  were  the  third  put  in,  then  the  probability  of  this  third 
being  white  would  be  the  same  whatever  the  colors  of  the 
first  two,  for  it  has  been  supposed  that  just  the  same  pro 
portion  of  urns  has  the  third  ball  white  among  those  which 
have  the  first  two  white-white,  white-black,  black-white. 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  97 

and  black-black.  Thus,  in  this  case,  the  chance  of  the  third 
ball  being  white  would  be  the  same  whatever  the  first  two 
were.  But,  by  inspecting  the  table,  the  reader  can  see  that 
in  each  group  all  orders  of  the  balls  occur  with  equal  fre 
quency,  so  that  it  makes  no  difference  whether  they  are 
drawn  out  in  the  order  they  were  put  in  or  not.  Hence  the 
colors  of  the  balls  already  drawn  have  no  influence  on  the 
probability  of  any  other  being  white  or  black. 

Now,  if  there  be  any  way  of  enumerating  the  possibilities 
of  Nature  so  as  to  make  them  equally  probable,  it  is  clearly 
one  which  should  make  one  arrangement  or  combination 
of  the  elements  of  Nature  as  probable  as  another,  that  is, 
a  distribution  like  that  we  have  supposed,  and  it,  therefore, 
appears  that  the  assumption  that  any  such  thing  can  be 
done,  leads  simply  to  the  conclusion  that  reasoning  from 
past  to  future  experience  is  absolutely  worthless.  In  fact, 
the  moment  that  you  assume  that  the  chances  in  favor  of 
that  of  which  we  are  totally  ignorant  are  even,  the  problem 
about  the  tides  does  not  differ,  in  any  arithmetical  particu 
lar,  from  the  case  in  which  a  penny  (known  to  be  equally 
likely  to  come  up  heads  and  tails)  should  turn  up  heads 
m  times  successively.  In  short,  it  would  be  to  assume  that 
Nature  is  a  pure  chaos,  or  chance  combination  of  inde 
pendent  elements,  in  which  reasoning  from  one  fact  to  an 
other  would  be  impossible;  and  since,  as  we  shall  hereafter 
see,  there  is  no  judgment  of  pure  observation  without  reason 
ing,  it  would  be  to  suppose  all  human  cognition  illusory 
and  no  real  knowledge  possible.  It  would  be  to  suppose 
that  if  we  have  found  the  order  of  Nature  more  or  less 
regular  in  the  past,  this  has  been  by  a  pure  run  of  luck  which 


98  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

we  may  expect  is  now  at  an  end.  Now,  it  may  be  we  have 
no  scintilla  of  proof  to  the  contrary,  but  reason  is  unneces 
sary  in  reference  to  that  belief  which  is  of  all  the  most 
settled,  which  nobody  doubts  or  can  doubt,  and  which  he 
who  should  deny  would  stultify  himself  in  so  doing. 

The  relative  probability  of  this  or  that  arrangement  of 
Nature  is  something  which  we  should  have  a  right  to  talk 
about  if  universes  were  as  plenty  as  blackberries,  if  we 
could  put  a  quantity  of  them  in  a  bag,  shake  them  well  up, 
draw  out  a  sample,  and  examine  them  to  see  what  propor 
tion  of  them  had  one  arrangement  and  what  proportion 
another.  But,  even  in  that  case,  a  higher  universe  would 
contain  us,  in  regard  to  whose  arrangements  the  conception 
of  probability  could  have  no  applicability. 


IV 

We  have  examined  the  problem  proposed  by  the  con- 
ceptualists,  which,  translated  into  clear  language,  is  this: 
Given  a  synthetic  conclusion;  required  to  know  out  of  all 
possible  states  of  things  how  many  will  accord,  to  any  as 
signed  extent,  with  this  conclusion;  and  we  have  found 
that  it  is  only  an  absurd  attempt  to  reduce  synthetic  to 
analytic  reason,  and  that  no  definite  solution  is  possible. 

But  there  is  another  problem  in  connection  with  this  sub 
ject.  It  is  this:  Given  a  certain  state  of  things,  required 
to  know  what  proportion  of  all  synthetic  inferences  relating 
to  it  will  be  true  within  a  given  degree  of  approximation. 
Now,  there  is  no  difficulty  about  this  problem  (except  for 
its  mathematical  complication);  it  has  been  much  studied, 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  99 

and  the  answer  is  perfectly  well  known.  And  is  not  this, 
after  all,  what  we  want  to  know  much  rather  than  the  other? 
Why  should  we  want  to  know  the  probability  that  the  fact 
will  accord  with  our  conclusion?  That  implies  that  we 
are  interested  in  all  possible  worlds,  and  not  merely  the  one 
in  which  we  find  ourselves  placed.  Why  is  it  not  much 
more  to  the  purpose  to  know  the  probability  that  our  con 
clusion  will  accord  with  the  fact?  One  of  these  questions 
is  the  first  above  stated  and  the  other  the  second,  and  I 
ask  the  reader  whether,  if  people,  instead  of  using  the  word 
probability  without  any  clear  apprehension  of  their  own 
meaning,  had  always  spoken  of  relative  frequency,  they 
could  have  failed  to  see  that  what  they  wanted  was  not  to 
follow  along  the  synthetic  procedure  with  an  analytic  one, 
in  order  to  find  the  probability  of  the  conclusion;  but,  on 
the  contrary,  to  begin  with  the  fact  at  which  the  synthetic 
inference  aims,  and  follow  back  to  the  facts  it  uses  for 
premises  in  order  to  see  the  probability  of  their  being  such 
as  will  yield  the  truth. 

As  we  cannot  have  an  urn  with  an  infinite  number  of 
balls  to  represent  the  inexhaustibleness  of  Nature,  let  us 
suppose  one  with  a  finite  number,  each  ball  being  thrown 
back  into  the  urn  after  being  drawn  out,  so  that  there  is 
no  exhaustion  of  them.  Suppose  one  ball  out  of  three  is 
white  and  the  rest  black,  and  that  four  balls  are  drawn. 
Then  the  table  on  pages  95-96  represents  the  relative  fre 
quency  of  the  different  ways  in  which  these  balls  might 
be  drawn.  It  will  be  seen  that  if  we  should  judge  by  these 
four  balls  of  the  proportion  in  the  urn,  32  times  out  of  81 
we  should  find  it  ^,  and  24  times  out  of  8 1  we  should  find  it 


ioo  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

i,  the  truth  being  $.  To  extend  this  table  to  high  numbers 
would  be  great  labor,  but  the  mathematicians  have  found 
some  ingenious  ways  of  reckoning  what  the  numbers  would 
be.  It  is  found  that,  if  the  true  proportion  of  white  balls 
is  p,  and  5  balls  are  drawn,  then  the  error  of  the  proportion 
obtained  by  the  induction  will  be  — 

half  the  time  within  0.477  \l      

9  times  out  of  10  within  1.163  \/— — 

99  times  out  of  ioo  within  1.821  \l      

999  times  out  of  1,000  within  2.328  V/-^ — 

9,999  times  out  of  10,000  within  2.751  %/— — 

9,999,999,999  times  out  of  10,000,000,000  within  4.77  \l      ~ 

The  use  of  this  may  be  illustrated  by  an  example.  By 
the  census  of  1870,  it  appears  that  the  proportion  of  males 
among  native  white  children  under  one  year  old  was  0.5082, 
while  among  colored  children  of  the  same  age  the  proportion 
was  only  0.4977.  The  difference  between  these  is  0.0105, 
or  about  one  in  a  ioo.  Can  this  be  attributed  to  chance, 
or  would  the  difference  always  exist  among  a  great  number 
of  white  and  colored  children  under  like  circumstances? 
Here  p  may  be  taken  at  i;  hence  2p  (i—p)  is  also  -J.  The 
number  of  white  children  counted  was  near  1,000,000; 
hence  the  fraction  whose  square-root  is  to  be  taken  is  about 

a6oo66Q-  The  root  is  about  r£>v>  and  this  multiplied  by 
0.477  gives  about  0.0003  as  the  probable  error  in  the  ratio 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  101 

'of  males  among  the  whites  as  obtained  from  the  induction. 
The  number  of  black  children  was  about  150,000,  which 
gives  0.0008  for  the  probable  error.  We  see  that  the  actual 
discrepancy  is  ten  times  the  sum  of  these,  and  such  a  result 
would  happen,  according  to  our  table,  only  once  out  of 
10,000,000,000  censuses,  in  the  long  run. 

It  may  be  remarked  that  when  the  real  value  of  the  prob 
ability  sought  inductively  is  either  very  large  or  very  small, 
the  reasoning  is  more  secure.  Thus,  suppose  there  were 
in  reality  one  white  ball  in  100  in  a  certain  urn,  and  we 
were  to  judge  of  the  number  by  100  drawings.  The  prob 
ability  of  drawing  no  white  ball  would  be  •£££$]  that  of 
drawing  one  white  ball  would  be  ^flfr;  that  of  drawing  two 
would  be  ^££5',  that  of  drawing  three  would  be  yf^; 
that  of  drawing  four  would  be  xJ^;  that  of  drawing  five 
would  be  only  T^f  etc.  Thus  we  should  be  tolerably  cer 
tain  of  not  being  in  error  by  more  than  one  ball  in  100. 

It  appears,  then,  that  in  one  sense  we  can,  and  in  another 
we  cannot,  determine  the  probability  of  synthetic  inference. 
When  I  reason  in  this  way: 

Ninety-nine  Cretans  in  a  hundred  are  liars; 

But  Epimenides  is  a  Cretan; 

Therefore,  Epimenides  is  a  liar:  — 

I  know  that  reasoning  similar  to  that  would  carry  truth  99 
times  in  100.  But  when  I  reason  in  the  opposite  direction: 

Minos,  Sarpedon,  Rhadamanthus,  Deucalion,  and  Epi 
menides,  are  all  the  Cretans  I  can  think  of; 

But  these  were  all  atrocious  liars, 

Therefore,  pretty  much  all  Cretans  must  have  been  liars; 
I  do  not  in  the  least  know  how  often  such  reasoning  would 


102  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

carry  me  right.  On  the  other  hand,  what  I  do  know  is 
that  some  definite  proportion  of  Cretans  must  have  been 
liars,  and  that  this  proportion  can  be  probably  approximated 
to  by  an  induction  from  five  or  six  instances.  Even  in  the 
worst  case  for  the  probability  of  such  an  inference,  that 
in  which  about  half  the  Cretans  are  liars,  the  ratio  so  ob 
tained  would  probably  not  be  in  error  by  more  than  £.  So 
much  I  know;  but,  then,  in  the  present  case  the  inference 
is  that  pretty  much  all  Cretans  are  liars,  and  whether  there 
may  not  be  a  special  improbability  in  that  I  do  not  know. 


Late  in  the  last  century,  Immanuel  Kant  asked  the  ques 
tion,  "  How  are  synthetical  judgments  a  priori  possible?  " 
By  synthetical  judgments  he  meant  such  as  assert  positive 
fact  and  are  not  mere  affairs  of  arrangement;  in  short, 
judgments  of  the  kind  which  synthetical  reasoning  produces, 
and  which  analytic  reasoning  cannot  yield.  By  a  priori 
judgments  he  meant  such  as  that  all  outward  objects  are  in 
space,  every  event  has  a  cause,  etc.,  propositions  which 
according  to  him  can  never  be  inferred  from  experience. 
Not  so  much  by  his  answer  to  this  question  as  by  the  mere 
asking  of  it,  the  current  philosophy  of  that  time  was  shat 
tered  and  destroyed,  and  a  new  epoch  in  its  history  was 
begun.  But  before  asking  that  question  he  ought  to  have 
asked  the  more  general  one,  "  How  are  any  synthetical 
judgments  at  all  possible?  "  How  is  it  that  a  man  can  ob 
serve  one  fact  and  straightway  pronounce  judgment  con 
cerning  another  different  fact  not  involved  in  the  first? 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  103 

Such  reasoning,  as  we  have  seen,  has,  at  least  in  the  usual 
sense  of  the  phrase,  no  definite  probability;  how,  then, 
can  it  add  to  our  knowledge?  This  is  a  strange  paradox; 
the  Abbe  Gratry  says  it  is  a  miracle,  and  that  every  true 
induction  is  an  immediate  inspiration  from  on  high.4  I 
respect  this  explanation  far  more  than  many  a  pedantic 
attempt  to  solve  the  question  by  some  juggle  with  proba 
bilities,  with  the  forms  of  syllogism,  or  what  not.  I  re 
spect  it  because  it  shows  an  appreciation  of  the  depth  of 
the  problem,  because  it  assigns  an  adequate  cause,  and  be 
cause  it  is  intimately  connected  —  as  the  true  account 
should  be  —  with  a  general  philosophy  of  the  universe. 
At  the  same  time,  I  do  not  accept  this  explanation,  because 
an  explanation  should  tell  how  a  thing  is  done,  and  to  as 
sert  a  perpetual  miracle  seems  to  be  an  abandonment  of  all 
hope  of  doing  that,  without  sufficient  justification. 

It  will  be  interesting  to  see  how  the  answer  which  Kant 
gave  to  his  question  about  synthetical  judgments  a.  priori 
will  appear  if  extended  to  the  question  of  synthetical  judg 
ments  in  general.  That  answer  is,  that  synthetical  judg 
ments  a  priori  are  possible  because  whatever  is  universally 
true  is  involved  in  the  conditions  of  experience.  Let  us 
apply  this  to  a  general  synthetical  reasoning.  I  take  from 
a  bag  a  handful  of  beans;  they  are  all  purple,  and  I  infer 
that  all  the  beans  in  the  bag  are  purple.  How  can  I  do 
that?  Why,  upon  the  principle  that  whatever  is  univer 
sally  true  of  my  experience  (which  is  here  the  appearance 

4  Logique.  The  same  is  true,  according  to  him,  of  every  performance 
of  a  differentiation,  but  not  of  integration.  He  does  not  tell  us  whether 
it  is  the  supernatural  assistance  which  makes  the  former  process  BO 
much  the  easier. 


104  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

of  these  different  beans)  is  involved  in  the  condition  of 
experience.  The  condition  of  this  special  experience  is 
that  all  these  beans  were  taken  from  that  bag.  According 
to  Kant's  principle,  then,  whatever  is  found  true  of  all  the 
beans  drawn  from  the  bag  must  find  its  explanation  in 
some  peculiarity  of  the  contents  of  the  bag.  This  is  a 
satisfactory  statement  of  the  principle  of  induction. 

When  we  draw  a  deductive  or  analytic  conclusion,  our 
rule  of  inference  is  that  facts  of  a  certain  general  character 
are  either  invariably  or  in  a  certain  proportion  of  cases 
accompanied  by  facts  of  another  general  character.  Then 
our  premise  being  a  fact  of  the  former  class,  we  infer  with 
certainty  or  with  the  appropriate  degree  of  probability 
the  existence  of  a  fact  of  the  second  class.  But  the  rule 
for  synthetic  inference  is  of  a  different  kind.  When  we 
sample  a  bag  of  beans  we  do  not  in  the  least  assume  that 
the  fact  of  some  beans  being  purple  involves  the  necessity 
or  even  the  probability  of  other  beans  being  so.  On  the 
contrary,  the  conceptualistic  method  of  treating  probabili 
ties,  which  really  amounts  simply  to  the  deductive  treat 
ment  of  them,  when  rightly  carried  out  leads  to  the  result 
that  a  synthetic  inference  has  just  an  even  chance  in  its 
favor,  or  in  other  words  is  absolutely  worthless.  The  color 
of  one  bean  is  entirely  independent  of  that  of  another.  But 
synthetic  inference  is  founded  upon  a  classification  of  facts, 
not  according  to  their  characters,  but  according  to  the  man 
ner  of  obtaining  them.  Its  rule  is,  that  a  number  of  facts 
obtained  in  a  given  way  will  in  general  more  or  less  re 
semble  other  facts  obtained  in  the  same  way;  or,  experi 
ences  whose  conditions  are  the  same  will  have  the  same 
general  characters. 


THE    PROBABILITY    OF    INDUCTION  105 

i 
In  the  former  case,  we  know  that  premises  precisely 

similar  in  form  to  those  of  the  given  ones  will  yield  true 
conclusions,  just  once  in  a  calculable  number  of  times.  In 
the  latter  case,  we  only  know  that  premises  obtained  under 
circumstances  similar  to  the  given  ones  (though  perhaps 
themselves  very  different)  will  yield  true  conclusions,  at 
least  once  in  a  calculable  number  of  times.  We  may  ex 
press  this  by  saying  that  in  the  case  of  analytic  inference 
we  know  the  probability  of  our  conclusion  (if  the  premises 
are  true),  but  in  the  case  of  synthetic  inferences  we  only 
know  the  degree  of  trustworthiness  of  our  proceeding.  As 
all  knowledge  comes  from  synthetic  inference,  we  must 
equally  infer  that  all  human  certainty  consists  merely  in 
our  knowing  that  the  processes  by  which  our  knowledge 
has  been  derived  are  such  as  must  generally  have  led  to 
true  conclusions. 

Though  a  synthetic  inference  cannot  by  any  means  be 
reduced  to  deduction,  yet  that  the  rule  of  induction  will 
hold  good  in  the  long  run  may  be  deduced  from  the  principle 
that  reality  is  only  the  object  of  the  final  opinion  to  which 
sufficient  investigation  would  lead.  That  belief  gradually 
tends  to  fix  itself  under  the  influence  of  inquiry  is,  indeed, 
one  of  the  facts  with  which  logic  sets  out- 


FIFTH    PAPER 
THE   ORDER   OF   NATURE1 


ANY  proposition  whatever  concerning  the  order  of  Nature 
must  touch  more  or  less  upon  religion.  In  our  day,  belief, 
even  in  these  matters,  depends  more  and  more  upon  the 
observation  of  facts.  If  a  remarkable  and  universal  order 
liness  be  found  in  the  universe,  there  must  be  some  cause 
for  this  regularity,  and  science  has  to  consider  what  hy 
potheses  might  account  for  the  phenomenon.  One  way  of 
accounting  for  it,  certainly,  would  be  to  suppose  that  the 
world  is  ordered  by  a  superior  power.  But  if  there  is 
nothing  in  the  universal  subjection  of  phenomena  to  laws, 
nor  in  the  character  of  those  laws  themselves  (as  being 
benevolent,  beautiful,  economical,  etc.),  which  goes  to  prove 
the  existence  of  a  governor  of  the  universe,  it  is  hardly  to 
be  anticipated  that  any  other  sort  of  evidence  will  be  found 
to  weigh  very  much  with  minds  emancipated  from  the  tyr 
anny  of  tradition. 

Nevertheless,  it  cannot  truly  be  said  that  even  an  abso 
lutely  negative  decision  of  that  question  could  altogether 
destroy  religion,  inasmuch  as  there  are  faiths  in  which, 
however  much  they  differ  from  our  own,  we  recognize  those 
essential  characters  which  make  them  worthy  to  be  called 
religions,  and  which,  nevertheless,  do  not  postulate  an 

1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  June,  1878. 

106 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  107 

actually  existing  Deity.  That  one,  for  instance,  which  has 
had  the  most  numerous  and  by  no  means  the  least  intelligent 
following  of  any  on  earth,  teaches  that  the  Divinity  in  his 
highest  perfection  is  wrapped  away  from  the  world  in  a 
state  of  profound  and  eternal  sleep,  which  really  does  not 
differ  from  non-existence,  whether  it  be  called  by  that  name 
or  not.  No  candid  mind  who  has  followed  the  writings  of 
M.  Vacherot  can  well  deny  that  his  religion  is  as  earnest 
as  can  be.  He  worships  the  Perfect,  the  Supreme  Ideal; 
but  he  conceives  that  the  very  notion  of  the  Ideal  is  re 
pugnant  to  its  real  existence.2  In  fact,  M.  Vacherot  finds 
it  agreeable  to  his  reason  to  assert  that  non-existence 
is  an  essential  character  of  the  perfect,  just  as  St. 
Anselm  and  Descartes  found  it  agreeable  to  theirs  to  assert 
the  extreme  opposite.  I  confess  that  there  is  one  respect  in 
which  either  of  these  positions  seems  to  me  more  congruous 
with  the  religious  attitude  than  that  of  a  theology  which 
stands  upon  evidences;  for  as  soon  as  the  Deity  presents 
himself  to  either  Anselm  or  Vacherot,  and  manifests  his 
glorious  attributes,  whether  it  be  in  a  vision  of  the  night 
or  day,  either  of  them  recognizes  his  adorable  God,  and 
sinks  upon  his  knees  at  once;  whereas  the  theologian  of 
evidences  will  first  demand  that  the  divine  apparition  shall 
identify  himself,  and  only  after  having  scrutinized  his  cre 
dentials  and  weighed  the  probabilities  of  his  being  found 
among  the  totality  of  existences,  will  he  finally  render  his 
circumspect  homage,  thinking  that  no  characters  can  be 
adorable  but  those  which  belong  to  a  real  thing. 
If  we  could  find  out  any  general  characteristic  of  the 

z  [See  Santayana,  Reason  in  Religion.] 


108  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

universe,  any  mannerism  in  the  ways  of  Nature,  any  law 
everywhere  applicable  and  universally  valid,  such  a  dis 
covery  would  be  of  such  singular  assistance  to  us  in  all  our 
future  reasoning,  that  it  would  deserve  a  place  almost  at 
the  head  of  the  principles  of  logic.  On  the  other  hand, 
if  it  can  be  shown  that  there  is  nothing  of  the  sort  to  find 
out,  but  that  every  discoverable  regularity  is  of  limited 
range,  this  again  will  be  of  logical  importance.  What  sort 
of  a  conception  we  ought  to  have  of  the  universe,  how  to 
think  of  the  ensemble  of  things,  is  a  fundamental  problem 
in  the  theory  of  reasoning. 

ii 

It  is  the  legitimate  endeavor  of  scientific  men  now,  as  it 
was  twenty-three  hundred  years  ago,  to  account  for  the 
formation  of  the  solar  system  and  of  the  cluster  of  stars 
which  forms  the  galaxy,  by  the  fortuitous  concourse  of 
atoms.  The  greatest  expounder  of  this  theory,  when  asked 
how  he  could  write  an  immense  book  on  the  system  of  the 
world  without  one  mention  of  its  author,  replied,  very 
logically,  "  Je  n'avais  pas  besoin  de  cette  hypothese-la." 
But,  in  truth,  there  is  nothing  atheistical  in  the  theory, 
any  more  than  there  was  in  this  answer.  Matter  is  sup 
posed  to  be  composed  of  molecules  which  obey  the  laws  of 
mechanics  and  exert  certain  attractions  upon  one  another; 
and  it  is  to  these  regularities  (which  there  is  no  attempt  to 
account  for)  that  general  arrangement  of  the  solar  system 
would  be  due,  and  not  to  hazard. 

If  any  one  has  ever  maintained  that  the  universe  is  a 
pure  throw  of  the  dice,  the  theologians  have  abundantly 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  109 

refuted  him.  "  How  often/'  says  Archbishop  Tillotson, 
"might  a  man,  after  he  had  jumbled  a  set  of  letters  in  a 
bag,  fling  them  out  upon  the  ground  before  they  would 
fall  into  an  exact  poem,  yea,  or  so  much  as  make  a  good 
discourse  in  prose !  And  may  not  a  little  book  be  as  easily 
made  by  chance  as  this  great  volume  of  the  world?  "  The 
chance  world  here  shown  to  be  so  different  from  that  in 
which  we  live  would  be  one  in  which  there  were  no  laws, 
the  characters  of  different  things  being  entirely  indepen 
dent;  so  that,  should  a  sample  of  any  kind  of  objects  ever 
show  a  prevalent  character,  it  could  only  be  by  accident, 
and  no  general  proposition  could  ever  be  established. 
Whatever  further  conclusions  we  may  come  to  in  regard 
to  the  order  of  the  universe,  thus  much  may  be  regarded 
as  solidly  established,  that  the  world  is  not  a  mere  chance- 
medley. 

But  whether  the  world  makes  an  exact  poem  or  not,  is 
another  question.  When  we  look  up  at  the  heavens  at 
night,  we  readily  perceive  that  the  stars  are  not  simply 
splashed  on  to  the  celestial  vault;  but  there  does  not  seem 
to  be  any  precise  system  in  their  arrangement  either.  It 
will  be  worth  our  while,  then,  to  inquire  into  the  degree  of 
orderliness  in  the  universe;  and,  to  begin,  let  us  ask  whether 
the  world  we  live  in  is  any  more  orderly  than  a  purely 
chance- world  would  be. 

Any  uniformity,  or  law  of  Nature,  may  be  stated  in  the 
form,  "  Every  A  is  B  ";  as,  every  ray  of  light  is  a  non- 
curved  line,  every  body  is  accelerated  toward  the  earth's 
center,  etc.  This  is  the  same  as  to  say,  "  There  does  not 
exist  any  A  which  is  not  B  ";  there  is  no  curved  ray;  there 


no  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

is  no  body  not  accelerated  toward  the  earth;  so  that  the 
uniformity  consists  in  the  non-occurrence  in  Nature  of  a 
certain  combination  of  characters  (in  this  case,  the  com 
bination  of  being  A  with  being  non-B).3  And,  conversely, 
every  case  of  the  non-occurrence  of  a  combination  of  char 
acters  would  constitute  a  uniformity  in  Nature.  Thus,  sup 
pose  the  quality  A  is  never  found  in  combination  with  the 
quality  C:  for  example,  suppose  the  quality  of  idiocy  is 
never  found  in  combination  with  that  of  having  a  well- 
developed  brain.  Then  nothing  of  the  sort  A  is  of  the  sort 
C,  or  everything  of  the  sort  A  is  of  the  sort  non-C  (or  say, 
every  idiot  has  an  ill-developed  brain),  which,  being  some 
thing  universally  true  of  the  A's,  is  a  uniformity  in  the 
world.  Thus  we  see  that,  in  a  world  where  there  were  no 
uniformities,  no  logically  possible  combination  of  characters 
would  be  excluded,  but  every  combination  would  exist  in 
some  object.  But  two  objects  not  identical  must  differ  in 
some  of  their  characters,  though  it  be  only  in  the  character 
of  being  in  such-and-such  a  place.  Hence,  precisely  the 
same  combination  of  characters  could  not  be  found  in  two 
different  objects;  and,  consequently,  in  a  chance-world  every 
combination  involving  either  the  positive  or  negative  of 
every  character  would  belong  to  just  one  thing.  Thus,  if 
there  were  but  five  simple  characters  in  such  a  world,4  we 
might  denote  them  by  A,  B,  C,  D,  E,  and  their  negatives 

3  For  the  present  purpose,  the  negative  of  a  character  is  to  be  con 
sidered  as  much  a  character  as  the  positive,  for  a  uniformity  may  either 
be  affirmative  or  negative.  I  do  not  say  that  no  distinction  can  be  drawn 
between  positive  and  negative  uniformities. 

*  There  being  5  simple  characters,  with  their  negatives,  they  could 
be  compounded  in  various  ways  so  as  to  make  241  characters  in  all,  with 
out  counting  the  characters  existence  and  non-existence,  which  make  up 
243  or  3? 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  in 

by  a,  b,  c,  d,  e;  and  then,  as  there  would  be  2 5  or  32  different 
combinations  of  these  characters,  completely  determinate 
in  reference  to  each  of  them,  that  world  would  have  just  32 
objects  in  it,  their  characters  being  as  in  the  following 
table: 

TABLE  I. 

ABCDE  AbCDE  aBCDE  abCDE 

ABCDe  AbCDe  aBCDe  abCDe 

ABCdE  AbCdE  aBCdE  abCdE 

ABCde  AbCde  aBCde  abCde 

ABcDE  AbcDE  aBcDE  abcDE 

ABcDe  AbcDe  aBcDe  abcDe 

ABcdE  AbcdE  aBcdE  abcdE 

ABcde  Abcde  aBcde  abcde 

For  example,  if  the  five  primary  characters  were  hard, 
sweet,  fragrant,  green,  bright,  there  would  be  one  object 
which  reunited  all  these  qualities,  one  which  was  hard, 
sweet,  fragrant,  and  green,  but  not  bright;  one  which  was 
hard,  sweet,  fragrant,  and  bright,  but  not  green;  one  which 
was  hard,  sweet,  and  fragrant,  but  neither  green  nor  bright; 
and  so  on  through  all  the  combinations. 

This  is  what  a  thoroughly  chance-world  would  be  like, 
and  certainly  nothing  could  be  imagined  more  systematic. 
When  a  quantity  of  letters  are  poured  out  of  a  bag,  the 
appearance  of  disorder  is  due  to  the  circumstance  that  the 
phenomena  are  only  partly  fortuitous.  The  laws  of  space 
are  supposed,  in  that  case,  to  be  rigidly  preserved,  and 
there  is  also  a  certain  amount  of  regularity  in  the  forma 
tion  of  the  letters.  The  result  is  that  some  elements  are 


ii2  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

orderly  and  some  are  disorderly,  which  is  precisely  what 
we  observe  in  the  actual  world.  Tillotson,  in  the  passage 
of  which  a  part  has  been  quoted,  goes  on  to  ask,  "  How  long 
might  20,000  blind  men  which  should  be  sent  out  from 
the  several  remote  parts  of  England,  wander  up  and  down 
before  they  would  all  meet  upon  Salisbury  Plains,  and  fall 
into  rank  and  file  in  the  exact  order  of  an  army?  And  yet 
this  is  much  more  easy  to  be  imagined  than  how  the  in 
numerable  blind  parts  of  matter  should  rendezvous  them 
selves  into  a  world."  This  is  very  true,  but  in  the  actual 
world  the  blind  men  are,  as  far  as  we  can  see,  not  drawn  up 
in  any  particular  order  at  all.  And,  in  short,  while  a  cer 
tain  amount  of  order  exists  in  the  world,  it  would  seem  that 
the  world  is  not  so  orderly  as  it  might  be,  and,  for  instance, 
not  so  much  so  as  a  world  of  pure  chance  would  be. 

But  we  can  never  get  to  the  bottom  of  this  question  until 
we  take  account  of  a  highly-important  logical  principle  5 
which  I  now  proceed  to  enounce.  This  principle  is  that 
any  plurality  or  lot  of  objects  whatever  have  some  character 
in  common  (no  matter  how  insignificant)  which  is  peculiar 
to  them  and  not  shared  by  anything  else.  The  word 
"  character  "  here  is  taken  in  such  a  sense  as  to  include 
negative  characters,  such  as  incivility,  inequality,  etc.,  as 
well  as  their  positives,  civility,  equality,  etc.  To  prove  the 
theorem,  I  will  show  what  character  any  two  things,  A  and 
B,  have  in  common,  not  shared  by  anything  else.  The 
things,  A  and  B,  are  each  distinguished  from  all  other 
things  by  the  possession  of  certain  characters  which  may  be 
named  A-ness  and  B-ness.  Corresponding  to  these  posi- 

5  This  principle  was,  I  believe,  first  stated  by  Mr.  De  Morgan. 


THE    ORDER    OF   NATURE  113 

tive  characters,  are  the  negative  characters  un-A-ness,  which 
is  possessed  by  everything  except  A,  and  un-B-ness,  which 
is  possessed  by  everything  except  B.  These  two  characters 
are  united  in  everything  except  A  and  B;  and  this  union 
of  the  characters  un-A-ness  and  un-B-ness  makes  a  com 
pound  character  which  may  be  termed  A-B-lessness.  This 
is  not  possessed  by  either  A  or  B,  but  it  is  possessed  by 
everything  else.  This  character,  like  every  other,  has  its 
corresponding  negative  un-A-B-lessness,  and  this  last  is  the 
character  possessed  by  both  A  and  B,  and  by  nothing  else. 
It  is  obvious  that  what  has  thus  been  shown  true  of  two 
things  is  mutatis  mutandis,  true  of  any  number  of  things. 
Q.  E.  D. 

In  any  world  whatever,  then,  there  must  be  a  character 
peculiar  to  each  possible  group  of  objects.  If,  as  a  matter 
of  nomenclature,  characters  peculiar  to  the  same  group  be 
regarded  as  only  different  aspects  of  the  same  character, 
then  we  may  say  that  there  will  be  precisely  one  character 
for  each  possible  group  of  objects.  Thus,  suppose  a  world 
to  contain  five  things,  a,  P,  y,  d,  e.  Then  it  will  have  a 
separate  character  for  each  of  the  31  groups  (with  non- 
existence  making  up  32  or  25)  shown  in  the  following  table: 

TABLE  II. 

ap      apy      apyd      apyde 
apye 


y     ae      ay5      ayde 
d     py     aye      Pyde 


ay 

apd 

ad 

ape 

ae 

ayd 

Py 

aye 

pd 

ade 

Pe 

Pyd 

yd 

pye 

ye 

pde 

de 

yde 

U4  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

This  shows  that  a  contradiction  is  involved  in  the  very 
idea6  of  a  chance-world,  for  in  a  world  of  32  things,  in 
stead  of  there  being  only  3°  or  243  characters,  as  we  have 
seen  that  the  notion  of  a  chance-world  requires,  there  would, 
in  fact,  be  no  less  than  232,  or  4,294,967,296  characters, 
which  would  not  be  all  independent,  but  would  have  all 
possible  relations  with  one  another. 

We  further  see  that  so  long  as  we  regard  characters 
abstractly,  without  regard  to  their  relative  importance,  etc., 
there  is  no  possibility  of  a  more  or  less  degree  of  orderli 
ness  in  the  world,  the  whole  system  of  relationship  between 
the  different  characters  being  given  by  mere  logic;  that  is, 
being  implied  in  those  facts  which  are  tacitly  admitted  as 
soon  as  we  admit  that  there  is  any  such  thing  as  reasoning. 

In  order  to  descend  from  this  abstract  point  of  view,  it 
is  requisite  to  consider  the  characters  of  things  as  relative 
to  the  perceptions  and  active  powers  of  living  beings.  In 
stead,  then,  of  attempting  to  imagine  a  world  in  which  there 
should  be  no  uniformities,  let  us  suppose  one  in  which  none 
of  the  uniformities  should  have  reference  to  characters 
interesting  or  important  to  us.  In  the  first  place,  there 
would  be  nothing  to  puzzle  us  in  such  a  world.  The  small 
number  of  qualities  which  would  directly  meet  the  senses 
would  be  the  ones  which  would  afford  the  key  to  every 
thing  which  could  possibly  interest  us.  The  whole  uni 
verse  would  have  such  an  air  of  system  and  perfect  regu 
larity  that  there  would  be  nothing  to  ask.  In  the  next 
place,  no  action  of  ours,  and  no  event  of  Nature,  would  have 
important  consequences  in  such  a  world.  We  should  be 

6  Not  in  every  idea  but  only  in  the  one  so  formulated. 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  115 

perfectly  free  from  all  responsibility,  and  there  would  be 
nothing  to  do  but  to  enjoy  or  suffer  whatever  happened  to 
come  along.  Thus  there  would  be  nothing  to  stimulate  or 
develop  either  the  mind  or  the  will,  and  we  consequently 
should  neither  act  nor  think.  We  should  have  no  memory, 
because  that  depends  on  a  law  of  our  organization.  Even 
if  we  had  any  senses,  we  should  be  situated  toward  such  a 
world  precisely  as  inanimate  objects  are  toward  the  present 
one,  provided  we  suppose  that  these  objects  have  an  abso 
lutely  transitory  and  instantaneous  consciousness  without 
memory  —  a  supposition  which  is  a  mere  mode  of  speech, 
for  that  would  be  no  consciousness  at  all.  We  may,  there 
fore,  say  that  a  world  of  chance  is  simply  our  actual  world 
viewed  from  the  standpoint  of  an  animal  at  the  very  van 
ishing-point  of  intelligence.  The  actual  world  is  almost  a 
chance-medley  to  the  mind  of  a  polyp.  The  interest  which 
the  uniformities  of  Nature  have  for  an  animal  measures 
his  place  in  the  scale  of  intelligence. 

Thus,  nothing  can  be  made  out  from  the  orderliness  of 
Nature  in  regard  to  the  existence  of  a  God,  unless  it  be 
maintained  that  the  existence  of  a  finite  mind  proves  the 
existence  of  an  infinite  one. 

in 

In  the  last  of  these  papers  we  examined  the  nature  of 
inductive  or  synthetic  reasoning.  We  found  it  to  be  a 
process  of  sampling.  A  number  of  specimens  of  a  class 
are  taken,  not  by  selection  within  that  class,  but  at  random. 
These  specimens  will  agree  in  a  great  number  of  respects. 
If,  now,  it  were  likely  that  a  second  lot  would  agree  with 


116  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

the  first  in  the  majority  of  these  respects,  we  might  base 
on  this  consideration  an  inference  in  regard  to  any  one  of 
these  characters.  But  such  an  inference  would  neither  be 
of  the  nature  of  induction,  nor  would  it  (except  in  special 
cases)  be  valid,  because  the  vast  majority  of  points  of 
agreement  in  the  first  sample  drawn  would  generally  be 
entirely  accidental,  as  well  as  insignificant.  To  illustrate 
this,  I  take  the  ages  at  death  of  the  first  five  poets  given  in 
Wheeler's  Biographical  Dictionary.  They  are: 

Aagard,  48. 
Abeille,  70. 
Abulola,  84. 
Abunowas,  48. 
Accords,  45. 

These  five  ages  have  the  following  characters  in  common: 

1.  The  difference  of  the  two  digits  composing  the  num 
ber,  divided  by  three,  leaves  a  remainder  of  one. 

2.  The  first  digit  raised  to  the  power  indicated  by  the 
second,  and  divided  by  three,  leaves  a  remainder  of  one. 

3.  The  sum  of  the  prime  factors  of  each  age,  including 
one,  is  divisible  by  three. 

It  is  easy  to  see  that  the  number  of  accidental  agree 
ments  of  this  sort  would  be  quite  endless.  But  suppose 
that,  instead  of  considering  a  character  because  of  its  prev 
alence  in  the  sample,  we  designate  a  character  before 
taking  the  sample,  selecting  it  for  its  importance,  obvious 
ness,  or  other  point  of  interest.  Then  two  considerable 
samples  drawn  at  random  are  extremely  likely  to  agree 


THE    ORDER    OF   NATURE  117 

approximately  in  regard  to  the  proportion  of  occurrences 
of  a  character  so  chosen.  The  inference  that  a  previously 
designated  character  has  nearly  the  same  frequency  of 
occurrence  in  the  whole  of  a  class  that  it  has  in  a  sample 
drawn  at  random  out  of  that  class  is  induction.  If  the  char 
acter  be  not  previously  designated,  then  a  sample  in  which 
it  is  found  to  be  prevalent  can  only  serve  to  suggest  that 
it  may  be  prevalent  in  the  whole  class.  We  may  consider 
this  surmise  as  an  inference  if  we  please  —  an  inference 
of  possibility;  but  a  second  sample  must  be  drawn  to  test 
the  question  of  whether  the  character  actually  is  prevalent. 
Instead  of  designating  beforehand  a  single  character  in 
reference  to  which  we  will  examine  a  sample,  we  may  desig 
nate  two,  and  use  the  same  sample  to  determine  the  relative 
frequencies  of  both.  This  will  be  making  two  inductive 
inferences  at  once;  and,  of  course,  we  are  less  certain  that 
both  will  yield  correct  conclusions  than  we  should  be  that 
either  separately  would  do  so.  What  is  true  of  two  char 
acters  is  true  of  any  limited  number.  Now,  the  number 
of  characters  which  have  any  considerable  interest  for  us 
in  reference  to  any  class  of  objects  is  more  moderate  than 
might  be  supposed.  As  we  shall  be  sure  to  examine  any 
sample  with  reference  to  these  characters,  they  may  be 
regarded  not  exactly  as  predesignated,  but  as  predeter 
mined  (which  amounts  to  the  same  thing);  and  we  may 
infer  that  the  sample  represents  the  class  in  all  these  re 
spects  if  we  please,  remembering  only  that  this  is  not  so 
secure  an  inference  as  if  the  particular  quality  to  be  looked 
for  had  been  fixed  upon  beforehand. 
The  demonstration  of  this  theory  of  induction  rests  upon 


u8  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 

principles  and  follows  methods  which  are  accepted  by  all 
those  who  display  in  other  matters  the  particular  knowledge 
and  force  of  mind  which  qualify  them  to  judge  of  this.  The 
theory  itself,  however,  quite  unaccountably  seems  never  to 
have  occurred  to  any  of  the  writers  who  have  undertaken 
to  explain  synthetic  reasoning.  The  most  widely-spread 
opinion  in  the  matter  is  one  which  was  much  promoted  by 
Mr.  John  Stuart  Mill  —  namely,  that  induction  depends 
for  its  validity  upon  the  uniformity  of  Nature  —  that  is, 
on  the  principle  that  what  happens  once  will,  under  a  suf 
ficient  degree  of  similarity  of  circumstances,  happen  again 
as  often  as  the  same  circumstances  recur.  The  application 
is  this:  The  fact  that  different  things  belong  to  the  same 
class  constitutes  the  similarity  of  circumstances,  and  the 
induction  is  good,  provided  this  similarity  is  "  sufficient." 
What  happens  once  is,  that  a  number  of  these  things  are 
found  to  have  a  certain  character;  what  may  be  expected, 
then,  to  happen  again  as  often  as  the  circumstances  recur 
consists  in  this,  that  all  things  belonging  to  the  same  class 
should  have  the  same  character. 

This  analysis  of  induction  has,  I  venture  to  think,  va 
rious  imperfections,  to  some  of  which  it  may  be  useful  to 
call  attention.  In  the  first  place,  when  I  put  my  hand  in 
a  bag  and  draw  out  a  handful  of  beans,  and,  finding  three- 
quarters  of  them  black,  infer  that  about  three-quarters  of 
all  in  the  bag  are  black,  my  inference  is  obviously  of  the 
same  kind  as  if  I  had  found  any  larger  proportion,  or  the 
whole,  of  the  sample  black,  and  had  assumed  that  it  rep 
resented  in  that  respect  the  rest  of  the  contents  of  the  bag. 
But  the  analysis  in  question  hardly  seems  adapted  to  the 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  119 

explanation  of  this  proportionate  induction,  where  the  con 
clusion,  instead  of  being  that  a  certain  event  uniformly 
happens  under  certain  circumstances,  is  precisely  that  it 
does  not  uniformly  occur,  but  only  happens  in  a  certain 
proportion  of  cases.  It  is  true  that  the  whole  sample  may 
be  regarded  as  a  single  object,  and  the  inference  may  be 
brought  under  the  formula  proposed  by  considering  the 
conclusion  to  be  that  any  similar  sample  will  show  a  similar 
proportion  among  its  constituents.  But  this  is  to  treat  the 
induction  as  if  it  rested  on  a  single  instance,  which  gives 
a  very  false  idea  of  its  probability. 

In  the  second  place,  if  the  uniformity  of  Nature  were  the 
sole  warrant  of  induction,  we  should  have  no  right  to  draw 
one  in  regard  to  a  character  whose  constancy  we  knew 
nothing  about.  Accordingly,  Mr.  Mill  says  that,  though 
none  but  white  swans  were  known  to  Europeans  for  thou 
sands  of  years,  yet  the  inference  that  all  swans  were  white 
was  "  not  a  good  induction,"  because  it  was  not  known 
that  color  was  a  usual  generic  character  (it,  in  fact,  not 
being  so  by  any  means).  But  it  is  mathematically  demon 
strable  that  an  inductive  inference  may  have  as  high  a  de 
gree  of  probability  as  you  please  independent  of  any  ante 
cedent  knowledge  of  the  constancy  of  the  character  inferred. 
Before  it  was  known  that  color  is  not  usually  a  character 
of  genera,  there  was  certainly  a  considerable  probability 
that  all  swans  were  white.  But  the  further  study  of  the 
genera  of  animals  led  to  the  induction  of  their  non-uni 
formity  in  regard  to  color.  A  deductive  application  of 
this  general  proposition  would  have  gone  far  to  overcome 
the  probability  of  the  universal  whiteness  of  swans  before 


120  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

the  black  species  was  discovered.  When  we  do  know  any 
thing  in  regard  to  the  general  constancy  or  inconstancy  of 
a  character,  the  application  of  that  general  knowledge  to 
the  particular  class  to  which  any  induction  relates,  though 
it  serves  to  increase  or  diminish  the  force  of  the  induction, 
is,  like  every  application  of  general  knowledge  to  particular 
cases,  deductive  in  its  nature  and  not  inductive. 

In  the  third  place,  to  say  that  inductions  are  true  because 
similar  events  happen  in  similar  circumstances  —  or,  what 
is  the  same  thing,  because  objects  similar  in  some  respects 
are  likely  to  be  similar  in  others  —  is  to  overlook  those 
conditions  which  really  are  essential  to  the  validity  of  in 
ductions.  When  we  take  all  the  characters  into  account, 
any  pair  of  objects  resemble  one  another  in  just  as  many 
particulars  as  any  other  pair.  If  we  limit  ourselves  to  such 
characters  as  have  for  us  any  importance,  interest,  or 
obviousness,  then  a  synthetic  conclusion  may  be  drawn, 
but  only  on  condition  that  the  specimens  by  which  we 
judge  have  been  taken  at  random  from  the  class  in  regard 
to  which  we  are  to  form  a  judgment,  and  not  selected  as 
belonging  to  any  sub-class.  The  induction  only  has  its  full 
force  when  the  character  concerned  has  been  designated 
before  examining  the  sample.  These  are  the  essentials  of 
induction,  and  they  are  not  recognized  in  attributing  the 
validity  of  induction  to  the  uniformity  of  Nature.  The 
explanation  of  induction  by  the  doctrine  of  probabilities, 
given  in  the  last  of  these  papers,  is  not  a  mere  metaphysical 
formula,  but  is  one  from  which  all  the  rules  of  synthetic 
reasoning  can  be  deduced  systematically  and  with  mathe 
matical  cogency.  But  the  account  of  the  matter  by  a  prin- 


THE    ORDER    OF   NATURE  121 

ciple  of  Nature,  even  if  it  were  in  other  respects  satisfactory, 
presents  the  fatal  disadvantage  of  leaving  us  quite  as  much 
afloat  as  before  in  regard  to  the  proper  method  of  induc 
tion.  It  does  not  surprise  me,  therefore,  that  those  who 
adopt  this  theory  have  given  erroneous  rules  for  the  con 
duct  of  reasoning,  nor  that  the  greater  number  of  examples 
put  forward  by  Mr.  Mill  in  his  first  edition,  as  models  of 
what  inductions  should  be,  proved  in  the  light  of  further 
scientific  progress  so  particularly  unfortunate  that  they  had 
to  be  replaced  by  others  in  later  editions.  One  would  have 
supposed  that  Mr.  Mill  might  have  based  an  induction  on 
this  circumstance,  especially  as  it  is  his  avowed  principle 
that,  if  the  conclusion  of  an  induction  turns  out  false,  it 
cannot  have  been  a  good  induction.  Nevertheless,  neither 
he  nor  any  of  his  scholars  seem  to  have  been  led  to  suspect, 
in  the  least,  the  perfect  solidity  of  the  framework  which  he 
devised  for  securely  supporting  the  mind  in  its  passage 
from  the  known  to  the  unknown,  although  at  its  first  trial 
it  did  not  answer  quite  so  well  as  had  been  expected. 


IV 

When  we  have  drawn  any  statistical  induction  —  such, 
for  instance,  as  that  one-half  of  all  births  are  of  male  chil 
dren —  it  is  always  possible  to  discover,  by  investigation 
sufficiently  prolonged,  a  class  of  which  the  same  predicate 
may  be  affirmed  universally;  to  find  out,  for  instance,  what 
sort  of  births  are  of  male  children.  The  truth  of  this  prin 
ciple  follows  immediately  from  the  theorem  that  there  is  a 
character  peculiar  to  every  possible  group  of  objects.  The 


122  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

form  in  which  the  principle  is  usually  stated  is,  that  every 
event  must  have  a  cause. 

But,  though  there  exists  a  cause  for  every  event,  and 
that  of  a  kind  which  is  capable  of  being  discovered,  yet  if 
there  be  nothing  to  guide  us  to  the  discovery;  if  we  have 
to  hunt  among  all  the  events  in  the  world  without  any 
scent;  if,  for  instance,  the  sex  of  a  child  might  equally  be 
supposed  to  depend  on  the  configuration  of  the  planets,  on 
what  was  going  on  at  the  antipodes,  or  on  anything  else  — 
then  the  discovery  would  have  no  chance  of  ever  getting 
made. 

That  we  ever  do  discover  the  precise  causes  of  things, 
that  any  induction  whatever  is  absolutely  without  excep 
tion,  is  what  we  have  no  right  to  assume.  On  the  contrary, 
it  is  an  easy  corollary,  from  the  theorem  just  referred  to, 
that  every  empirical  rule  has  an  exception.7  But  there  are 
certain  of  our  inductions  which  present  an  approach  to 
universality  so  extraordinary  that,  even  if  we  are  to  sup 
pose  that  they  are  not  strictly  universal  truths,  we  cannot 
possibly  think  that  they  have  been  reached  merely  by 
accident.  The  most  remarkable  laws  of  this  kind  are  those 
of  time  and  space.  With  reference  to  space,  Bishop 
Berkeley  first  showed,  in  a  very  conclusive  manner,  that 
it  was  not  a  thing  seen,  but  a  thing  inferred.  Berkeley 
chiefly  insists  on  the  impossibility  of  directly  seeing  the 
third  dimension  of  space,  since  the  retina  of  the  eye  is  a 
surface.  But,  in  point  of  fact,  the  retina  is  not  even  a 
surface;  it  is  a  conglomeration  of  nerve-needles  directed 

7  [Note  that  this  corollary  is  itself  a  theoretical  inference  and  not  an 
empirical  rule.] 


THE    ORDER    OF   NATURE  123 

toward  the  light  and  having  only  their  extreme  points  sen- 
sitive,  these  points  lying  at  considerable  distances  from  one 
another  compared  with  their  areas.  Now,  of  these  points, 
certainly  the  excitation  of  no  one  singly  can  produce  the 
perception  of  a  surface,  and  consequently  not  the  aggregate 
of  all  the  sensations  can  amount  to  this.  But  certain  rela 
tions  subsist  between  the  excitations  of  different  nerve- 
points,  and  these  constitute  the  premises  upon  which  the 
hypothesis  of  space  is  founded,  and  from  which  it  is  in 
ferred.  That  space  is  not  immediately  perceived  is  now 
universally  admitted;  and  a  mediate  cognition  is  what  is 
called  an  inference,  and  is  subject  to  the  criticism  of  logic. 
But  what  are  we  to  say  to  the  fact  of  every  chicken  as  soon 
as  it  is  hatched  solving  a  problem  whose  data  are  of  a  com 
plexity  sufficient  to  try  the  greatest  mathematical  powers? 
It  would  be  insane  to  deny  that  the  tendency  to  light  upon 
the  conception  of  space  is  inborn  in  the  mind  of  the  chicken 
and  of  every  animal.  The  same  thing  is  equally  true  of 
time.  That  time  is  not  directly  perceived  is  evident,  since 
no  lapse  of  time  is  present,  and  we  only  perceive  what  is 
present.  That,  not  having  the  idea  of  time,  we  should 
never  be  able  to  perceive  the  flow  in  our  sensations  without 
some  particular  aptitude  for  it,  will  probably  also  be  ad 
mitted.  The  idea  of  force  —  at  least,  in  its  rudiments  — 
is  another  conception  so  early  arrived  at,  and  found  in 
animals  so  low  in  the  scale  of  intelligence,  that  it  must  be 
supposed  innate.  But  the  innateness  of  an  idea  admits 
of  degree,  for  it  consists  in  the  tendency  of  that  idea  to 
present  itself  to  the  mind.  Some  ideas,  like  that  of  space, 
do  so  present  themselves  irresistibly  at  the  very  dawn  of 


124  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

intelligence,  and  take  possession  of  the  mind  on  small  prov 
ocation,  while  of  other  conceptions  we  are  prepossessed, 
indeed,  but  not  so  strongly,  down  a  scale  which  is  greatly 
extended.  The  tendency  to  personify  every  thing,  and  to 
attribute  human  characters  to  it,  may  be  said  to  be  innate; 
but  it  is  a  tendency  which  is  very  soon  overcome  by  civilized 
man  in  regard  to  the  greater  part  of  the  objects  about  him. 
Take  such  a  conception  as  that  of  gravitation  varying  in 
versely  as  the  square  of  the  distance.  It  is  a  very  simple 
law.  But  to  say  that  it  is  simple  is  merely  to  say  that  it 
is  one  which  the  mind  is  particularly  adapted  to  apprehend 
with  facility.  Suppose  the  idea  of  a  quantity  multiplied 
into  another  had  been  no  more  easy  to  the  mind  than  that 
of  a  quantity  raised  to  the  power  indicated  by  itself  — 
should  we  ever  have  discovered  the  law  of  the  solar  system? 

It  seems  incontestable,  therefore,  that  the  mind  of  man 
is  strongly  adapted  to  the  comprehension  of  the  world;  at 
least,  so  far  as  this  goes,  that  certain  conceptions,  highly 
important  for  such  a  comprehension,  naturally  arise  in  his 
mind;  and,  without  such  a  tendency,  the  mind  could  never 
have  had  any  development  at  all. 

How  are  we  to  explain  this  adaptation?  The  great 
utility  and  indispensableness  of  the  conceptions  of  time, 
space,  and  force,  even  to  the  lowest  intelligence,  are  such 
as  to  suggest  that  they  are  the  results  of  natural  selection. 
Without  something  like  geometrical,  kinetical,  and  mechani 
cal  conceptions,  no  animal  could  seize  his  food  or  do  any 
thing  which  might  be  necessary  for  the  preservation  of  the 
species.  He  might,  it  is  true,  be  provided  with  an  instinct 
which  would  generally  have  the  same  effect;  that  is  to  say, 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  125 

he  might  have  conceptions  different  from  those  of  time, 
space,  and  force,  but  which  coincided  with  them  in  regard 
to  the  ordinary  cases  of  the  animal's  experience.  But,  as 
that  animal  would  have  an  immense  advantage  in  the 
struggle  for  life  whose  mechanical  conceptions  did  not  break 
down  in  a  novel  situation  (such  as  development  must  bring 
about),  there  would  be  a  constant  selection  in  favor  of 
more  and  more  correct  ideas  of  these  matters.  Thus  would 
be  attained  the  knowledge  of  that  fundamental  law  upon 
which  all  science  rolls;  namely,  that  forces  depend  upon 
relations  of  time,  space,  and  mass.  When  this  idea  was 
once  sufficiently  clear,  it  would  require  no  more  than  a 
comprehensible  degree  of  genius  to  discover  the  exact  na 
ture  of  these  relations.  Such  an  hypothesis  naturally  sug 
gests  itself,  but  it  must  be  admitted  that  it  does  not  seem 
sufficient  to  account  for  the  extraordinary  accuracy  with 
which  these  conceptions  apply  to  the  phenomena  of  Nature, 
and  it  is  probable  that  there  is  some  secret  here  which 
remains  to  be  discovered. 


Some  important  questions  of  logic  depend  upon  whether 
we  are  to  consider  the  material  universe  as  of  limited  ex 
tent  and  finite  age,  or  quite  boundless  in  space  and  in  time. 
In  the  former  case,  it  is  conceivable  that  a  general  plan 
or  design  embracing  the  whole  universe  should  be  discov 
ered,  and  it  would  be  proper  to  be  on  the  alert  for  some 
traces  of  such  a  unity.  In  the  latter  case,  since  the  pro 
portion  of  the  world  of  which  we  can  have  any  experience  ) 
is  less  than  the  smallest  assignable  fraction,  it  follows  that 


126  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

we  never  could  discover  any  pattern  in  the  universe  except 
a  repeating  one;  any  design  embracing  the  whole  would  be 
beyond  our  powers  to  discern,  and  beyond  the  united  powers 
of  all  intellects  during  all  time.  Now,  what  is  absolutely 
incapable  of  being  known  is,  as  we  have  seen  in  a  former 
paper,  not  real  at  all.  An  absolutely  incognizable  existence 
is  a  nonsensical  phrase.  If,  therefore,  the  universe  is  infinite, 
the  attempt  to  find  in  it  any  design  embracing  it  as  a  whole 
is  futile,  and  involves  a  false  way  of  looking  at  the  subject. 
If  the  universe  never  had  any  beginning,  and  if  in  space 
world  stretches  beyond  world  without  limit,  there  is  no 
whole  of  material  things,  and  consequently  no  general  char 
acter  to  the  universe,  and  no  need  or  possibility  of  any 
governor  for  it.  But  if  there  was  a  time  before  which 
absolutely  no  matter  existed,  if  there  are  certain  absolute 
bounds  to  the  region  of  things  outside  of  which  there  is  a 
mere  void,  then  we  naturally  seek  for  an  explanation  of  it, 
and,  since  we  cannot  look  for  it  among  material  things, 
the  hypothesis  of  a  great  disembodied  animal,  the  creator 
and  governor  of  the  world,  is  natural  enough. 

The  actual  state  of  the  evidence  as  to  the  limitation  of 
the  universe  is  as  follows:  As  to  time,  we  find  on  our  earth 
a  constant  progress  of  development  since  the  planet  was  a 
red-hot  ball;  the  solar  system  seems  to  have  resulted  from 
the  condensation  of  a  nebula,  and  the  process  appears  to 
be  still  going  on.  We  sometimes  see  stars  (presumably 
with  systems  of  worlds)  destroyed  and  apparently  resolved 
back  into  the  nebulous  condition,  but  we  have  no  evidence 
of  any  existence  of  the  world  previous  to  the  nebulous  stage 
from  which  it  seems  to  have  been  evolved.  All  this  rather 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  I27 

favors  the  idea  of  a  beginning  than  otherwise.  As  for 
limits  in  space,  we  cannot  be  sure  that  we  see  anything 
outside  of  the  system  of  the  Milky  Way.  Minds  of  theo 
logical  predilections  have  therefore  no  need  of  distorting  the 
facts  to  reconcile  them  with  their  views. 

But  the  only  scientific  presumption  is,  that  the  unknown 
parts  of  space  and  time  are  like  the  known  parts,  occupied; 
that,  as  we  see  cycles  of  life  and  death  in  all  development 
which  we  can  trace  out  to  the  end,  the  same  holds  good  in 
regard  to  solar  systems;  that  as  enormous  distances  lie  be 
tween  the  different  planets  of  our  solar  system,  relatively 
to  their  diameters,  and  as  still  more  enormous  distances  lie 
between  our  system  relatively  to  its  diameter  and  other 
systems,  so  it  may  be  supposed  that  other  galactic  clusters 
exist  so  remote  from  ours  as  not  to  be  recognized  as  such 
with  certainty.  I  do  not  say  that  these  are  strong  induc 
tions;  I  only  say  that  they  are  the  presumptions  which, 
in  our  ignorance  of  the  facts,  should  be  preferred  to  hy 
potheses  which  involve  conceptions  of  things  and  occur 
rences  totally  different  in  their  character  from  any  of  which 
we  have  had  any  experience,  such  as  disembodied  spirits, 
the  creation  of  matter,  infringements  of  the  laws  of  me 
chanics,  etc. 

The  universe  ought  to  be  presumed  too  vast  to  have  any 
character.  When  it  is  claimed  that  the  arrangements  of 
Nature  are  benevolent,  or  just,  or  wise,  or  of  any  other 
peculiar  kind,  we  ought  to  be  prejudiced  against  such 
opinions,  as  being  the  offspring  of  an  ill-founded  notion 
of  the  finitude  of  the  world.  And  examination  has  hitherto 
shown  that  such  beneficences,  justice,  etc.,  are  of  a  most 
limited  kind  —  limited  in  degree  and  limited  in  range. 


iz8  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

In  like  manner,  if  any  one  claims  to  have  discovered  a 
plan  in  the  structure  of  organized  beings,  or  a  scheme  in 
their  classification,  or  a  regular  arrangement  among  natural 
objects,  or  a  system  of  proportionality  in  the  human  form, 
or  an  order  of  development,  or  a  correspondence  between 
conjunctions  of  the  planets  and  human  events,  or  a  signifi 
cance  in  numbers,  or  a  key  to  dreams,  the  first  thing  we 
have  to  ask  is  whether  such  relations  are  susceptible  of 
explanation  on  mechanical  principles,  and  if  not  they  should 
be  looked  upon  with  disfavor  as  having  already  a  strong 
presumption  against  them;  and  examination  has  generally 
exploded  all  such  theories. 

There  are  minds  to  whom  every  prejudice,  every  pre 
sumption,  seems  unfair.  It  is  easy  to  say  what  minds  these 
are.  They  are  those  who  never  have  known  what  it  is  to 
draw  a  well-grounded  induction,  and  who  imagine  that 
other  people's  knowledge  is  as  nebulous  as  their  own.  That 
all  science  rolls  upon  presumption  (not  of  a  formal  but  of 
a  real  kind)  is  no  argument  with  them,  because  they  can 
not  imagine  that  there  is  anything  solid  in  human  knowl 
edge.  These  are  the  people  who  waste  their  time  and 
money  upon  perpetual  motions  and  other  such  rubbish. 

But  there  are  better  minds  who  take  up  mystical  theories 
(by  which  I  mean  all  those  which  have  no  possibility  of 
being  mechanically  explained).  These  are  persons  who  are 
strongly  prejudiced  in  favor  of  such  theories.  We  all  have 
natural  tendencies  to  believe  in  such  things;  our  education 
often  strengthens  this  tendency;  and  the  result  is,  that  to 
many  minds  nothing  seems  so  antecedently  probable  as 
a  theory  of  this  kind.  Such  persons  find  evidence  enough 


THE    ORDER    OF    NATURE  129 

in  favor  of  their  views,  and  in  the  absence  of  any  recognized 
logic  of  induction  they  cannot  be  driven  from  their  belief. 

But  to  the  mind  of  a  physicist  there  ought  to  be  a  strong 
presumption  against  every  mystical  theory;  and,  therefore, 
it  seems  to  me  that  those  scientific  men  who  have  sought 
to  make  out  that  science  was  not  hostile  to  theology  have 
not  been  so  clear-sighted  as  their  opponents. 

It  would  be  extravagant  to  say  that  science  can  at  present 
disprove  religion;  but  it  does  seem  to  me  that  the  spirit  of 
science  is  hostile  to  any  religion  except  such  a  one  as  that 
of  M.  Vacherot.  Our  appointed  teachers  inform  us  that 
Buddhism  is  a  miserable  and  atheistical  faith,  shorn  of  the 
most  glorious  and  needful  attributes  of  a  religion;  that  its 
priests  can  be  of  no  use  to  agriculture  by  praying  for  rain, 
nor  to  war  by  commanding  the  sun  to  stand  still.  We  also 
hear  the  remonstances  of  those  who  warn  us  that  to  shake 
the  general  belief  in  the  living  God  would  be  to  shake  the 
general  morals,  public  and  private.  This,  too,  must  be  ad 
mitted;  such  a  revolution  of  thought  could  no  more  be 
accomplished  without  waste  and  desolation  than  a  planta 
tion  of  trees  could  be  transferred  to  new  ground,  however 
wholesome  in  itself,  without  all  of  them  .languishing  for  a 
time,  and  many  of  them  dying.  Nor  is  it,  by-the-way,  a 
thing  to  be  presumed  that  a  man  would  have  taken  part 
in  a  movement  having  a  possible  atheistical  issue  without 
having  taken  serious  and  adequate  counsel  in  regard  to  that 
responsibility.  But,  let  the  consequences  of  such  a  belief 
be  as  dire  as  they  may,  one  thing  is  certain:  that  the  state 
of  the  facts,  whatever  it  may  be,  will  surely  get  found  out, 
and  no  human  prudence  can  long  arrest  the  triumphal  car 


130  CHANCE   AND   LOGIC 

of  truth  —  no,  not  if  the  discovery  were  such  as  to  drive 
every  individual  of  our  race  to  suicide! 

But  it  would  be  folly  to  suppose  that  any  metaphysical 
theory  in  regard  to  the  mode  of  being  of  the  perfect  is  to 
destroy  that  aspiration  toward  the  perfect  which  constitutes 
the  essence  of  religion.  It  is  true  that,  if  the  priests  of 
any  particular  form  of  religion  succeed  in  making  it  gen 
erally  believed  that  religion  cannot  exist  without  the  accept 
ance  of  certain  formulas,  or  if  they  succeed  in  so  inter 
weaving  certain  dogmas  with  the  popular  religion  that  the 
people  can  see  no  essential  analogy  between  a  religion 
which  accepts  these  points  of  faith  and  one  which  rejects 
them,  the  result  may  very  well  be  to  render  thpse  who  can 
not  believe  these  things  irreligious.  Nor  can  we  ever  hope 
that  any  body  of  priests  should  consider  themselves  more 
teachers  of  religion  in  general  than  of  the  particular  system 
of  theology  advocated  by  their  own  party.  But  no  man 
need  be  excluded  from  participation  in  the  common  feelings, 
nor  from  so  much  of  the  public  expression  of  them  as  is 
open  to  all  the  laity,  by  the  unphilosophical  narrowness  of 
those  who  guard  the  mysteries  of  worship.  Am  I  to  be 
prevented  from  joining  in  that  common  joy  at  the  revela 
tion  of  enlightened  principles  of  religion,  which  we  celebrate 
at  Easter  and  Christmas,  because  I  think  that  certain  scien 
tific,  logical,  and  metaphysical  ideas  which  have  been  mixed 
up  with  these  principles  are  untenable?  No;  to  do  so 
would  be  to  estimate  those  errors  as  of  more  consequence 
than  the  truth  —  an  opinion  which  few  would  admit. 
People  who  do  not  believe  what  are  really  the  fundamental 
principles  of  Christianity  are  rare  to  find,  and  all  but  these 
few  ought  to  feel  at  home  in  the  churches. 


SIXTH   PAPER 
DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    AND    HYPOTHESIS1 


THE  chief  business  of  the  logician  is  to  classify  arguments; 
for  all  testing  clearly  depends  on  classification.  The  classes 
of  the  logicians  are  defined  by  certain  typical  forms  called 
syllogisms.  For  example,  the  syllogism  called  Barbara  is 
as  follows: 

S  is  M;    M  is  P: 

Hence,  S  is  P. 

Or,  to  put  words  for  letters  — 

Enoch  and  Elijah  were  men;  all  men  die: 
Hence,  Enoch  and  Elijah  must  have  died. 

The  "is  P  "  of  the  logicians  stands  for  any  verb,  active 
or  neuter.  It  is  capable  of  strict  proof  (with  which,  how 
ever,  I  will  not  trouble  the  reader)  that  all  arguments 
whatever  can  be  put  into  this  form;  but  only  under  the 
condition  that  the  is  shall  mean  "  is  for  the  purposes  of  the 
argument "  or  "  is  represented  by."  Thus,  an  induction 
will  appear  in  this  form  something  like  this: 

These  beans  are  two-thirds  white; 

But,  the  beans  in  this  bag  are  (represented  by)  these 
beans; 

1  Popular  Science  Monthly,  August,  1878. 


132  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

.'.  The  beans  in  the  bag  are  two-thirds  white. 
But,  because  all  inference  may  be  reduced  in  some  way 
to  Barbara,  it  does  not  follow  that  this  is  the  most  appro 
priate  form  in  which  to  represent  every  kind  of  inference. 
On  the  contrary,  to  show  the  distinctive  characters  of  dif 
ferent  sorts  of  inference,  they  must  clearly  be  exhibited  in 
different  forms  peculiar  to  each.  Barbara  particularly 
typifies  deductive  reasoning;  and  so  long  as  the  is  is  taken 
literally,  no  inductive  reasoning  can  be  put  into  this  form. 
Barbara  is,  in  fact,  nothing  but  the  application  of  a  rule. 
The  so-called  major  premise  lays  down  this  rule;  as,  for 
example,  All  men  are  mortal.  The  other  or  minor  premise 
states  a  case  under  the  rule;  as,  Enoch  was  a  man.  The 
conclusion  applies  the  rule  to  the  case  and  states  the  result : 
Enoch  is  mortal.  All  deduction  is  of  this  character;  it  is 
merely  the  application  of  general  rules  to  particular  cases. 
Sometimes  this  is  not  very  evident,  as  in  the  following; 

All  quadrangles  are  figures, 

But  no  triangle  is  a  quadrangle; 

Therefore,  some  figures  are  not  triangles. 

But  here  the  reasoning  is  really  this: 

Rule.  —  Every  quadrangle  is  other  than  a  triangle. 

Case.  —  Some  figures  are  quadrangles. 

Result.  —  Some  figures  are  not  triangles. 

Inductive  or  synthetic  reasoning,  being  something  more 
than  the  mere  application  of  a  general  rule  to  a  particular 
case,  can  never  be  reduced  to  this  form. 

If,  from  a  bag  of  beans  of  which  we  know  that  f  are 
white,  we  take  one  at  random,  it  is  a  deductive  inference 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          133 

that  this  bean  is  probably  white,  the  probability  being  f . 
We  have,  in  effect,  the  following  syllogism: 

Ride.  —  The  beans  in  this  bag  are  f  white. 

Case.  —  This  bean  has  been  drawn  in  such  a  way  that 
in  the  long  run  the  relative  number  of  white  beans  so  drawn 
would  be  equal  to  the  relative  number  in  the  bag. 

Result.  —  This  bean  has  been  drawn  in  such  a  way  that 
in  the  long  run  it  would  turn  out  white  f  of  the  time. 

If  instead  of  drawing  one  bean  we  draw  a  handful  at 
random  and  conclude  that  about  f  of  the  handful  are  prob 
ably  white,  the  reasoning  is  of  the  same  sort.  If,  however, 
not  knowing  what  proportion  of  white  beans  there  are  in 
the  bag,  we  draw  a  handful  at  random  and,  rinding  f  of 
the  beans  in  the  handful  white,  conclude  that  about  -f  of 
those  in  the  bag  are  white,  we  are  rowing  up  the  current 
of  deductive  sequence,  and  are  concluding  a  rule  from  the 
observation  of  a  result  in  a  certain  case.  This  is  particu 
larly  clear  when  all  the  handful  turn  out  one  color.  The 
induction  then  is: 

These  beans  were  in  this  bag 

These  beans  are  white 

.'.All  the  beans  in  the  bag  were  white. 

Which  is  but  an  inversion  of  the  deductive 
syllogism. 
Rule.  —  All  the  beans  in  the  bag  were  white — 

Case.  —  These  beans  were  in  the  bag. 

Result.  —  These  beans  are  white 


So  that  jnduction  is  the  inference  of  the  rule  from  the  case 
and  result. 


CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

But  this  is  not  the  only  way  of  inverting  a  deductive 
syllogism  so  as  to  produce  a  synthetic  inference.  Suppose 
I  enter  a  room  and  there  find  a  number  of  bags,  containing 
different  kinds  of  beans.  On  the  table  there  is  a  handful 
of  white  beans;  and,  after  some  searching,  I  find  one  of  the 
bags  contains  white  beans  only.  I  at  once  infer  as  a  prob 
ability,  or  as  a  fair  guess,  that  this  handful  was  taken  out 
of  that  bag.  This  sort  of  inference  is  called  making  an 
hypothesis*  It  is  the  inference  of  a  case  from  a  rule  and 
result.  We  have,  then  — 

DEDUCTION. 

Rule.  —  All  the  beans  from  this  bag  are  white. 
Case.  —  These  beans  are  from  this  bag. 
.'.Result.  —  These  beans  are  white. 

INDUCTION. 

Case.  —  These  beans  are  from  this  bag. 
Result.  —  These  beans  are  white. 
.'.Rule.  —  All  the  beans  from  this  bag  are  white. 

HYPOTHESIS. 

Rule.  —  All  the  beans  from  this  bag  are  white. 
Result.  —  These  beans  are  white. 
^y.  Case.  —  These  beans  are  from  this  bag. 
We,  accordingly,  classify  all  inference  as  follows: 
Inference. 


Deductive  or  Analytic.  Synthetic. 


Induction.  Hypothesis. 

2  [Later  Pierce   called   it   presumptive    inference.    See    Baldwin's  Dic 
tionary  art.  Probable  Inference.! 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          135 

Induction  is  where  we  generalize  from  a  number  of  cases 
of  which  something  is  true,  and  infer  that  the  same  thing 
is  true  of  a  whole  class.  Or,  where  we  find  a  certain  thing 
to  be  true  of  a  certain  proportion  of  cases  and  infer  that  it 
is  true  of  the  same  proportion  of  the  whole  class.  Hy 
pothesis  is  where  we  find  some  very  curious  circumstance, 
which  would  be  explained  by  the  supposition  that  it  was 
a  case  of  a  certain  general  rule,  and  thereupon  adopt  that 
supposition.  Or,  where  we  find  that  in  certain  respects 
two  objects  have  a  strong  resemblance,  and  infer  that  they 
resemble  one  another  strongly  in  other  respects. 

I  once  landed  at  a  seaport  in  a  Turkish  province;  and, 
as  I  was  walking  up  to  the  house  which  I  was  to  visit,  I 
met  a  man  upon  horseback,  surrounded  by  four  horsemen 
holding  a  canopy  over  his  head.  As  the  governor  of  the 
province  was  the  only  personage  I  could  think  of  who  would 
be  so  greatly  honored,  I  inferred  that  this  was  he.  This 
was  an  hypothesis. 

Fossils  are  found;  say,  remains  like  those  of  fishes,  but 
far  in  the  interior  of  the  country.  To  explain  the  phe 
nomenon,  we  suppose  the  sea  once  washed  over  this  land. 
This  is  another  hypothesis. 

Numberless  documents  and  monuments  refer  to  a  con 
queror  called  Napoleon  Bonaparte.  Though  we  have  not 
seen  the  man,  yet  we  cannot  explain  what  we  have  seen, 
namely,  all  these  documents  and  monuments,  without  sup 
posing  that  he  really  existed.  Hypothesis  again. 

As  a  general  rule,  hypothesis  is  a  weak  kind  of  argument. 
It  often  inclines  our  judgment  so  slightly  toward  its  con 
clusion  that  we  cannot  say  that  we  believe  the  latter  to 


,36  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

be  true;  we  only  surmise  that  it  may  be  so.  But  there  is  no 
difference  except  one  of  degree  between  such  an  inference 
and  that  by  which  we  are  led  to  believe  that  we  remember 
the  occurrences  of  yesterday  from  our  feeling  as  if  we  did  so. 

ii 

Besides  the  way  just  pointed  out  of  inverting  a  deductive 
syllogism  to  produce  an  induction  or  hypothesis,  there  is 
another.  If  from  the  truth  of  a  certain  premise  the  truth 
of  a  certain  conclusion  would  necessarily  follow,  then  from 
the  falsity  of  the  conclusion  the  falsity  of  the  premise  would 
follow.  Thus,  take  the  following  syllogism  in  Barbara: 

Rule.  —  All  men  are  mortal. 
Case.  —  Enoch  and  Elijah  were  men. 
.*.  Result.  —  Enoch  and  Elijah  were  mortal. 

Now,  a  person  who  denies  this  result  may  admit  the  rule, 
and,  in  that  case,  he  must  deny  the  case.  Thus: 

Denial  of  Result.  —  Enoch  and  Elijah  were  not  mortal. 
Rule.  —  All  men  are  mortal. 
/.  Denial  of  Case.  —  Enoch  and  Elijah  were  not  men. 

This  kind  of  syllogism  is  called  Baroco,  which  is  the  typi 
cal  mood  of  the  second  figure.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
person  who  denies  the  result  may  admit  the  case,  and  in 
that  case  he  must  deny  the  rule.  Thus: 

Denial  of  the  Result.  —  Enoch  and   Elijah   were  not 

mortal. 

Case.  —  Enoch  and  Elijah  were  men. 
.*.  Denial  of  the  Rule.  —  Some  men  are  not  mortal. 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          137 

This  kind  of  syllogism  is  called  Bocardo,  which  is  the 
typical  mood  of  the  third  figure. 

Baroco  and  Bocardo  are,  of  course,  deductive  syllogisms; 
but  of  a  very  peculiar  kind.  They  are  called  by  logicians 
indirect  moods,  because  they  need  some  transformation  to 
appear  as  the  application  of  a  rule  to  a  particular  case. 
But  if,  instead  of  setting  out  as  we  have  here  done  with  a 
necessary  deduction  in  Barbara,  we  take  a  probable  deduc 
tion  of  similar  form,  the  indirect  moods  which  we  shall 
obtain  will  be  — 

Corresponding  to  Baroco,  an  hypothesis; 
and,  Corresponding  to  Bocardo,  an  induction. 

For  example,  let  us  begin  with  this  probable  deduction 
in  Barbara: 

Rule.  —  Most  of  the  beans  in  this  bag  are  white. 
Case.  —  This  handful  of  beans  are  from  this  bag. 
.'.  Result.  —  Probably,  most  of  this  handful  of  beans  are 
white. 

Now,  deny  the  result,  but  accept  the  rule: 
Denial  of  Result.  —  Few  beans  of  this  handful  are 

white. 

Rule.  —  Most  beans  in  this  bag  are  white. 
.'.Denial  of  Case.  —  Probably,  these  beans  were  taken 
from  another  bag. 

This  is  an  hypothetical  inference.  Next,  deny  the  result, 
but  accept  the  case: 

Denial  of  Result.  —  Few  beans  of  this  handful  are 

white. 
Case.  —  These  beans  came  from  this  bag. 


138  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

/.  Denial  oj  Ride.  —  Probably,  few  beans  in  the  bag  are 
white. 

This  is  an  induction. 

The  relation  thus  exhibited  between  synthetic  and  de 
ductive  reasoning  is  not  without  its  importance.  When  we 
adopt  a  certain  hypothesis,  it  is  not  alone  because  it  will 
explain  the  observed  facts,  but  also  because  the  contrary 
hypothesis  would  probably  lead  to  results  contrary  to  those 
observed.  So,  when  we  make  an  induction,  it  is  drawn  not 
only  because  it  explains  the  distribution  of  characters  in 
the  sample,  but  also  because  a  different  rule  would  prob 
ably  have  led  to  the  sample  being  other  than  it  is. 

But  the  advantage  of  this  way  of  considering  the  subject 
might  easily  be  overrated.  An  induction  is  really  the  in 
ference  of  a  rule,  and  to  consider  it  as  the  denial  of  a  rule 
is  an  artificial  conception,  only  admissible  because,  when 
statistical  or  proportional  propositions  are  considered  as 
rules,  the  denial  of  a  rule  is  itself  a  rule.  So,  an  hypothesis 
is  really  a  subsumption  of  a  case  under  a  class  and  not  the 
denial  of  it,  except  for  this,  that  to  deny  a  subsumption 
under  one  class  is  to  admit  a  subsumption  under  another. 

Bocardo  may  be  considered  as  an  induction,  so  timid  as 
to  lose  its  amplificative  character  entirely.  Enoch  and  Eli 
jah  are  specimens  of  a  certan  kind  of  men.  All  that  kind 
of  men  are  shown  by  these  instances  to  be  immortal.  But 
instead  of  boldly  concluding  that  all  very  pious  men,  or  all 
men  favorites  of  the  Almighty,  etc.,  are  immortal,  we  re 
frain  from  specifying  the  description  of  men,  and  rest  in 
the  merely  explicative  inference  that  so  me  men  are  im- 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          139 

mortal.  So  Baroco  might  be  considered  as  a  very  timid 
hypothesis.  Enoch  and  Elijah  are  not  mortal.  Now,  we 
might  boldly  suppose  them  to  be  gods  or  something  of  that 
sort,  but  instead  of  that  we  limit  ourselves  to  the  inference 
that  they  are  of  some  nature  different  from  that  of  man. 

But,  after  all,  there  is  an  immense  difference  between  the 
relation  of  Baroco  and  Bocardo  to  Barbara  and  that  of 
Induction  and  Hypothesis  to  Deduction.  Baroco  and  Bo 
cardo  are  based  upon  the  fact  that  if  the  truth  of  a  con 
clusion  necessarily  follows  from  the  truth  of  a  premise,  then 
the  falsity  of  the  premise  follows  from  the  falsity  of  the 
conclusion.  This  is  always  true.  It  is  different  when  the 
inference  is  only  probable.  It  by  no  means  follows  that, 
because  the  truth  of  a  certain  premise  would  render  the 
truth  of  a  conclusion  probable,  therefore  the  falsity  of  the 
conclusion  renders  the  falsity  of  the  premise  probable.  At 
least,  this  is  only  true,  as  we  have  seen  in  a  former  paper, 
when  the  word  probable  is  used  in  one  sense  in  the  ante 
cedent  and  in  another  in  the  consequent. 


in 

A  certain  anonymous  writing  is  upon  a  torn  piece  of 
paper.  It  is  suspected  that  the  author  is  a  certain  person. 
His  desk,  to  which  only  he  has  had  access,  is  searched,  and 
in  it  is  found  a  piece  of  paper,  the  torn  edge  of  which  ex 
actly  fits,  in  all  its  irregularities,  that  of  the  paper  in  ques 
tion.  It  is  a  fair  hypothetic  inference  that  the  suspected 
man  was  actually  the  author.  The  ground  of  this  inference 
evidently  is  that  two  torn  pieces  of  paper  are  extremely 


I4o  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

unlikely  to  fit  together  by  accident.  Therefore,  of  a  great 
number  of  inferences  of  this  sort,  but  a  very  small  propor 
tion  would  be  deceptive.  The  analogy  of  hypothesis  with 
induction  is  so  strong  that  some  logicians  have  confounded 
them.  Hypothesis  has  been  called  an  induction  of  charac 
ters.  A  number  of  characters  belonging  to  a  certain  class 
are  found  in  a  certain  object;  whence  it  is  inferred  that  all 
the  characters  of  that  class  belong  to  the  object  in  question. 
This  certainly  involves  the  same  principle  as  induction; 
yet  in  a  modified  form.  In  the  first  place,  characters  are 
not  susceptible  of  simple  enumeration  like  objects;  in  the 
next  place,  characters  run  in  categories.  When  we  make 
an  hypothesis  like  that  about  the  piece  of  paper,  we  only 
examine  a  single  line  of  characters,  or  perhaps  two  or  three, 
and  we  take  no  specimen  at  all  of  others.  If  the  hypothesis 
were  nothing  but  an  induction,  all  that  we  should  be  justi 
fied  in  concluding,  in  the  example  above,  would  be  that  the 
two  pieces  of  paper  which  matched  in  such  irregularities 
as  have  been  examined  would  be  found  to  match  in  other, 
say  slighter,  irregularities.  The  inference  from  the  shape 
of  the  paper  to  its  ownership  is  precisely  what  distinguishes 
hypothesis  from  induction,  and  makes  it  a  bolder  and  more 
perilous  step. 

The  same  warnings  that  have  been  given  against  imagin 
ing  that  induction  rests  upon  the  uniformity  of  Nature 
might  be  repeated  in  regard  to  hypothesis.  Here,  as  there, 
such  a  theory  not  only  utterly  fails  to  account  for  the 
validity  of  the  inference,  but  it  also  gives  rise  to  methods 
of  conducting  it  which  are  absolutely  vicious.  There  are, 
no  doubt,  certain  uniformities  in  Nature,  the  knowledge  of 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          141 

which  will  fortify  an  hypothesis  very  much.  For  example, 
we  suppose  that  iron,  titanium,  and  other  metals  exist  in 
the  sun,  because  we  find  in  the  solar  spectrum  many  lines 
coincident  in  position  with  those  which  these  metals  would 
produce;  and  this  hypothesis  is  greatly  strengthened  by 
our  knowledge  of  the  remarkable  distinctiveness  of  the  par 
ticular  line  of  characters  observed.  But  such  a  fortification 
of  hypothesis  is  of  a  deductive  kind,  and  hypothesis  may 
still  be  probable  when  such  reinforcement  is  wanting. 

There  is  no  greater  nor  more  frequent  mistake  in  prac 
tical  logic  than  to  suppose  that  things  which  resemble  one 
another  strongly  in  some  respects  are  any  the  more  likely 
for  that  to  be  alike  in  others.  That  this  is  absolutely  false, 
admits  of  rigid  demonstration;  but,  inasmuch  as  the 
reasoning  is  somewhat  severe  and  complicated  (requiring, 
like  all  such  reasoning,  the  use  of  A,  B,  C,  etc.,  to  set  it 
forth),  the  reader  would  probably  find  it  distasteful,  and 
I  omit  it.  An  example,  however,  may  illustrate  the  propo 
sition:  The  comparative  mythologists  occupy  themselves 
with  finding  points  of  resemblance  between  solar  phenom 
ena  and  the  careers  of  the  heroes  of  all  sorts  of  traditional 
stories;  and  upon  the  basis  of  such  resemblances  they  in 
fer  that  these  heroes  are  impersonations  of  the  sun.  If 
there  be  anything  more  in  their  reasonings,  it  has  never 
been  made  clear  to  me.  An  ingenious  logician,  to  show  how 
futile  all  that  is,  wrote  a  little  book,  in  which  he  pretended 
to  prove,  in  the  same  manner,  that  Napoleon  Bonaparte 
is  only  an  impersonation  of  the  sun.  It  was  really  wonder 
ful  to  see  how  many  points  of  resemblance  he  made  out. 
The  truth  is,  that  any  two  things  resemble  one  another 


H2  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

just  as  strongly  as  any  two  others,  if  recondite  resemblances 
are  admitted.  But,  in  order  that  the  process  of  making  an 
hypothesis  should  lead  to  a  probable  result,  the  following 
rules  must  be  followed: 

fPThe  hypothesis  should  be  distinctly  put  as  a  question, 
before  making  the  observations  which  are  to  test  its  truth. 
In  other  words,  we  must  try  to  see  what  the  result  of  pre 
dictions  from  the  hypothesis  will  be. 

2.  The  respect  in  regard  to  which  the  resemblances  are 
noted  must  be  taken  at  random.    We  must  not  take  a  par 
ticular  kind  of  predictions  for  which  the  hypothesis  is  known 
to  be  good. 

3.  The  failures  as  well  as  the  successes  of  the  predictions 
must  be  honestly  noted.     The  whole  proceeding  must  be 
fair  and  unbiased. 

Some  persons  fancy  that  bias  and  counter-bias  are  favor 
able  to  the  extraction  of  truth  —  that  hot  and  partisan  de 
bate  is  the  way  to  investigate.  This  is  the  theory  of  our 
atrocious  legal  procedure.  But  Logic  puts  its  heel  upon 
this  suggestion.  It  irrefragably  demonstrates  that  knowl 
edge  can  only  be  furthered  by  the  real  desire  for  it,  and 
that  the  methods  of  obstinacy,  of  authority,  and  every  mode 
of  trying  to  reach  a  foregone  conclusion,  are  absolutely  of 
no  value.  These  things  are  proved.  The  reader  is  at  lib 
erty  to  think  so  or  not  as  long  as  the  proof  is  not  set  forth, 
or  as  long  as  he  refrains  from  examining  it.  Just  so,  he 
can  preserve,  if  he  likes,  his  freedom  of  opinion  in  regard 
to  the  propositions  of  geometry;  only,  in  that  case,  if  he 
takes  a  fancy  to  read  Euclid,  he  will  do  well  to  skip  what 
ever  he  finds  with  A,  B,  C,  etc.,  for,  if  he  reads  attentively 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          143 

that  disagreeable  matter,  the  freedom  of  his  opinion  about 
geometry  may  unhappily  be  lost  forever. 

How  many  people  there  are  who  are  incapable  of  putting 
to  their  own  consciences  this  question,  "  Do  I  want  to  know 
how  the  fact  stands,  or  not?  " 

The  rules  which  have  thus  far  been  laid  down  for  in 
duction  and  hypothesis  are  such  as  are  absolutely  essential. 
There  are  many  other  maxims  expressing  particular  con 
trivances  for  making  synthetic  inferences  strong,  which  are 
extremely  valuable  and  should  not  be  neglected.  Such 
are,  for  example,  Mr.  MilPs  four  methods.  Nevertheless, 
in  the  total  neglect  of  these,  inductions  and  hypotheses 
may  and  sometimes  do  attain  the  greatest  force. 

-^ 

IV 

Classifications  in  all  cases  perfectly  satisfactory  hardly 
exist.  Even  in  regard  to  the  great  distinction  between  ex 
plicative  and  ampliative  inferences,  examples  could  be  found 
which  seem  to  lie  upon  the  border  between  the  two  classes, 
and  to  partake  in  some  respects  of  the  characters  of  either. 
The  same  thing  is  true  of  the  distinction  between  induction 
and  hypothesis.  In  the  main,  it  is  broad  and  decided.  By 
induction,  we  conclude  that  facts,  similar  to  observed  facts, 
are  true  in  cases  not  examined.  By  hypothesis,  we  con 
clude  the  existence  of  a  fact  quite  different  from  anything 
observed,  from  which,  according  to  known  laws,  something 
observed  would  necessarily  result.  The  former,  is  reason 
ing  from  particulars  to  the  general  law;  the  latter,  from 
effect  to  cause.  The  former  classifies,  the  latter  explains. 


144  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

It  is  only  in  some  special  cases  that  there  can  be  more  than 
a  momentary  doubt  to  which  category  a  given  inference 
belongs.  One  exception  is  where  we  observe,  not  facts  sim 
ilar  under  similar  circumstances,  but  facts  different  under 
different  circumstances  —  the  difference  of  the  former  hav 
ing,  however,  a  definite  relation  to  the  difference  of  the 
latter.  Such  inferences,  which  are  really  inductions,  some 
times  present  nevertheless  some  indubitable  resemblances 
to  hypotheses. 

Knowing  that  water  expands  by  heat,  we  make  a  number 
of  observations  of  the  volume  of  a  constant  mass  of  water 
at  different  temperatures.  The  scrutiny  of  a  few  of  these 
suggests  a  form  of  algebraical  formula  which  will  approxi 
mately  express  the  relation  of  the  volume  to  the  tempera 
ture.  It  may  be,  for  instance,  that  v  being  the  relative 
volume,  and  t  the  temperature,  a  few  observations  ex 
amined  indicate  a  relation  of  the  form  — 

v  =  i  +  at  +  bt-  +  cf. 

Upon  examining  observations  at  other  temperatures  taken 
at  random,  this  idea  is  confirmed;  and  we  draw  the  induc 
tive  conclusion  that  all  observations  within  the  limits  of 
temperature  from  which  we  have  drawn  our  observations 
could  equally  be  so  satisfied.  Having  once  ascertained  that 
such  a  formula  is  possible,  it  is  a  mere  affair  of  arithmetic 
to  find  the  values  of  a,  b,  and  c,  which  will  make  the  formula 
satisfy  the  observations  best.  This  is  what  physicists  call 
an  empirical  formula,  because  it  rests  upon  mere  induction, 
and  is  not  explained  by  any  hypothesis. 

Such  formulae,  though  very  useful  as  means  of  describing 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          145 

in  general  terms  the  results  of  observations,  do  not  take 
any  high  rank  among  scientific  discoveries.  The  induction 
which  they  embody,  that  expansion  by  heat  (or  whatever 
other  phenomenon  is  referred  to)  takes  place  in  a  perfectly 
gradual  manner,  without  sudden  leaps  or  inummerable  fluc 
tuations,  although  really  important,  attracts  no  attention, 
because  it  is  what  we  naturally  anticipate.  But  the  defects 
of  such  expressions  are  very  serious.  In  the  first  place,  as 
long  as  the  observations  are  subject  to  error,  as  all  observa 
tions  are,  the  formula  cannot  be  expected  to  satisfy  the 
observations  exactly.  But  the  discrepancies  cannot  be  due 
solely  to  the  errors  of  the  observations,  but  must  be  partly 
owing  to  the  error  of  the  formula  which  has  been  deducted 
from  erroneous  observations.  Moreover,  we  have  no  right 
to  suppose  that  the  real  facts,  if  they  could  be  had  free 
from  error,  could  be  expressed  by  such  a  formula  at  all. 
They  might,  perhaps,  be  expressed  by  a  similar  formula 
with  an  infinite  number  of  terms;  but  of  what  use  would 
that  be  to  us,  since  it  would  require  an  infinite  number  of 
coefficients  to  be  written  down?  When  one  quantity  varies 
with  another,  if  the  corresponding  values  are  exactly  known, 
it  is  a  mere  matter  of  mathematical  ingenuity  to  find  some 
way  of  expressing  their  relation  in  a  simple  manner.  If 
one  quantity  is  of  one  kind  —  say,  a  specific  gravity  —  and 
the  other  of  another  kind  —  say,  a  temperature  —  we  do 
not  desire  to  find  an  expression  for  their  relation  which  is 
wholly  free  from  numerical  constants,  since  if  it  were  free 
from  them  when,  say,  specific  gravity  as  compared  with 
water,  and  temperature  as  expressed  by  the  Centigrade  ther 
mometer,  were  in  question,  numbers  would  have  to  be  in- 


I46  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

troduced  when  the  scales  of  measurement  were  changed. 
We  may,  however,  and  do  desire  to  find  formulas  expressing 
the  relations  of  physical  phenomena  which  shall  contain 
no  more  arbitrary  numbers  than  changes  in  the  scales  of 
measurement  might  require. 

When  a  formula  of  this  kind  is  discovered,  it  is  no  longer 
called  an  empirical  formula,  but  a  law  of  Nature;  and  is 
sooner  or  later  made  the  basis  of  an  hypothesis  which  is 
to  explain  it.  These  simple  formulae  are  not  usually,  if 
ever,  exactly  true,  but  they  are  none  the  less  important  for 
that;  and  the  great  triumph  of  the  hypothesis  comes  when 
it  explains  not  only  the  formula,  but  also  the  deviations 
from  the  formula.  In  the  current  language  of  the  physi 
cists,  an  hypothesis  of  this  importance  is  called  a  theory, 
while  the  term  hypothesis  is  restricted  to  suggestions  which 
have  little  evidence  in  their  favor.  There  is  some  justice 
in  the  contempt  which  clings  to  the  word  hypothesis.  To 
think  that  we  can  strike  out  of  our  own  minds  a  true  pre 
conception  of  how  Nature  acts,  in  a  vain  fancy.  As  Lord 
Bacon  well  says:  "  The  subtlety  of  Nature  far  exceeds  the 
subtlety  of  sense  and  intellect:  so  that  these  fine  medita 
tions,  and  speculations,  and  reasonings  of  men  are  a  sort 
of  insanity,  only  there  is  no  one  at  hand  to  remark  it." 
The  successful  theories  are  not  pure  guesses,  but  are  guided 
by  reasons. 

The  kinetical  theory  of  gases  is  a  good  example  of  this. 
This  theory  is  intended  to  explain  certain  simple  formulae, 
the  chief  of  which  is  called  the  law  of  Boyle.  It  is,  that  if 
air  or  any  other  gas  be  placed  in  a  cylinder  with  a  piston, 
and  if  its  volume  be  measured  under  the  pressure  of  the 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          147 

atmosphere,  say  fifteen  pounds  on  the  square  inch,  and  if 
then  another  fifteen  pounds  per  square  inch  be  placed  on 
the  piston,  the  gas  will  be  compressed  to  one-half  its  bulk, 
and  in  similar  inverse  ratio  for  other  pressures.  The 
hypothesis  which  has  been  adopted  to  account  for  this  law 
is  that  the  molecules  of  a  gas  are  small,  solid  particles  at 
great  distances  from  each  other  (relatively  to  their  dimen 
sions),  and  moving  with  great  velocity,  without  sensible 
attractions  or  repulsions,  until  they  happen  to  approach 
one  another  very  closely.  Admit  this,  and  it  follows  that 
when  a  gas  is  under  pressure  what  prevents  it  from  collaps 
ing  is  not  the  incompressibility  of  the  separate  mole 
cules,  which  are  under  no  pressure  at  all,  since  they  do  not 
touch,  but  the  pounding  of  the  molecules  against  the  piston. 
The  more  the  piston  falls,  and  the  more  the  gas  is  com 
pressed,  the  nearer  together  the  molecules  will  be;  the 
greater  number  there  will  be  at  any  moment  within  a  given 
distance  of  the  piston,  the  shorter  the  distance  which  any 
one  will  go  before  its  course  is  changed  by  the  influence  of 
another,  the  greater  number  of  new  courses  of  each  in  a 
given  time,  and  the  oftener  each,  within  a  given  distance 
of  the  piston,  will  strike  it.  This  explains  Boyle's  law.  The 
law  is  not  exact;  but  the  hypothesis  does  not  lead  us  to  it 
exactly.  For,  in  the  first  place,  if  the  molecules  are  large, 
they  will  strike  each  other  oftener  when  their  mean  dis 
tances  are  diminished,  and  will  consequently  strike  the 
piston  oftener,  and  will  produce  more  pressure  upon  it.  On 
the  other  hand,  if  the  molecules  have  an  attraction  for  one 
another,  they  will  remain  for  a  sensible  time  within  one 
another's  influence,  and  consequently  they  will  not  strike 


i48  CHANCE   AND    LOGIC 

the  wall  so  often  as  they  otherwise  would,  and  the  pressure 
will  be  less  increased  by  compression. 

When  the  kinetical  theory  of  gases  was  first  proposed  by 
Daniel  Bernoulli,  in  1738,  it  rested  only  on  the  law  of 
Boyle,  and  was  therefore  pure  hypothesis.  It  was  ac 
cordingly  quite  naturally  and  deservedly  neglected.  But, 
at  present,  the  theory  presents  quite  another  aspect;  for, 
not  to  speak  of  the  considerable  number  of  observed  facts 
of  different  kinds  with  which  it  has  been  brought  into  re 
lation,  it  is  supported  by  the  mechanical  theory  of  heat. 
That  bringing  together  bodies  which  attract  one  another,  or 
separating  bodies  which  repel  one  another,  when  sensible 
motion  is  not  produced  nor  destroyed,  is  always  accompanied 
by  the  evolution  of  heat,  is  little  more  than  an  induction. 
Now,  it  has  been  shown  by  experiment  that,  when  a  gas  is 
allowed  to  expand  without  doing  work,  a  very  small  amount 
of  heat  disappears.  This  proves  that  the  particles  of  the 
gas  attract  one  another  slightly,  and  but  very  slightly.  It 
follows  that,  when  a  gas  is  under  pressure,  what  prevents 
it  from  collapsing  is  not  any  repulsion  between  the  parti 
cles,  since  there  is  none.  Now,  there  are  only  two  modes 
of  force  known  to  us,  force  of  position  or  attractions  and 
repulsions,  and  force  of  motion.  Since,  therefore,  it  is  not 
the  force  of  position  which  gives  a  gas  its  expansive  force, 
it  must  be  the  force  of  motion.  In  this  point  of  view,  the 
kinetical  theory  of  gases  appears  as  a  deduction  from  the 
mechanical  theory  of  heat.  It  is  to  be  observed,  however, 
that  it  supposes  the  same  law  of  mechanics  (that  there  are 
only  those  two  modes  of  force)  which  holds  in  regard  to 
bodies  such  as  we  can  see  and  examine,  to  hold  also  for 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          149 

what  are  very  different,  the  molecules  of  bodies.  Such  a 
supposition  has  but  a  slender  support  from  induction.  Our 
belief  in  it  is  greatly  strengthened  by  its  connection  with  the 
law  of  Boyle,  and  it  is,  therefore,  to  be  considered  as  an 
hypothetical  inference.  Yet  it  must  be  admitted  that  the 
kinetical  theory  of  gases  would  deserve  little  credence  if  it 
had  not  been  connected  with  the  principles  of  mechanics. 

The  great  difference  between  induction  and  hypothesis  is, 
that  the  former  infers  the  existence  of  phenomena  such  as 
we  have  observed  in  cases  which  are  similar,  while  hypothe 
sis  supposes  something  of  a  different  kind  from  what  we 
have  directly  observed,  and  frequently  something  which 
it  would  be  impossible  for  us  to  observe  directly.  Accord 
ingly,  when  we  stretch  an  induction  quite  beyond  the  limits 
of  our  observation,  the  inference  partakes  of  the  nature  of 
hypothesis.  It  would  be  absurd  to  say  that  we  have  no 
inductive  warrant  for  a  generalization  extending  a  little 
beyond  the  limits  of  experience,  and  there  is  no  line  to  be 
drawn  beyond  which  we  cannot  push  our  inference;  only 
it  becomes  weaker  the  further  it  is  pushed.  Yet,  if  an  in 
duction  be  pushed  very  far,  we  cannot  give  it  much  credence 
unless  we  find  that  such  an  extension  explains  some  fact 
which  we  can  and  do  observe.  Here,  then,  we  have  a  kind 
of  mixture  of  induction  and  hypothesis  supporting  one  an 
other;  and  of  this  kind  are  most  of  the  theories  of  physics. 


150  CHANCE    AND   LOGIC 


That  synthetic  inferences  may  be  divided  into  induction 
and  hypothesis  in  the  manner  here  proposed,3  admits  of  no 
question.  The  utility  and  value  of  the  distinction  are  to 
be  tested  by  their  applications. 

Induction  is,  plainly,  a  much  stronger  kind  of  inference 
than  hypothesis;  and  this  is  the  first  reason  for  distinguish 
ing  between  them.  Hypotheses  are  sometimes  regarded  as 
provisional  resorts,  which  in  the 'progress  of  science  are  to 
be  replaced  by  inductions.  But  this  is  a  false  view  of  the 
subject.  Hypothetic  reasoning  infers  very  frequently  a  fact 
not  capable  of  direct  observation.  It  is  an  hypothesis  that 
Napoleon  Bonaparte  once  existed.  How  is  that  hypothesis 
ever  to  be  replaced  by  an  induction?  It  may  be  said  that 
from  the  premise  that  such  facts  as  we  have  observed  are 
as  they  would  be  if  Napoleon  existed,  we  are  to  infer  by 
induction  that  all  facts  that  are  hereafter  to  be  observed 
will  be  of  the  same  character.  There  is  no  doubt  that  every 
hypothetic  inference  may  be  distorted  into  the  appearance 
of  an  induction  in  this  way.  But  the  essence  of  an  induc 
tion  is  that  it  infers  from  one  set  of  facts  another  set  of 
similar  facts,  whereas  hypothesis  infers  from  facts  of  one 
kind  to  facts  of  another.  Now,  the  facts  which  serve  as 
grounds  for  our  belief  in  the  historic  reality  of  Napoleon 
are  not  by  any  means  necessarily  the  only  kind  of  facts 
which  are  explained  by  his  existence.  It  may  be  that,  at 

3  This  division  was  first  made  in  a  course  of  lectures  by  the  author 
before  the  Lowell  Institute,  Boston,  in  1866,  and  was  printed  in  the 
Proceedings  of  the  American  Academy  of  Arts  and  Sciences,  lor  April  9, 
1867. 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          151 

the  time  of  his  career,  events  were  being  recorded  in  some 
way  not  now  dreamed  of,  that  some  ingenious  creature  on 
a  neighboring  planet  was  photographing  the  earth,  and  that 
these  pictures  on  a  sufficiently  large  scale  may  some  time 
come  into  our  possession,  or  that  some  mirror  upon  a  dis 
tant  star  will,  when  the  light  reaches  it,  reflect  the  whole 
story  back  to  earth.  Never  mind  how  improbable  these 
suppositions  are;  everything  which  happens  is  infinitely 
improbable.  I  am  not  saying  that  these  things  are  likely 
to  occur,  but  that  some  effect  of  Napoleon's  existence  which 
now  seems  impossible  is  certain  nevertheless  to  be  brought 
about.  The  hypothesis  asserts  that  such  facts,  when  they 
do  occur,  will  be  of  a  nature  to  confirm,  and  not  to  refute, 
the  existence  of  the  man.  We  have,  in  the  impossibility  of 
inductively  inferring  hypothetical  conclusions,  a  second 
reason  for  distinguishing  between  the  two  kinds  of  inference. 
A  third  merit  of  the  distinction  is,  that  it  is  associated 
with  an  important  psychological  or  rather  physiological 
difference  in  the  mode  of  apprehending  facts.  Induction 
infers  a  rule.  Now,  the  belief  of  a  rule  is  a  habit.  That 
a  habit  is  a  rule  active  in  us,  is  evident.  That  every  belief 
is  of  the  nature  of  a  habit,  in  so  far  as  it  is  of  a  general 
character,  has  been  shown  in  the  earlier  papers  of  this 
series.  Induction,  therefore,  is  the  logical  formula  which 
expresses  the  physiological  process  of  formation  of  a  habit. 
Hypothesis  substitutes,  for  a  complicated  tangle  of  predi 
cates  attached  to  one  subject,  a  single  conception.  Now, 
there  is  a  peculiar  sensation  belonging  to  the  act  of  thinking 
that  each  of  these  predicates  inheres  in  the  subject.  In 
hypothetic  inference  this  complicated  feeling  so  produced 


IS2  CHANCE    AND    LOGIC 

is  replaced  by  a  single  feeling  of  greater  intensity,  that 
belonging  to  the  act  of  thinking  the  hypothetic  conclusion. 
Now,  when  our  nervous  system  is  excited  in  a  complicated 
way,  there  being  a  relation  between  the  elements  of  the 
excitation,  the  result  is  a  single  harmonious  disturbance 
which  I  call  an  emotion.  Thus,  the  various  sounds  made 
by  the  instruments  of  an  orchestra  strike  upon  the  ear, 
and  the  result  is  a  peculiar  musical  emotion,  quite  distinct 
from  the  sounds  themselves.  This  emotion  is  essentially 
the  same  thing  as  an  hypothetic  inference,  and  every  hypo 
thetic  inference  involves  the  formation  of  such  an  emotion. 
We  may  say,  therefore,  that  hypothesis  produces  the  sensu 
ous  element  of  thought,  and  induction  the  habitual  element. 
As  for  deduction,  which  adds  nothing  to  the  premises,  but 
only  out  of  the  various  facts  represented  in  the  premises 
selects  one  and  brings  the  attention  down  to  it,  this  may 
be  considered  as  the  logical  formula  for  paying  attention, 
which  is  the  volitional  element  of  thought,  and  corresponds 
to  nervous  discharge  in  the  sphere  of  physiology. 

Another  merit  of  the  distinction  between  induction  and 
hypothesis  is,  that  it  leads  to  a  very  natural  classification 
of  the  sciences  and  of  the  minds  which  prosecute  them. 
What  must  separate  different  kinds  of  scientific  men  more 
than  anything  else  are  the  differences  of  their  techniques. 
We  cannot  expect  men  who  work  with  books  chiefly  to 
have  much  in  common  with  men  whose  lives  are  passed  in 
laboratories.  But,  after  differences  of  this  kind,  the  next 
most  important  are  differences  in  the  modes  of  reasoning. 
Of  the  natural  sciences,  we  have,  first,  the  classificatory 
sciences,  which  are  purely  inductive  —  systematic  botany 


DEDUCTION,    INDUCTION,    HYPOTHESIS          153 

and  zoology,  mineralogy,  and  chemistry.  Then,  we  have 
the  sciences  of  theory,  as  above  explained  —  astronomy, 
pure  physics,  etc.  Then,  we  have  sciences  of  hypothesis  — 
geology,  biology,  etc. 

There  are  many  other  advantages  of  the  distinction  in 
question  which  I  shall  leave  the  reader  to  find  out  by  ex 
perience.  If  he  will  only  take  the  custom  of  considering 
whether  a  given  inference  belongs  to  one  or  other  of  the 
two  forms  of  synthetic  inference  given  on  page  134,  I  can 
promise  him  that  he  will  find  his  advantage  in  it,  in 
various  ways. 


PART  II 
LOVE   AND   CHANCE 


LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

I.    THE   ARCHITECTURE   OF   THEORIES1 

OF  the  fifty  or  hundred  systems  of  philosophy  that  have 
been  advanced  at  different  times  of  the  world's  history, 
perhaps  the  larger  number  have  been,  not  so  much  results 
,  of  historical  evolution,  as  happy  thoughts  which  have  acci- 
dently  occurred  to  their  authors.  An  idea  which  has  been 
found  interesting  and  fruitful  has  been  adopted,  developed, 
and  forced  to  yield  explanations  of  all  sorts  of  phenomena. 
The  English  have  been  particularly  given  to  this  way  of 
philosophizing;  witness,  Hobbes,  Hartley,  Berkeley,  James 
Mill.  Nor  has  it  been  by  any  means  useless  labor;  it 
shows  us  what  the  true  nature  and  value  of  the  ideas  de 
veloped  are,  and  in  that  way  affords  serviceable  materials 
for  philosophy.  Just  as  if  a  man,  being  seized  with  the 
conviction  that  paper  was  a  good  material  to  make  things 
of,  were  to  go  to  work  to  build  a  papier  mdch6  house,  with 
roof  of  roofing-paper,  foundations  of  pasteboard,  windows 
of  paraffined  paper,  chimneys,  bath  tubs,  locks,  etc.,  all  of 
different  forms  of  paper,  his  experiment  would  probably 
afford  valuable  lessons  to  builders,  while  it  would  certainly 
make  a  detestable  house,  so  those  one-idea'd  philosophies 
are  exceedingly  interesting  and  instructive,  and  yet  are  quite 
unsound. 

The  remaining  systems  of  philosophy  have  been  of  the 
nature  of  reforms,  sometimes  amounting  to  radical  revolu 
tions,  suggested  by  certain  difficulties  which  have  been  found 

1  The  Monist,  January,  1891. 

JS7 


I58  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

to  beset  systems  previously  in  vogue;  and  such  ought  cer 
tainly  to  be  in  large  part  the  motive  of  any  new  theory. 
This  is  like  partially  rebuilding  a  house.  The  faults  that 
have  been  committed  are,  first,  that  the  repairs  of  the 
dilapidations  have  generally  not  been  sufficiently  thorough 
going,  and  second,  that  not  sufficient  pains  had  been  taken 
to  bring  the  additions  into  deep  harmony  with  the  really 
sound  parts  of  the  old  structure. 

When  a  man  is  about  to  build  a  house,  what  a  power  of 
thinking  he  has  to  do,  before  he  can  safely  break  ground! 
With  what  pains  he  has  to  excogitate  the  precise  wants  that 
are  to  be  supplied!  What  a  study  to  ascertain  the  most 
available  and  suitable  materials,  to  determine  the  mode 
of  construction  to  which  those  materials  are  best  adapted, 
and  to  answer  a  hundred  such  questions!  Now  without 
riding  the  metaphor  too  far,  I  think  we  may  safely  say 
that  the  studies  preliminary  to  the  construction  of  a  great 
theory  should  be  at  least  as  deliberate  and  thorough  as 
those  that  are  preliminary  to  the  building  of  a  dwelling- 
house. 

That  systems  ought  to  be  constructed  architectonically 
has  been  preached  since  Kant,  but  I  do  not  think  the  full 
import  of  the  maxim  has  by  any  means  been  apprehended. 
What  I  would  recommend  is  that  every  person  who  wishes 
to  form  an  opinion  concerning  fundamental  problems,  should 
first  of  all  make  a  complete  survey  of  human  knowledge, 
should  take  note  of  all  the  valuable  ideas  in  each  branch  of 
science,  should  observe  in  just  what  respect  each  has  been 
successful  and  where  it  has  failed,  in  order  that  in  the  light 
of  the  thorough  acquaintance  so  attained  of  the  available 


THE   ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  159 

materials  for  a  philosophical  theory  and  of  the  nature  and 
strength  of  each,  he  may  proceed  to  the  study  of  what  the 
problem  of  philosophy  consists  in,  and  of  the  proper  way 
of  solving  it.  I  must  not  be  understood  as  endeavoring 
to  state  fully  all  that  these  preparatory  studies  should  em 
brace;  on  the  contrary,  I  purposely  slur  over  many  points, 
in  order  to  give  emphasis  to  one  special  recommendation, 
namely,  to  make  a  systematic  study  of  the  conceptions  out 
of  which  a  philosophical  theory  may  be  built,  in  order  to 
ascertain  what  place  each  conception  may  fitly  occupy  in 
such  a  theory,  and  to  what  uses  it  is  adapted. 

The  adequate  treatment  of  this  single  point  would  fill  a 
volume,  but  I  shall  endeavor  to  illustrate  my  meaning  by 
glancing  at  several  sciences  and  indicating  conceptions  in 
them  serviceable  for  philosophy.  As  to  the  results  to  which 
long  studies  thus  commenced  have  led  me,  I  shall  just  give 
a  hint  at  their  nature. 

We  may  begin  with  dynamics,  —  field  in  our  day  of 
perhaps  the  grandest  conquest  human  science  has  ever 
made,  —  I  mean  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy. 
But  let  us  revert  to  the  first  step  taken  by  modern  scientific 
thought,  —  and  a  great  stride  it  was,  —  the  inauguration  of 
dynamics  by  Galileo.  A  modern  physicist  on  examining 
Galileo's  works  is  surprised  to  find  how  little  experiment 
had  to  do  with  the  establishment  of  the  foundations  of 
mechanics.  His  principal  appeal  is  to  common  sense  and 
il  lume  naturale.  He  always  assumes  that  the  true  theory 
will  be  found  to  be  a  simple  and  natural  one.  And  we  can 
see  why  it  should  indeed  be  so  in  dynamics.  For  instance, 
a  body  left  to  its  own  inertia,  moves  in  a  straight  line,  and 


160  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

a  straight  line  appears  to  us  the  simplest  of  curves.  In 
itself,  no  curve  is  simpler  than  another.  A  system  of 
straight  lines  has  intersections  precisely  corresponding  to 
those  of  a  system  of  like  parabolas  similarly  placed,  or  to 
those  of  any  one  of  an  infinity  of  systems  of  curves.  But 
the  straight  line  appears  to  us  simple,  because,  as  Euclid 
says,  it  lies  evenly  between  its  extremities;  that  is,  because 
viewed  endwise  it  appears  as  a  point.  That  is,  again,  be 
cause  light  moves  in  straight  lines.  Now,  light  moves  in 
straight  lines  because  of  the  part  which  the  straight  line 
plays  in  the  laws  of  dynamics.  Thus  it  is  that  our  minds 
having  been  formed  under  the  influence  of  phenomena 
>  governed  by  the  laws  of  mechanics,  certain  conceptions 
entering  into  those  laws  become  implanted  in  our  minds, 
so  that  we  readily  guess  at  what  the  laws  are.  Without 
such  a  natural  prompting,  having  to  search  blindfold  for 
a  law  which  would  suit  the  phenomena,  our  chance  of  find 
ing  it  would  be  as  one  to  infinity.  The  further  physical 
studies  depart  from  phenomena  which  have  directly  in 
fluenced  the  growth  of  the  mind,  the  less  we  can  expect  to 
find  the  laws  which  govern  them  "  simple,"  that  is,  com 
posed  of  a  few  conceptions  natural  to  our  minds. 

The  researches  of  Galileo,  followed  up  by  Huygens  and 
others,  led  to  those  modern  conceptions  of  Force  and  Law, 
which  have  revolutionized  the  intellectual  world.  The  great 
attention  given  to  mechanics  in  the  seventeenth  century 
soon  so  emphasized  these  conceptions  as  to  give  rise  to  the 
Mechanical  Philosophy,  or  doctrine  that  all  the  phenomena 
of  the  physical  universe  are  to  be  explained  upon  mechani 
cal  principles.  Newton's  great  discovery  imparted  a  new 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  161 

impetus  to  this  tendency.  The  old  notion  that  heat  consists 
in  an  agitation  of  corpuscles  was  now  applied  to  the  ex 
planation  of  the  chief  properties  of  gases.  The  first  sugges 
tion  in  this  direction  was  that  the  pressure  of  gases  is 
explained  by  the  battering  of  the  particles  against  the  walls 
of  the  containing  vessel,  which  explained  Boyle's  law  of  the 
compressibility  of  air.  Later,  the  expansion  of  gases,  Avo- 
gadro's  chemical  law,  the  diffusion  and  viscosity  of  gases, 
and  the  action  of  Crookes's  radiometer  were  shown  to  be 
consequences  of  the  same  kinetical  theory;  but  other  phe 
nomena,  such  as  the  ratio  of  the  specific  heat  at  constant 
volume  to  that  at  constant  pressure,  require  additional 
hypotheses,  which  we  have  little  reason  to  suppose  are 
simple,  so  that  we  find  ourselves  quite  afloat.  In  like 
manner  with  regard  to  light.  That  it  consists  of  vibrations 
was  almost  proved  by  the  phenomena  of  diffraction,  while 
those  of  polarization  showed  the  excursions  of  the  particles 
to  be  perpendicular  to  the  line  of  propagation;  but  the 
phenomena  of  dispersion,  etc.,  require  additional  hypotheses 
which  may  be  very  complicated.  Thus,  the  further  prog 
ress  of  molecular  speculation  appears  quite  uncertain.  If 
hypotheses  are  to  be  tried  haphazard,  or  simply  because 
they  will  suit  certain  phenomena,  it  will  occupy  the  mathe 
matical  physicists  of  the  world  say  half  a  century  on  the 
average  to  bring  each  theory  to  the  test,  and  since  the  num 
ber  of  possible  theories  may  go  up  into  the  trillions,  only 
one  of  which  can  be  true,  we  have  little  prospect  of  making 
further  solid  additions  to  the  subject  in  our  time.  When 
we  come  to  atoms,  the  presumption  in  favor  of  a  simple  law 
seems  very  slender.  There  is  room  for  serious  doubt 


1 62  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

whether  the  fundamental  laws  of  mechanics  hold  good  for 
single  atoms,  and  it  seems  quite  likely  that  they  are  capable 
of  motion  in  more  than  three  dimensions. 

To  find  out  much  more  about  molecules  and  atoms,  we 
must  search  out  a  natural  history  of  laws  of  nature,  which 
may  fulfil  that  function  which  the  presumption  in  favor 
of  simple  laws  fulfilled  in  the  early  days  of  dynamics,  by 
showing  us  what  kind  of  laws  we  have  to  expect  and  by 
answering  such  questions  as  this:  Can  we  with  reasonable 
prospect  of  not  wasting  time,  try  the  supposition  that  atoms 
attract  one  another  inversely  as  the  seventh  power  of  their 
distances,  or  can  we  not?  To  suppose  universal  laws  of 
nature  capable  of  being  apprehended  by  the  mind  and  yet 
having  no  reason  for  their  special  forms,  but  standing  in 
explicable  and  irrational,  is  hardly  a  justifiable  position. 
Uniformities  are  precisely  the  sort  of  facts  that  need  to  be 
accounted  for.  That  a  pitched  coin  should  sometimes  turn 
up  heads  and  sometimes  tails  calls  for  no  particular  ex 
planation;  but  if  it  shows  heads  every  time,  we  wish  to  know 
how  this  result  has  been  brought  about.  Law  is  par  ex 
cellence  the  thing  that  wants  a  reason. 

Now  the  only  possible  way  of  accounting  for  the  laws  of 
nature  and  for  uniformity  in  general  is  to  suppose  them 
results  of  evolution.  This  supposes  them  not  to  be  abso 
lute,  not  to  be  obeyed  precisely.  It  makes  an  element  of 
indeterminacy,  spontaneity,  or  absolute  chance  in  nature. 
Just  as,  when  we  attempt  to  verify  any  physical  law,  we 
find  our  observations  cannot  be  precisely  satisfied  by  it, 
and  rightly  attribute  the  discrepancy  to  errors  of  observa 
tion,  so  we  must  suppose  far  more  minute  discrepancies  to 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  163 

exist  owing  to  the  imperfect  cogency  of  the  law  itself,  to  a 
certain  swerving  of  the  facts  from  any  definite  formula. 

Mr.  Herbert  Spencer  wishes  to  explain  evolution  upon 
mechanical  principles.  This  is  illogical,  for  four  reasons. 
First,  because  the  principle  of  evolution  requires  no  ex 
traneous  cause;  since  the  tendency  to  growth  can  be  sup- 
posed  itself  to  have  grown  from  an  infinitesimal  germ  acci 
dentally  started.  Second,  because  law  ought  more  than 
anything  else  to  be  supposed  a  result  of  evolution.  Third, 
because  exact  law  obviously  never  can  produce  heterogeneity 
out  of  homogeneity;  and  arbitrary  heterogeneity  is  the 
feature  of  the  universe  the  most  manifest  and  characteristic. 
Fourth,  because  the  law  of  the  conservation  of  energy  is 
equivalent  to  the  proposition  that  all  operations  governed 
by  mechanical  laws  are  reversible;  so  that  an  immediate 
corollary  from  it  is  that  growth  is  not  explicable  by  those 
laws,  even  if  they  be  not  violated  in  the  process  of  growth. 
In  short,  Spencer  is  not  a  philosophical  evolutionist,  but 
only  a  half-evolutionist,  —  or,  if  you  will,  only  a  semi- 
Spencerian.  Now  philosophy  requires  thoroughgoing  evo 
lutionism  or  none. 

The  theory  of  Darwin  was  that  evolution  had  been 
brought  about  by  the  action  of  two  factors:  first,  heredity, 
as  a  principle  making  offspring  nearly  resemble  their 
parents,  while  yet  giving  room  for  "  sporting,"  or  accidental 
variations,  —  for  very  slight  variations  often,  for  wider  ones 
rarely;  and,  second,  the  destruction  of  breeds  or  races  that 
are  unable  to  keep  the  birth  rate  up  to  the  death  rate. 
This  Darwinian  principle  is  plainly  capable  of  great  gen 
eralization.  Wherever  there  are  large  numbers  of  objects, 


1 64  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

having  a  tendency  to  retain  certain  characters  unaltered, 
this  tendency,  however,  not  being  absolute  but  giving  room 
for  chance  variations,  then,  if  the  amount  of  variation  is 
absolutely  limited  in  certain  directions  by  the  destruction 
of  everything  which  reaches  those  limits,  there  will  be  a 
gradual  tendency  to  change  in  directions  of  departure 
from  them.  Thus,  if  a  million  players  sit  down  to  bet  at 
an  even  game,  since  one  after  another  will  get  ruined,  the 
average  wealth  of  those  who  remain  will  perpetually  in 
crease.  Here  is  indubitably  a  genuine  formula  of  possible 
evolution,  whether  its  operation  accounts  for  much  or  little 
in  the  development  of  animal  and  vegetable  species. 

The  Lamarckian  theory  also  supposes  that  the  develop 
ment  of  species  has  taken  place  by  a  long  series  of  in 
sensible  changes,  but  it  supposes  that  those  changes  have 
taken  place  during  the  lives  of  the  individuals,  in  conse 
quence  of  effort  and  exercise,  and  that  reproduction  plays 
no  part  in  the  process  except  in  preserving  these  modifica 
tions.  Thus,  the  Lamarckian  theory  only  explains  the 
development  of  characters  for  which  individuals  strive,  while 
the  Darwinian  theory  only  explains  the  production  of  char 
acters  really  beneficial  to  the  race,  though  these  may  be 
fatal  to  individuals.2  But  more  broadly  and  philosophically 
conceived,  Darwinian  evolution  is  evolution  by  the  opera 
tion  of  chance,  and  the  destruction  of  bad  results,  while 
Lamarckian  evolution  is  evolution  by  the  effect  of  habit 
and  effort. 

A  third  theory  of  evolution  is  that  of  Mr.  Clarence  King. 

2  The  neo-Darwinian,  Weismann,  has  shown  that  mortality  would 
almost  necessarily  result  from  the  action  of  the  Darwinian  principle. 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  165 

The  testimony  of  monuments  and  of  rocks  is  that  species 
are  unmodified  or  scarcely  modified,  under  ordinary  cir 
cumstances,  but  are  rapidly  altered  after  cataclysms  or 
rapid  geological  changes.  Under  novel  circumstances,  we 
often  see  animals  and  plants  sporting  excessively  in  repro 
duction,  and  sometimes  even  undergoing  transformations 
during  individual  life,  phenomena  no  doubt  due  partly  to 
the  enfeeblement  of  vitality  from  the  breaking  up  of  hab 
itual  modes  of  life,  partly  to  changed  food,  partly  to  direct 
specific  influence  of  the  element  in  which  the  organism  is 
immersed.  If  evolution  has  been  brought  about  in  this 
way,  not  only  have  its  single  steps  not  been  insensible,  as 
both  Darwinians  and  Lamarckians  suppose,  but  they  are 
furthermore  neither  haphazard  on  the  one  hand,  nor  yet 
determined  by  an  inward  striving  on  the  other,  but  on  the 
contrary  are  effects  of  the  changed  environment,  and  have 
a  positive  general  tendency  to  adapt  the  organism  to  that 

'  environment,  since  variation  will  particularly  affect  organs 
at  once  enfeebled  and  stimulated.  This  mode  of  evolution, 
by  external  forces  and  the  breaking  up  of  habits,  seems  to 
be  called  for  by  some  of  the  broadest  and  most  important 
facts  of  biology  and  paleontology;  while  it  certainly  has 

,  been  the  chief  factor  in  the  historical  evolution  of  institu 
tions  as  in  that  of  ideas;  and  cannot  possibly  be  refused 
a  very  prominent  place  in  the  process  of  evolution  of  the 
universe  in  general. 

Passing  to  psychology,  we  find  the  elementary  phenomena 
of  mind  fall  into  three  categories.  First,  we  have  Feelings, 
comprising  all  that  is  immediately  present,  such  as  pain, 
blue,  cheerfulness,  the  feeling  that  arises  when  we  contem- 


1 66  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

plate  a  consistent  theory,  etc.  A  feeling  is  a  state  of  mind 
having  its  own  living  quality,  independent  of  any  other 
state  of  mind.  Or,  a  feeling  is  an  element  of  consciousness 
which  might  conceivably  override  every  other  state  until  it 
monopolized  the  mind,  although  such  a  rudimentary  state 
cannot  actually  be  realized,  and  would  not  properly  be 
consciousness.  Still,  it  is  conceivable,  or  supposable,  that 
the  quality  of  blue  should  usurp  the  whole  mind,  to  the 
exclusion  of  the  ideas  of  shape,  extension,  contrast,  com 
mencement  and  cessation,  and  all  other  ideas,  whatsoever. 
A  feeling  is  necessarily  perfectly  simple,  in  itself,  for  if  it 
had  parts  these  would  also  be  in  the  mind,  whenever  the 
whole  was  present,  and  thus  the  whole  could  not  monopolize 
the  mind.3 

Besides  Feelings,  we  have  Sensations  of  reaction;  as 
when  a  person  blindfold  suddenly  runs  against  a  post,  when 
we  make  a  muscular  effort,  or  when  any  feeling  gives  way 
to  a  new  feeling.  Suppose  I  had  nothing  in  my  mind  but 
a  feeling  of  blue,  which  were  suddenly  to  give  place  to  a 
feeling  of  red;  then,  at  the  instant  of  transition  there  would 
be  a  shock,  a  sense  of  reaction,  my  blue  life  being  trans 
muted  into  red  life.  If  I  were  further  endowed  with  a 
memory,  that  sense  would  continue  for  some  time,  and  there 
would  also  be  a  peculiar  feeling  or  sentiment  connected 
with  it.  This  last  feeling  might  endure  (conceivably  I 
mean)  after  the  memory  of  the  occurrence  and  the  feelings 
of  blue  and  red  had  passed  away.  But  the  sensation  of 
reaction  cannot  exist  except  in  the  actual  presence  of  the 

3  A  feeling  may  certainly  be  compound,  but  only  in  virtue  of  a  per 
ception  which  is  not  that  feeling  nor  any  feeling  at  all. 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  167 

two  feelings  blue  and  red  to  which  it  relates.  Wherever 
we  have  two  feelings  and  pay  attention  to  a  relation  be 
tween  them  of  whatever  kind,  there  is  the  sensation  of 
which  I  am  speaking.  But  the  sense  of  action  and  reaction 
has  two  types:  it  may  either  be  a  perception  of  relation 
between  two  ideas,  or  it  may  be  a  sense  of  action  and  re 
action  between  feeling  and  something  out  of  feeling.  And 
this  sense  of  external  reaction  again  has  two  forms;  for  it 
is  either  a  sense  of  something  happening  to  us,  by  no  act  of 
ours,  we  being  passive  in  the  matter,  or  it  is  a  sense  of  re 
sistance,  that  is,  of  our  expending  feeling  upon  something 
without.  The  sense  of  reaction  is  thus  a  sense  of  connection 
or  comparison  between  feelings,  either,  A,  between  one 
feeling  and  another,  or  B,  between  feeling  and  its  absence 
or  lower  degree;  and  under  B  we  have,  First,  the  sense  of 
the  access  of  feeling,  and  Second,  the  sense  of  remission  of 
feeling. 

Very  different  both  from  feelings  and  from  reaction- 
sensations  or  disturbances  of  feeling  are  general  conceptions. 
When  we  think,  we  are  conscious  that  a  connection  between 
feelings  is  determined  by  a  general  rule,  we  are  aware  of 
being  governed  by  a  habit.  Intellectual  power  is  nothing 
but  facility  in  taking  habits  and  in  following  them  in  cases 
essentially  analogous  to,  but  in  non-essentials  widely  re 
mote  from,  the  normal  cases  of  connections  of  feelings  under 
which  those  habits  were  formed. 

The  one  primary  and  fundamental  law  of  mental  action 
consists  in  a  tendency  to  generalization.  Feeling  tends  to 
spread;  connections  between  feelings  awaken  feelings; 
neighboring  feelings  become  assimilated;  ideas  are  apt  to 


1 68  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

reproduce  themselves.  These  are  so  many  formulations  of 
the  one  law  of  the  growth  of  mind.  When  a  disturbance 
of  feeling  takes  place,  we  have  a  consciousness  of  gain,  the 
gain  of  experience;  and  a  new  disturbance  will  be  apt  to 
assimilate  itself  to  the  one  that  preceded  it.  Feelings,  by 
being  excited,  become  more  easily  excited,  especially  in  the 
ways  in  which  they  have  previously  been  excited.  The  con 
sciousness  of  such  a  habit  constitutes  a  general  conception. 

The  cloudiness  of  psychological  notions  may  be  corrected 
by  connecting  them  with  physiological  conceptions.  Feel 
ing  may  be  supposed  to  exist,  wherever  a  nerve-cell  is  in  an 
excited  condition.  The  disturbance  of  feeling,  or  sense  of 
reaction,  accompanies  the  transmission  of  disturbance  be 
tween  nerve-cells  or  from  a  nerve-cell  to  a  muscle-cell  or 
the  external  stimulation  of  a  nerve-cell.  General  concep 
tions  arise  upon  the  formation  of  habits  in  the  nerve-matter, 
which  are  molecular  changes  consequent  upon  its  activity 
and  probably  connected  with  its  nutrition. 

The  law  of  habit  exhibits  a  striking  contrast  to  all  physi 
cal  laws  in  the  character  of  its  commands.  A  physical  law 
is  absolute.  What  it  requires  is  an  exact  relation.  Thus, 
a  physical  force  introduces  into  a  motion  a  component 
motion  to  be  combined  with  the  rest  by  the  parallelogram 
of  forces;  but  the  component  motion  must  actually  take 
place  exactly  as  required  by  the  law  of  force.  On  the 
other  hand,  no  exact  conformity  is  required  by  the  mental 
law.  Nay,  exact  conformity  would  be  in  downright  con 
flict  with  the  law;  since  it  would  instantly  crystallize  thought 
and  prevent  all  further  formation  of  habit.  The  law  of 
mind  only  makes  a  given  feeling  more  likely  to  arise.  It 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  169 

thus  resembles  the  "  non-conservative  "  forces  of  physics, 
such  as  viscosity  and  the  like,  which  are  due  to  statistical 
uniformities  in  the  chance  encounters  of  trillions  of  mole 
cules. 

The  old  dualistic  notion  of  mind  and  matter,  so  prominent 
in  Cartesianism,  as  two  radically  different  kinds  of  sub 
stance,  will  hardly  find  defenders  to-day.  Rejecting  this, 
we  are  driven  to  some  form  of  hylopathy,  otherwise  called 
monism.  Then  the  question  arises  whether  physical  laws 
on  the  one  hand,  and  the  psychical  law  on  the  other  are  to 
be  taken  — 

(A)  as  independent,  a  doctrine  often  called  monism,  but 
which  I  would  name  neutralism;  or, 

(B)  the  psychical  law  as  derived  and  special,  the  physi 
cal  law  alone  as  primordial,  which  is  materialism;  or, 

(C)  the  physical  law  as  derived  and  special,  the  psychical 
law  alone  as  primordial,  which  is  idealism. 

The  materialistic  doctrine  seems  to  me  quite  as  repugnant 
to  scientific  logic  as  to  common  sense;  since  it  requires  us 
to  suppose  that  a  certain  kind  of  mechanism  will  feel,  which 
would  be  a  hypothesis  absolutely  irreducible  to  reason,  — 
an  ultimate,  inexplicable  regularity;  while  the  only  possible 
justification  of  any  theory  is  that  it  should  make  things 
clear  and  reasonable. 

Neutralism  is  sufficiently  condemned  by  the  logical  maxim 
known  as  Ockham's  razor,  i.e.,  that  not  more  independent 
elements  are  to  be  supposed  than  necessary.  By  placing 
the  inward  and  outward  aspects  of  substance  on  a  par,  it 
seems  to  render  both  primordial. 

The  one  intelligible  theory  of  the  universe  is  that  of  ob- 


1 7o  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

jective  idealism,  that  matter  is  effete  mind,  inveterate  habits 
becoming  physical  laws.  But  before  this  can  be  accepted 
it  must  show  itself  capable  of  explaining  the  tridimension- 
ality  of  space,  the  laws  of  motion,  and  the  general  charac 
teristics  of  the  universe,  with  mathematical  clearness  and 
precision;  for  no  less  should  be  demanded  of  every 
Philosophy. 

Modern  mathematics  is  replete  with  ideas  which  may  be 
applied  to  philosophy.  I  can  only  notice  one  or  two.  The 
manner  in  which  mathematicians  generalize  is  very  instruc 
tive.  Thus,  painters  are  accustomed  to  think  of  a  picture 


as  consisting  geometrically  of  the  intersections  of  its  plane 
by  rays  of  light  from  the  natural  objects  to  the  eye.  But 
geometers  use  a  generalized  perspective.*  For  instance 
in  the  figure  let  0  be  the  eye,  let  A  B  C  D  E  be  the  edge- 

4  [The  reader  will  find  further  light  on  the  following  illustration  in 
any  text-book  of  projective  geometry,  e.g.,  Reye,  Geometry  of  Position, 
I,  pp.  17-24,  or  Encyc.  Britannka,  XI,  p.  689.! 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF   THEORIES  171 

wise  view  of  any  plane,  and  let  a  f  e  D  c  be  the  edgewise 
view  of  another  plane.  The  geometers  draw  rays 
through  O  cutting  both  these  planes,  and  treat  the  points 
of  intersection  of  each  ray  with  one  plane  as  representing 
the  point  of  intersection  of  the  same  ray  with  the  other 
plane.  Thus,  e  represents  E,  in  the  painter's  way.  D 
represents  itself.  C  is  represented  by  c,  which  is  further 
from  the  eye;  and  A  is  represented  by  a  which  is  on  the 
other  side  of  the  eye.  Such  generalization  is  not  bound 
down  to  sensuous  images.  Further,  according  to  this  mode 
of  representation  every  point  on  one  plane  represents  a 
point  on  the  other,  and  every  point  on  the  latter  is  repre 
sented  by  a  point  on  the  former.  But  how  about  the  point 
/  which  is  in  a  direction  from  O  parallel  to  the  represented 
plane,  and  how  about  the  point  B  which  is  in  a  direction 
parallel  to  the  representing  plane?  Some  will  say  that 
these  are  exceptions;  but  modern  mathematics  does  not 
allow  exceptions  which  can  be  annulled  by  generalization.5 
As  a  point  moves  from  C  to  D  and  thence  to  E  and  off 
toward  infinity,  the  corresponding  point  on  the  other  plane 
moves  from  c  to  D  and  thence  to  e  and  toward  /.  But  this 
second  point  can  pass  through  f  to  a;  and  when  it  is  there 
the  first  point  has  arrived  at  A .  We  therefore  say  that  the 
first  point  has  passed  through  infinity,  and  that  every  line 
joins  in  to  itself  somewhat  like  an  oval.  Geometers  talk  of 


5  [A  more  familiar  example  of  this  is  the  introduction  of  irrational  or 
surd  numbers  like  V*-  After  it  was  proved  that  no  ratio  of  two  integers 
could  possibly  equal  V5  the  idea  of  number  was  generalized  to  include  the 
latter.  Fractions  and  the  so-called  imaginary  numbers  illustrate  the  same 
process  of  generalization  for  the  sake  of  making  certain  operations  (i.e. 
division  and  finding  the  root)  continuously  applicable. 


1 72  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

the  parts  of  lines  at  an  infinite  distance  as  points.    This  is 
a  kind  of  generalization  very  efficient  in  mathematics. 

Modern  views  of  measurement  have  a  philosophical 
aspect.  There  is  an  indefinite  number  of  systems  of  measur 
ing  along  a  line;  thus,  a  perspective  representation  of  a 
scale  on  one  line  may  be  taken  to  measure  another,  although 
of  course  such  measurements  will  not  agree  with  what  we 
call  the  distances  of  points  on  the  latter  line.  To  establish 
a  system  of  measurement  on  a  line  we  must  assign  a  distinct 
number  to  each  point  of  it,  and  for  this  purpose  we  shall 
plainly  have  to  suppose  the  numbers  carried  out  into  an 
infinite  number  of  places  of  decimals.  These  numbers 
must  be  ranged  along  the  line  in  unbroken  sequence. 
Further,  in  order  that  such  a  scale  of  numbers  should  be 
of  any  use,  it  must  be  capable  of  being  shifted  into  new 
positions,  each  number  continuing  to  be  attached  to  a  single 
distinct  point.  Now  it  is  found  that  if  this  is  true  for 
"  imaginary  "  as  well  as  for  real  points  (an  expression 
which  I  cannot  stop  to  elucidate),  any  such  shifting  will 
necessarily  leave  two  numbers  attached  to  the  same  points 
as  before.  So  that  when  the  scale  is  moved  over  the  line 
by  any  continuous  series  of  shiftings  of  one  kind,  there  are 
two  points  which  no1  numbers  on  the  scale  can  ever  reach, 
except  the  numbers  fixed  there.  This  pair  of  points,  thus 
unattainable  in  measurement,  is  called  the  Absolute.  These 
two  points  may  be  distinct  and  real,  or  they  may  coincide, 
or  they  may  be  both  imaginary.  As  an  example  of  a  linear 
quantity  with  a  double  absolute  we  may  take  probability, 
which  ranges  from  an  unattainable  absolute  certainty 
against  a  proposition  to  an  equally  unattainable  absolute 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  173 

certainty  for  it.  A  line,  according  to  ordinary  notions,  we 
have  seen  is  a  linear  quantity  where  the  two  points  at  infinity 
coincide.  A  velocity  is  another  example.  A  train  going  with 
infinite  velocity  from  Chicago  to  New  York  would  be  at  all 
the  points  on  the  line  at  the  very  same  instant,  and  if  the 
time  of  transit  were  reduced  to  less  than  nothing  it  would  be 
moving  in  the  other  direction.  An  angle  is  a  familiar  ex 
ample  of  a  mode  of  magnitude  with  no  real  immeasurable 
values.  One  of  the  questions  philosophy  has  to  consider 
is  whether  the  development  of  the  universe  is  like  the  in 
crease  of  an  angle,  so  that  it  proceeds  forever  without  tend 
ing  toward  anything  unattained,  which  I  take  to  be  the 
Epicurean  view,  or  whether  the  universe  sprang  from  a 
chaos  in  the  infinitely  distant  past  to  tend  toward  some 
thing  different  in  the  infinitely  distant  future,  or  whether 
the  universe  sprang  from  nothing  in  the  past  to  go  on  in 
definitely  toward  a  point  in  the  infinitely  distant  future, 
which,  were  it  attained,  would  be  the  mere  nothing  from 
which  it  set  out. 

The  doctrine  of  the  absolute  applied  to  space  comes  to 
this,  that  either  — 

First,  space  is,  as  Euclid  teaches,  both  unlimited  and 
immeasurable,  so  that  the  infinitely  distant  parts  of  any 
plane  seen  in  perspective  appear  as  a  straight  line,  in  which 
case  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  amounts  to 
1 80°;  or, 

Second,  space  is  immeasurable  but  limited,  so  that  the 
infinitely  distant  parts  of  any  plane  seen  in  perspective 
appear  as  a  circle,  beyond  which  all  is  blackness,  and  in 
this  case  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of  a  triangle  is  less 


i74  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

than  1 80°  by  an  amount  proportional  to  the  area  of  the 
triangle;  or, 

Third,  space  is  unlimited  but  finite,  (like  the  surface  of 
a  sphere),  so  that  it  has  no  infinitely  distant  parts;  but  a 
finite  journey  along  any  straight  line  would  bring  one  back 
to  his  original  position,  and  looking  off  with  an  unobstructed 
view  one  would  see  the  back  of  his  own  head  enormously 
magnified,  in  which  case  the  sum  of  the  three  angles  of  a 
triangle  exceeds  180°  by  an  amount  proportional  to  the 
area. 

Which  of  these  three  hypotheses  is  true  we  know  not. 
The  largest  triangles  we  can  measure  are  such  as  have  the 
earth's  orbit  for  base,  and  the  distance  of  a  fixed  star  for 
altitude.  The  angular  magnitude  resulting  from  subtract 
ing  the  sum  of  the  two  angles  at  the  base  of  such  a  triangle 
from  1 80°  is  called  the  star's  parallax.  The  parallaxes  of 
only  about  forty  stars  have  been  measured  as  yet.  Two 
of  them  come  out  negative,  that  of  Added  (a  Cycni),  a 
star  of  magnitude  ij,  which  is  —  o."o82,  according  to  C.  A. 
F.  Peters,  and  that  of  a  star  of  magnitude  yf ,  known  as 
Piazzi  III  422,  which  is  —  o."o45,  according  to  R.  S.  Ball. 
But  these  negative  parallaxes  are  undoubtedly  to  be  at 
tributed  to  errors  of  observation;  for  the  probable  error  of 
such  a  determination  is  about  =*=  o."o75,  and  it  would  be 
strange  indeed  if  we  were  to  be  able  to  see,  as  it  were, 
more  than  half  way  round  space,  without  being  able  to  see 
stars  with  larger  negative  parallaxes.  Indeed,  the  very 
fact  that  of  all  the  parallaxes  measured  only  two  come  out 
negative  would  be  a  strong  argument  that  the  smallest 
parallaxes  really  amount  to  +  o."i,  were  it  not  for  the  re- 


THE   ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  I?s 

flection  that  the  publication  of  other  negative  parallaxes 
may  have  been  suppressed.  I  think  we  may  feel  confident 
that  the  parallax  of  the  furthest  star  lies  somewhere  between 
—  o/'o5  and  +  o." 1 5,  and  within  another  century  our  grand 
children  will  surely  know  whether  the  three  angles  of  a 
triangle  are  greater  or  less  than  180°,  —  that  they  are 
exactly  that  amount  is  what  nobody  ever  can  be  justified  in 
concluding.  It  is  true  that  according  to  the  axioms  of 
geometry  the  sum  of  the  three  sides  of  a  triangle  are  pre 
cisely  1 80°;  but  these  axioms  are  now  exploded,  and 
geometers  confess  that  they,  as  geometers,  know  not  the 
slightest  reason  for  supposing  them  to  be  precisely  true. 
They  are  expressions  of  our  inborn  conception  of  space, 
and  as  such  are  entitled  to  credit,  so  far  as  their  truth  could 
have  influenced  the  formation  of  the  mind.  But  that  af 
fords  not  the  slightest  reason  for  supposing  them  exact. 

Now,  metaphysics  has  always  been  the  ape  of  mathe 
matics.  Geometry  suggested  the  idea  of  a  demonstrative 
system  of  absolutely  certain  philosophical  principles;  and 
the  ideas  of  the  metaphysicians  have  at  all  times  been  in 
large  part  drawn  from  mathematics.  The  metaphysical 
axioms  are  imitations  of  the  geometrical  axioms;  and  now 
that  the  latter  have  been  thrown  overboard,  without  doubt 
the  former  will  be  sent  after  them.  It  is  evident,  for  in 
stance,  that  we  can  have  no  reason  to  think  that  every 
phenomenon  in  all  its  minutest  details  is  precisely  deter 
mined  by  law.  That  there  is  an  arbitrary  element  in  the 
universe  we  see,  —  namely,  its  variety.  This  variety  must 
be  attributed  to  spontaneity  in  some  form. 

Had  I  more  space,  I  now  ought  to  show  how  important 


176  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

for  philosophy  is  the  mathematical  conception  of  continuity. 
Most  of  what  is  true  in  Hegel  is  a  darkling  glimmer  of  a 
conception  which  the  mathematicians  had  long  before  made 
pretty  clear,  and  which  recent  researches  have  still  further 
illustrated. 

Among  the  many  principles  of  Logic  which  find  their 
application  in  Philosophy,  I  can  here  only  mention  one. 
Three  conceptions  are  perpetually  turning  up  at  every  point 
in  every  theory  of  logic,  and  in  the  most  rounded  systems 
they  occur  in  connection  with  one  another.  They  are  con 
ceptions  so  very  broad  and  consequently  indefinite  that  they 
are  hard  to  seize  and  may  be  easily  overlooked.  I  call 
them  the  conceptions  of  First,  Second,  Third.  First  is  the 
conception  of  being  or  existing  independent  of  anything  else. 
Second  is  the  conception  of  being  relative  to,  the  concep 
tion  of  reaction  with,  something  else.  Third  is  the  con 
ception  of  mediation,  whereby  a  first  and  second  are  brought 
into  relation.  To  illustrate  these  ideas,  I  will  show  how 
they  enter  into  those  we  have  been  considering.  The  origin 
of  things,  considered  not  as  leading  to  anything,  but  in 
itself,  contains  the  idea  of  First,  the  end  of  things  that  of 
Second,  the  process  mediating  between  them  that  of  Third. 
A  philosophy  which  emphasizes  the  idea  of  the  One,  is 
generally  a  dualistic  philosophy  in  which  the  conception 
of  Second  receives  exaggerated  attention;  for  this  One 
(though  of  course  involving  the  idea  of  First)  is  always 
the  other  of  a  manifold  which  is  not  one.  The  idea  of  the 
Many,  because  variety  is  arbitrariness  and  arbitrariness  is 
repudiation  of  any  Secondness,  has  for  its  principal  com 
ponent  the  conception  of  First.  In  psychology  Feeling  is 


THE    ARCHITECTURE    OF    THEORIES  177 

First,  Sense  of  reaction  Second,  General  conception  Third, 
or  mediation.  In  biology,  the  idea  of  arbitrary  sporting  is 
First,  heredity  is  Second,  the  process  whereby  the  accidental 
characters  become  fixed  is  Third.  Chance  is  First,  Law 
is  Second,  the  tendency  to  take  habits  is  Third.  Mind  is 
First,  Matter  is  Second,  Evolution  is  Third. 

Such  are  the  materials  out  of  which  chiefly  a  philosophical 
theory  ought  to  be  built,  in  order  to  represent  the  state  of 
knowledge  to  which  the  nineteenth  century  has  brought  us. 
Without  going  into  other  important  questions  of  philoso 
phical  architectonic,  we  can  readily  foresee  what  sort  of 
a  metaphysics  would  appropriately  be  constructed  from 
those  conceptions.  Like  some  of  the  most  ancient  and 
some  of  the  most  recent  speculations  it  would  be  a  Cosmo- 
gonic  Philosophy.  It  would  suppose  that  in  the  beginning, 
—  infinitely  remote,  —  there  was  a  chaos  of  unpersonalized 
feeling,  which  being  without  connection  or  regularity  would 
properly  be  without  existence.  This  feeling,  sporting  here 
and  there  in  pure  arbitrariness,  would  have  started  the  germ 
of  a  generalizing  tendency.  Its  other  sportings  would  be 
evanescent,  but  this  would  have  a  growing  virtue.  Thus, 
the  tendency  to  habit  would  be  started;  and  from  this  with 
the  other  principles  of  evolution  all  the  regularities  of  the 
universe  would  be  evolved.  At  any  time,  however,  an 
element  of  pure  chance  survives  and  will  remain  until  the 
world  becomes  an  absolutely  perfect,  rational,  and  sym 
metrical  system,  in  which  mind  is  at  last  crystallized  in  the 
infinitely  distant  future. 

That  idea  has  been  worked  out  by  me  with  elaboration. 
It  accounts  for  the  main  features  of  the  universe  as  we 


1 78  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

know  it,  —  the  characters  of  time,  space,  matter,  force, 
gravitation,  electricity,  etc.  It  predicts  many  more  things 
which  new  observations  can  alone  bring  to  the  test.  May 
some  future  student  go  over  this  ground  again,  and  have  the 
leisure  to  give  his  results  to  the  world. 


II.    THE  DOCTRINE  OF  NECESSITY  EXAMINED  l 

IN  The  Monist  for  January,  1891,  I  endeavored  to  show 
what  elementary  ideas  ought  to  enter  into  our  view  of  the 
universe.  I  may  mention  that  on  those  considerations  I 
had  already  grounded  a  cosmical  theory,  and  from  it  had 
deduced  a  considerable  number  of  consequences  capable 
of  being  compared  with  experience.  This  comparison  is 
now  in  progress,  but  under  existing  circumstances  must 
occupy  many  years. 

I  propose  here  to  examine  the  common  belief  that  every 
single  fact  in  the  universe  is  precisely  determined  by  law. 
It  must  not  be  supposed  that  this  is  a  doctrine  accepted 
everywhere  and  at  all  times  by  all  rational  men.  Its  first 
advocate  appears  to  have  been  Democritus,  the  atomist,  who 
was  led  to  it,  as  we  are  informed,  by  reflecting  upon  the 
"  impenetrability,  translation,  and  impact  of  matter 
(avTLTViria  Kal  (fropa  /cat  7r\r)yrj  rrjs  v\r)s)."  That  is  to 
say,  having  restricted  his  attention  to  a  field  where  no  influ 
ence  other  than  mechanical  constraint  could  possibly  come 
before  his  notice,  he  straightway  jumped  to  the  conclusion 
that  throughout  the  universe  that  was  the  sole  principle  of 
action,  —  a  style  of  reasoning  so  usual  in  our  day  with  men 
not  unreflecting  as  to  be  more  than  excusable  in  the  in 
fancy  of  thought.  But  Epicurus,  in  revising  the  atomic 
doctrine  and  repairing  its  defences,  found  himself  obliged 

1  The  Monist,  April,  1892. 

179 


1 8o  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

to  suppose  that  atoms  swerve  from  their  courses  by  spon 
taneous  chance;  and  thereby  he  conferred  upon  the  theory 
life  and  entelechy.  For  we  now  see  clearly  that  the  pe 
culiar  function  of  the  molecular  hypothesis  in  physics  is 
to  open  an  entry  for  the  calculus  of  probabilities.  Already, 
the  prince  of  philosophers  had  repeatedly  and  emphatically 
condemned  the  dictum  of  Democritus  (especially  in  the 
"  Physics,"  Book  II,  chapters  iv,  v,  vi),  holding  that  events 
come  to  pass  in  three  ways,  namely,  (i)  by  external  com 
pulsion,  or  the  action  of  efficient  causes,  (2)  by  virtue  of 
an  inward  nature,  or  the  influence  of  final  causes,  and  (3) 
irregularly  without  definite  cause,  but  just  by  absolute 
chance;  and  this  doctrine  is  of  the  inmost  essence  of  Aris- 
totelianism.  It  affords,  at  any  rate,  a  valuable  enumeration 
of  the  possible  ways  in  which  anything  can  be  supposed 
to  have  come  about.  The  freedom  of  the  will,  too,  was 
admitted  both  by  Aristotle  and  by  Epicurus.  But  the  Stoa, 
which  in  every  department  seized  upon  the  most  tangible, 
hard,  and  lifeless  element,  and  blindly  denied  the  existence 
of  every  other,  which,  for  example,  impugned  the  validity 
of  the  inductive  method  and  wished  to  fill  its  place  with  the 
reductio  ad  absurdum,  very  naturally  became  the  one  school 
of  ancient  philosophy  to  stand  by  a  strict  necessitarianism, 
thus  returning  to  a  single  principle  of  Democritus  that 
Epicurus  had  been  unable  to  swallow.  Necessitarianism 
and  materialism  with  the  Stoics  went  hand  in  hand,  as  by 
affinity  they  should.  At  the  revival  of  learning,  Stoicism 
met  with  considerable  favor,  partly  because  it  departed 
just  enough  from  Aristotle  to  give  it  the  spice  of  novelty, 
and  partly  because  its  superficialities  well  adapted  it  for 


DOCTRINE    OF   NECESSITY    EXAMINED  181 

acceptance  by  students  of  literature  and  art  who  wanted 
their  philosophy  drawn  mild.  Afterwards,  the  great  dis 
coveries  in  mechanics  inspired  the  hope  that  mechanical 
principles  might  suffice  to  explain  the  universe;  and  though 
without  logical  justification,  this  hope  has  since  been  con 
tinually  stimulated  by  subsequent  advances  in  physics. 
Nevertheless,  the  doctrine  was  in  too  evident  conflict  with 
the  freedom  of  the  will  and  with  miracles  to  be  generally 
acceptable,  at  first.  But  meantime  there  arose  that  most 
widely  spread  of  philosophical  blunders,  the  notion  that 
associationalism  belongs  intrinsically  to  the  materialistic 
family  of  doctrines;  and  thus  was  evolved  the  theory  of 
motives;  and  libertarianism  became  weakened.  At  present, 
historical  criticism  has  almost  exploded  the  miracles,  great 
and  small;  so  that  the  doctrine  of  necessity  has  never  been 
in  so  great  vogue  as  now. 

The  proposition  in  question  is  that  the  state  of  things 
existing  at  any  time,  together  with  certain  immutable  laws, 
completely  determine  the  state  of  things  at  every  other  time 
(for  a  limitation  to  future  time  is  indefensible).  Thus, 
given  the  state  of  the  universe  in  the  original  nebula,  and 
given  the  laws  of  mechanics,  a  sufficiently  powerful  mind 
could  deduce  from  these  data  the  precise  form  of  every 
curlicue  of  every  letter  I  am  now  writing. 

Whoever  holds  that  every  act  of  the  will  as  well  as  every 
idea  of  the  mind  is  under  the  rigid  governance  of  a  neces 
sity  co-ordinated  with  that  of  the  physical  world,  will  logi 
cally  be  carried  to  the  proposition  that  minds  are  part  of 
the  physical  world  in  such  a  sense  that  the  laws  of  me 
chanics  determine  everything  that  happens  according  to 


182  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

immutable  attractions  and  repulsions.  In  that  case,  that 
instantaneous  state  of  things  from  which  every  other  state 
of  things  is  calculable  consists  in  the  positions  and  velocities 
of  all  the  particles  at  any  instant.  This,  the  usual  and 
most  logical  form  of  necessitarianism,  is  called  the  mechani 
cal  philosophy. 

When  I  have  asked  thinking  men  what  reason  they  had 
to  believe  that  every  fact  in  the  universe  is  precisely  de 
termined  by  law,  the  first  answer  has  usually  been  that 
the  proposition  is  a  "  presupposition  "  or  postulate  of  scien 
tific  reasoning.  Well,  if  that  is  the  best  that  can  be  said 
for  it,  the  belief  is  doomed.  Suppose  it  be  "  postulated  ": 
that  does  not  make  it  true,  nor  so  much  as  afford  the  slight 
est  rational  motive  for  yielding  it  any  credence.  It  is  as 
if  a  man  should  come  to  borrow  money,  and  when  asked 
for  his  security,  should  reply  he  "  postulated  "  the  loan. 
To  "  postulate  "  a  proposition  is  no  more  than  to  hope  it  is 
true.  There  are,  indeed,  practical  emergencies  in  which 
we  act  upon  assumptions  of  certain  propositions  as  true, 
because  if  they  are  not  so,  it  can  make  no  difference  how 
we  act.  But  all  such  propositions  I  take  to  be  hypotheses 
of  individual  facts.  For  it  is  manifest  that  no  universal 
principle  can  in  its  universality  be  comprised  in  a  special 
case  or  can  be  requisite  for  the  validity  of  any  ordinary 
inference.  To  say,  for  instance,  that  the  demonstration 
by  Archimedes  of  the  property  of  the  lever  would  fall  to 
the  ground  if  men  were  endowed  with  free-will,  is  extrava 
gant;  yet  this  is  implied  by  those  who  make  a  proposition 
incompatible  with  the  freedom  of  the  will  the  postulate  of 
all  inference.  Considering,  too,  that  the  conclusions  of 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  183 

science  make  no  pretence  to  being  more  than  probable,  and 
considering  that  a  probable  inference  can  at  most  only 
suppose  something  to  be  most  frequently,  or  otherwise 
approximately,  true,  but  never  that  anything  is  precisely 
true  without  exception  throughout  the  universe,  we  see  how 
far  this  proposition  in  truth  is  from  being  so  postulated. 

But  the  whole  notion  of  a  postulate  being  involved  in 
reasoning  appertains  to  a  by-gone  and  false  conception  of 
logic.  Non-deductive,  or  ampliative  inference,  is  of  three 
kinds:  induction,  hypothesis,  and  analogy.  If  there  be 
any  other  modes,  they  must  be  extremely  unusual  and 
highly  complicated,  and  may  be  assumed  with  little  doubt 
to  be  of  the  same  nature  as  those  enumerated.  For  induc 
tion,  hypothesis,  and  analogy,  as  far  as  their  ampliative 
character  goes,  that  is,  so  far  as  they  conclude  something 
not  implied  in  the  premises,  depend  upon  one  principle  and 
involve  the  same  procedure.  All  are  essentially  inferences 
from  sampling.  Suppose  a  ship  arrives  at  Liverpool  laden 
with  wheat  in  bulk.  Suppose  that  by  some  machinery  the 
whole  cargo  be  stirred  up  with  great  thoroughness.  Sup 
pose  that  twenty-seven  thimble fuls  be  taken  equally  from 
the  forward,  midships,  and  aft  parts,  from  the  starboard, 
center,  and  larboard  parts,  and  from  the  top,  half  depth, 
and  lower  parts  of  her  hold,  and  that  these  being  mixed 
and  the  grains  counted,  four-fifths  of  the  latter  are  found 
to  be  of  quality  A.  Then  we  infer,  experientially  and  pro 
visionally,  that  approximately  four-fifths  of  all  the  grain  in 
the  cargo  is  of  the  same  quality.  I  say  we  infer  this  ex 
perientially  and  provisionally.  By  saying  that  we  infer  it 
experientially ,  I  mean  that  our  conclusion  makes  no  pre- 


1 84  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

tension  to  knowledge  of  wheat-in-itself,  our 
as  the  derivation  of  that  word  implies,  has  nothing  to  do 
with  latent  wheat.  We  are  dealing  only  with  the  matter 
of  possible  experience,  —  experience  in  the  full  acceptation 
of  the  term  as  something  not  merely  affecting  the  senses 
but  also  as  the  subject  of  thought.  If  there  be  any  wheat 
hidden  on  the  ship,  so  that  it  can  neither  turn  up  in  the 
sample  nor  be  heard  of  subsequently  from  purchasers, — 
or  if  it  be  half-hidden,  so  that  it  may,  indeed,  turn  up,  but 
is  less  likely  to  do  so  than  the  rest,  —  or  if  it  can  affect  our 
senses  and  our  pockets,  but  from  some  strange  cause  or 
causelessness  cannot  be  reasoned  about,  —  all  such  wheat 
is  to  be  excluded  (or  have  only  its  proportional  weight)  in 
calculating  that  true  proportion  of  quality  A,  to  which  our 
inference  seeks  to  approximate.  By  saying  that  we  draw 
the  inference  provisionally,  I  mean  that  we  do  not  hold 
that  we  have  reached  any  assigned  degree  of  approximation 
as  yet,  but  only  hold  that  if  our  experience  be  indefinitely 
extended,  and  if  every  fact  of  whatever  nature,  as  fast  as  it 
presents  itself,  be  duly  applied,  according  to  the  inductive 
method,  in  correcting  the  inferred  ratio,  then  our  approxi 
mation  will  become  indefinitely  close  in  the  long  run;  that 
is  to  say,  close  to  the  experience  to  come  (not  merely  close 
by  the  exhaustion  of  a  finite  collection)  so  that  if  experience 
in  general  is  to  fluctuate  irregularly  to  and  fro,  in  a  manner 
to  deprive  the  ratio  sought  of  all  definite  value,  we  shall 
be  able  to  find  out  approximately  within  what  limits  it 
fluctuates,  and  if,  after  having  one  definite  value,  it  changes 
and  assumes  another,  we  shall  be  able  to  find  that  out,  and 
in  short,  whatever  may  be  the  variations  of  this  ratio  in 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  185 

experience,  experience  indefinitely  extended  will  enable  us 
to  detect  them,  so  as  to  predict  rightly,  at  last,  what  its 
ultimate  value  may  be,  if  it  have  any  ultimate  value,  or 
what  the  ultimate  law  of  succession  of  values  may  be,  if 
there  be  any  such  ultimate  law,  or  that  it  ultimately  fluc 
tuates  irregularly  within  certain  limits,  if  it  do  so  ultimately 
fluctuate.  Now  our  inference,  claiming  to  be  no  more  than 
thus  experiential  and  provisional,  manifestly  involves  no 
postulate  whatever. 

For  what  is  a  postulate?  It  is  the  formulation  of  a  ma 
terial  fact  which  we  are  not  entitled  to  assume  as  a  premise, 
but  the  truth  of  which  is  requisite  to  the  validity  of  an 
inference.  Any  fact,  then,  which  might  be  supposed  postu 
lated,  must  either  be  such  that  it  would  ultimately  present 
itself  in  experience,  or  not.  If  it  will  present  itself,  we 
need  not  postulate  it  now  in  our  provisional  inference,  since 
we  shall  ultimately  be  entitled  to  use  it  as  a  premise.  But 
if  it  never  would  present  itself  in  experience,  our  conclusion 
is  valid  but  for  the  possibility  of  this  fact  being  otherwise 
than  assumed,  that  is,  it  is  valid  as  far  as  possible  experi 
ence  goes,  and  that  is  all  that  we  claim.  Thus,  every 
postulate  is  cut  off,  either  by  the  provisionality  or  by  the 
experientiality  of  our  inference.  For  instance,  it  has  been 
said  that  induction  postulates  that,  if  an  indefinite  succes 
sion  of  samples  be  drawn,  examined,  and  thrown  back  each 
before  the  next  is  drawn,  then  in  the  long  run  every  grain 
will  be  drawn  as  often  as  any  other,  that  is  to  say,  postulates 
that  the  ratio  of  the  numbers  of  times  in  which  any  two 
are  drawn  will  indefinitely  approximate  to  unity.  But  no 
such  postulate  is  made;  for  if,  on  the  one  hand,  we  are  to 


1 86  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

have  no  other  experience  of  the  wheat  than  from  such 
drawings,  it  is  the  ratio  that  presents  itself  in  those'  drawings 
and  not  the  ratio  which  belongs  to  the  wheat  in  its  latent 
existence  that  we  are  endeavoring  to  determine;  while  if, 
on  the  other  hand,  there  is  some  other  mode  by  which  the 
wheat  is  to  come  under  our  knowledge,  equivalent  to  an 
other  kind  of  sampling,  so  that  after  all  our  care  in  stirring 
up  the  wheat,  some  experiential  grains  will  present  them 
selves  in  the  first  sampling  operation  more  often  than  others 
in  the  long  run,  this  very  singular  fact  will  be  sure  to  get 
discovered  by  the  inductive  method,  which  must  avail  itself 
of  every  sort  of  experience;  and  our  inference,  which  was 
only  provisional,  corrects  itself  at  last.  Again,  it  has  been 
said,  that  induction  postulates  that  under  like  circumstances 
like  events  will  happen,  and  that  this  postulate  is  at  bottom 
the  same  as  the  principle  of  universal  causation.  But  this 
is  a  blunder,  or  bevue,  due  to  thinking  exclusively  of  in 
ductions  where  the  concluded  ratio  is  either  i  or  o.  If 
any  such  proposition  were  postulated,  it  would  be  that 
under  like  circumstances  (the  circumstances  of  drawing  the 
different  samples)  different  events  occur  in  the  same  pro 
portions  in  all  the  different  sets,  —  a  proposition  which  is 
false  and  even  absurd.  But  in  truth  no  such  thing  is  postu 
lated,  the  experiential  character  of  the  inference  reducing 
the  condition  of  validity  to  this,  that  if  a  certain  result  does 
not  occur,  the  opposite  result  will  be  manifested,  a  condition 
assured  by  the  provisionality  of  the  inference.  But  it  may 
be  asked  whether  it  is  not  conceivable  that  every  instance 
of  a  certain  class  destined  to  be  ever  employed  as  a  datum 
of  induction  should  have  one  character,  while  every  instance 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  187 

destined  not  to  be  so  employed  should  have  the  opposite 
character.  The  answer  is  that  in  that  case,  the  instances 
excluded  from  being  subjects  of  reasoning  would  not  be 
experienced  in  the  full  sense  of  the  word,  but  would  be 
among  these  latent  individuals  of  which  our  conclusion  does 
not  pretend  to  speak. 

To  this  account  of  the  rationale  of  induction  I  know  of 
but  one  objection  worth  mention:  it  is  that  I  thus  fail  to 
deduce  the  full  degree  of  force  which  this  mode  of  inference 
in  fact  possesses;  that  according  to  my  view,  no  matter 
how  thorough  and  elaborate  the  stirring  and  mixing  process 
had  been,  the  examination  of  a  single  handful  of  grain 
would  not  give  me  any  assurance,  sufficient  to  risk  money 
upon  that  the  next  handful  would  not  greatly  modify  the 
concluded  value  of  the  ratio  under  inquiry,  while,  in  fact, 
the  assurance  would  be  very  high  that  this  ratio  was  not 
greatly  in  error.  If  the  true  ratio  of  grains  of  quality  A 
were  0.80  and  the  handful  contained  a  thousand  grains, 
nine  such  handfuls  out  of  every  ten  would  contain  from 
780  to  820  grains  of  quality  A.  The  answer  to  this  is  that 
the  calculation  given  is  correct  when  we  know  that  the  units 
of  this  handful  and  the  quality  inquired  into  have  the  nor 
mal  independence  of  one  another,  if  for  instance  the  stirring 
has  been  complete  and  the  character  sampled  for  has  been 
settled  upon  in  advance  of  the  examination  of  the  sample. 
But  in  so  far  as  these  conditions  are  not  known  to  be  com 
plied  with,  the  above  figures  cease  to  be  applicable.  Ran 
dom  sampling  and  predesignation  of  the  character  sampled 
for  should  always  be  striven  after  in  inductive  reasoning, 
but  when  they  cannot  be  attained,  so  long  as  it  is  conducted 


1 88  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

honestly,  the  inference  retains  some  value.  When  we  can 
not  ascertain  how  the  sampling  has  been  done  or  the  sample- 
character  selected,  induction  still  has  the  essential  validity 
which  my  present  account  of  it  shows  it  to  have. 

I  do  not  think  a  man  who  combines  a  willingness  to  be 
convinced  with  a  power  of  appreciating  an  argument  upon 
a  difficult  subject  can  resist  the  reasons  which  have  been 
given  to  show  that  the  principle  of  universal  necessity  can 
not  be  defended  as  being  a  postulate  of  reasoning.  But  then 
the  question  immediately  arises  whether  it  is  not  proved  to 
be  true,  or  at  least  rendered  highly  probable,  by  observa 
tion  of  nature. 

Still,  this  question  ought  not  long  to  arrest  a  person 
accustomed  to  reflect  upon  the  force  of  scientific  reasoning. 
For  the  essence  of  the  necessitarian  position  is  that  certain 
continuous  quantities  have  certain  exact  values.  Now,  how 
can  observation  determine  the  value  of  such  a  quantity  with 
a  probable  error  absolutely  nil?  To  one  who  is  behind  the 
scenes,  and  knows  that  the  most  refined  comparisons  of 
masses,  lengths,  and  angles,  far  surpassing  in  precision  all 
other  measurements,  yet  fall  behind  the  accuracy  of  bank- 
accounts,  and  that  the  ordinary  determinations  of  physi 
cal  constants,  such  as  appear  from  month  to  month  in  the 
journals,  are  about  on  a  par  with  an  upholsterer's  measure 
ments  of  carpets  and  curtains,  the  idea  of  mathematical 
exactitude  being  demonstrated  in  the  laboratory  will  appear 
simply  ridiculous.  There  is  a  recognized  method  of  esti 
mating  the  probable  magnitudes  of  errors  in  physics,  —  the 
method  of  least  squares.  It  is  universally  admitted  that 
this  method  makes  the  errors  smaller  than  they  really  are; 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  189 

yet  even  according  to  that  theory  an  error  indefinitely  small 
is  indefinitely  improbable;  so  that  any  statement  to  the 
effect  that  a  certain  continuous  quantity  has  a  certain  exact 
value,  if  well-founded  at  all,  must  be  founded  on  something 
other  than  observation. 

Still,  I  am  obliged  to  admit  that  this  rule  is  subject  to  a 
certain  qualification.  Namely,  it  only  applies  to  continuous  2 
quantity.  Now,  certain  kinds  of  continuous  quantity  are 
discontinuous  at  one  or  at  two  limits,  and  for  such  limits 
the  rule  must  be  modified.  Thus,  the  length  of  a  line  can 
not  be  less  than  zero.  Suppose,  then,  the  question  arises 
how  long  a  line  a  certain  person  had  drawn  from  a  marked 
point  on  a  piece  of  paper.  If  no  line  at  all  can  be  seen,  the 
observed  length  is  zero;  and  the  only  conclusion  this  obser 
vation  warrants  is  that  the  length  of  the  line  is  less  than  the 
smallest  length  visible  with  the  optical  power  employed. 
But  indirect  observations,  —  for  example,  that  the  person 
supposed  to  have  drawn  the  line  was  never  within  fifty 
feet  of  the  paper,  —  may;  make  it  probable  that  no  line 
at  all  was  made,  so  that  the  concluded  length  will  be  strictly 
zero.  In  like  manner,  experience  no  doubt  would  warrant 
the  conclusion  that  there  is  absolutely  no  indigo  in  a  given 
ear  of  wheat,  and  absolutely  no  attar  in  a  given  lichen. 
But  such  inferences  can  only  be  rendered  valid  by  posi 
tive  experiential  evidence,  direct  or  remote,  and  cannot  rest 
upon  a  mere  inability  to  detect  the  quantity  in  question. 
We  have  reason  to  think  there  is  no  indigo  in  the  wheat, 
because  we  have  remarked  that  wherever  indigo  is  pro- 

2  Continuous  is  not  exactly  the  right  word,  but  I  let  it  go  to  avoid  a 
long  and  irrelevant  discussion. 


1 9o  LOVE   AND    CHANCE 

duced  it  is  produced  in  considerable  quantities,  to  mention 
only  one  argument.  We  have  reason  to  think  there  is  no 
attar  in  the  lichen,  because  essential  oils  seem  to  be  in 
general  peculiar  to  single  species.  If  the  question  had  been 
whether  there  was  iron  in  the  wheat  or  the  lichen,  though 
chemical  analysis  should  fail  to  detect  its  presence,  we 
should  think  some  of  it  probably  was  there,  since  iron  is 
almost  everywhere.  Without  any  such  information,  one 
way  or  the  other,  we  could  only  abstain  from  any  opinion  as 
to  the  presence  of  the  substance  in  question.  It  cannot,  I 
conceive,  be  maintained  that  we  are  in  any  better  position 
than  this  in  regard  to  the  presence  of  the  element  of  chance 
or  spontaneous  departures  from  law  in  nature. 

Those  observations  which  are  generally  adduced  in  favor 
of  mechanical  causation  simply  prove  that  there  is  an  ele 
ment  of  regularity  in  nature,  and  have  no  bearing  what 
ever  upon  the  question  of  whether  such  regularity  is  exact 
and  universal,  or  not.  Nay,  in  regard  to  this  exactitude,  all 
observation  is  directly  opposed  to  it;  and  the  most  that  can 
be  said  is  that  a  good  deal  of  this  observation  can  be  ex 
plained  away.  Try  to  verify  any  law  of  nature,  and  you 
will  find  that  the  more  precise  your  observations,  the  more 
certain  they  will  be  to  show  irregular  departures  from  the 
law.  We  are  accustomed  to  ascribe  these,  and  I  do  not 
say  wrongly,  to  errors  of  observation;  yet  we  cannot  usually 
account  for  such  errors  in  any  antecedently  probable  way. 
Trace  their  causes  back  far  enough,  and  you  will  be  forced 
to  admit  they  are  always  due  to  arbitrary  determination, 
or  chance. 

But  it  may  be  asked  whether  if  there  were  an  element 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  191 

of  real  chance  in  the  universe  it  must  not  occasionally  be 
productive  of  signal  effects  such  as  could  not  pass  un 
observed.  In  answer  to  this  question,  without  stopping  to 
point  out  that  there  is  an  abundance  of  great  events  which 
one  might  be  tempted  to  suppose  were  of  that  nature,  it  will 
be  simplest  to  remark  that  physicists  hold  that  the  particles 
of  gases  are  moving  about  irregularly,  substantially  as  if 
by  real  chance,  and  that  by  the  principles  of  probabilities 
there  must  occasionally  happen  to  be  concentrations  of  heat 
in  the  gases  contrary  to  the  second  law  of  thermodynamics, 
and  these  concentrations,  occurring  in  explosive  mixtures, 
must  sometimes  have  tremendous  effects.  Here,  then,  is 
in  substance  the  very  situation  supposed;  yet  no  phenomena 
ever  have  resulted  which  we  are  forced  to  attribute  to  such 
chance  concentration  of  heat,  or  which  anybody,  wise  or 
foolish,  has  ever  dreamed  of  accounting  for  in  that  manner. 

In  view  of  all  these  considerations,  I  do  not  believe  that 
anybody,  not  in  a  state  of  case-hardened  ignorance  respect 
ing  the  logic  of  science,  can  maintain  that  the  precise  and 
universal  conformity  of  facts  to  law  is  clearly  proved,  or 
even  rendered  particularly  probable,  by  any  observations 
hitherto  made.  In  this  way,  the  determined  advocate  of 
exact  regularity  will  soon  find  himself  driven  to  a  priori 
reasons  to  support  his  thesis.  These  received  such  a  soc- 
dolager  from  Stuart  Mill  in  his  Examination  of  Hamilton, 
that  holding  to  them  now  seems  to  me  to  denote  a  high 
degree  of  imperviousness  to  reason;  so  that  I  shall  pass 
them  by  with  little  notice. 

To  say  that  we  cannot  help  believing  a  given  proposi 
tion  is  no  argument,  but  it  is  a  conclusive  fact  if  it  be 


1 92  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

true;  and  with  the  substitution  of  "I"  for  "we,"  it  is 
true  in  the  mouths  of  several  classes  of  minds,  the  blindly 
passionate,  the  unreflecting  and  ignorant,  and  the  per 
son  who  has  overwhelming  evidence  before  his  eyes.  But 
that  which  has  been  inconceivable  to-day  has  often  turned 
out  indisputable  on  the  morrow.  Inability  to  conceive  is 
only  a  stage  through  which  every  man  must  pass  in  regard 
to  a  number  of  beliefs,  —  unless  endowed  with  extraordinary 
obstinacy  and  obtuseness.  His  understanding  is  enslaved 
to  some  blind  compulsion  which  a  vigorous  mind  is  pretty 
sure  soon  to  cast  off. 

Some  seek  to  back  up  the  a  priori  position  with  empirical 
arguments.  They  say  that  the  exact  regularity  of  the  world 
is  a  natural  belief,  and  that  natural  beliefs  have  generally 
been  confirmed  by  experience.  There  is  some  reason  in 
this.  Natural  beliefs,  however,  if  they  generally  have  a 
foundation  of  truth,  also  require  correction  and  purification 
from  natural  illusions.  The  principles  of  mechanics  are  un 
doubtedly  natural  beliefs;  but,  for  all  that,  the  early  formu 
lations  of  them  were  exceedingly  erroneous.  The  general 
approximation  to  truth  in  natural  beliefs  is,  in  fact,  a  case 
of  the  general  adaptation  of  genetic  products  to  recogniz 
able  utilities  or  ends.  Now,  the  adaptations  of  nature, 
beautiful  and  often  marvelous  as  they  verily  are,  are  never 
found  to  be  quite  perfect;  so  that  the  argument  is  quite 
against  the  absolute  exactitude  of  any  natural  belief,  in 
cluding  that  of  the  principle  of  causation. 

Another  argument,  or  convenient  commonplace,  is  that 
absolute  chance  is  inconceivable.  (This  word  has  eight  cur 
rent  significations.  The  Century  Dictionary  enumerates 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  193 

six.)  Those  who  talk  like  this  will  hardly  be  persuaded 
to  say  in  what  sense  they  mean  that  chance  is  inconceiv 
able.  Should  they  do  so,  it  would  easily  be  shown  either 
that  they  have  no  sufficient  reason  for  the  statement  or 
that  the  inconceivability  is  of  a  kind  which  does  not  prove 
that  chance  is  non-existent. 

Another  a  priori  argument  is  that  chance  is  unintelligible; 
that  is  to  say,  while  it  may  perhaps  be  conceivable,  it  does 
not  disclose  to  the  eye  of  reason  the  how  or  why  of  things; 
and  since  a  hypothesis  can  only  be  justified  so  far  as  it 
renders  some  phenomenon  intelligible,  we  never  can  have 
any  right  to  suppose  absolute  chance  to  enter  into  the 
production  of  anything  in  nature.  This  argument  may  be 
considered  in  connection  with  two  others.  Namely,  instead 
of  going  so  far  as  to  say  that  the  supposition  of  chance  can 
never  properly  be  used  to  explain  any  observed  fact,  it 
may  be  alleged  merely  that  no  facts  are  known  which  such 
a  supposition  could  in  any  way  help  in  explaining.  Or 
again,  the  allegation  being  still  further  weakened,  it  may  be 
said  that  since  departures  from  law  are  not  unmistakably 
observed,  chance  is  not  a  vera  causa,  and  ought  not  un 
necessarily  to  be  introduced  into  a  hypothesis. 

These  are  no  mean  arguments,  and  require  us  to  examine 
the  matter  a  little  more  closely.  Come,  my  superior  op 
ponent,  let  me  learn  from  your  wisdom.  It  seems  to  me 
that  every  throw  of  sixes  with  a  pair  of  dice  is  a  manifest 
instance  of  chance. 

"While  you  would  hold  a  throw  of  deuce-ace  to  be 
brought  about  by  necessity?  "  (The  opponent's  supposed 
remarks  are  placed  in  quotation  marks.) 


194  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

Clearly  one  throw  is  as  much  chance  as  another. 

"  Do  you  think  throws  of  dice  are  of  a  different  nature 
from  other  events?  " 

I  see  that  I  must  say  that  all  the  diversity  and  specifical- 
ness  of  events  is  attributable  to  chance. 

"  Would  you,  then,  deny  that  there  is  any  regularity  in 
the  world?  " 

That  is  clearly  undeniable.  I  must  acknowledge  there 
is  an  approximate  regularity,  and  that  every  event  is  in 
fluenced  by  it.  But  the  diversification,  specificalness,  and 
irregularity  of  things  I  suppose  is  chance.  A  throw  of 
sixes  appears  to  me  a  case  in  which  this  element  is  par 
ticularly  obtrusive. 

"  If  you  reflect  more  deeply,  you  will  come  to  see  that 
chance  is  only  a  name  for  a  cause  that  is  unknown  to  us." 

Do  you  mean  that  we  have  no  idea  whatever  what  kind 
of  causes  could  bring  about  a  throw  of  sixes? 

"  On  the  contrary,  each  die  moves  under  the  influence 
of  precise  mechanical  laws." 

But  it  appears  to  me  that  it  is  not  these  laws  which  made 
the  die  turn  up  sixes;  for  these  laws  act  just  the  same  when 
other  throws  come  up.  The  chance  lies  in  the  diversity  of 
throws;  and  this  diversity  cannot  be  due  to  laws  which  are 
immutable. 

"  The  diversity  is  due  to  the  diverse  circumstances  under 
which  the  laws  act.  The  dice  lie  differently  in  the  box, 
and  the  motion  given  to  the  box  is  different.  These  are  the 
unknown  causes  which  produce  the  throws,  and  to  which 
we  give  the  name  of  chance;  not  the  mechanical  law  which 
regulates  the  operation  of  these  causes.  You  see  you  are 
already  beginning  to  think  more  clearly  about  this  subject." 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  195 

Does  the  operation  of  mechanical  law  not  increase  the 
diversity? 

"  Properly  not.  You  must  know  that  the  instantaneous 
state  of  a  system  of  particles  is  defined  by  six  times  as  many 
numbers  as  there  are  particles,  three  for  the  co-ordinates 
of  each  particle's  position,  and  three  more  for  the  com 
ponents  of  its  velocity.  This  number  of  numbers,  which 
expresses  the  amount  of  diversity  in  the  system,  remains 
the  same  at  all  times.  There  may  be,  to  be  sure,  some 
kind  of  relation  between  the  co-ordinates  and  component 
velocities  of  the  different  particles,  by  means  of  which  the 
state  of  the  system  might  be  expressed  by  a  smaller  number 
of  numbers.  But,  if  this  is  the  case,  a  precisely  correspond 
ing  relationship  must  exist  between  the  co-ordinates  and 
component  velocities  at  any  other  time,  though  it  may 
doubtless  be  a  relation  less  obvious  to  us.  Thus,  the  in 
trinsic  complexity  of  the  system  is  the  same  at  all  times." 

Very  well,  my  obliging  opponent,  we  have  now  reached  an 
issue.  You  think  all  the  arbitrary  specifications  of  the 
universe  were  introduced  in  one  dose,  in  the  beginning,  if 
there  was  a  beginning,  and  that  the  variety  and  complica 
tion  of  nature  has  always  been  just  as  much  as  it  is  now. 
But  I,  for  my  part,  think  that  the  diversification,  the  speci 
fication,  has  been  continually  taking  place.  Should  you 
condescend  to  ask  me  why  I  so  think,  I  should  give  my 
reasons  as  follows: 

(i)  Question  any  science  which  deals  with  the  course  of 
time.  Consider  the  life  of  an  individual  animal  or  plant, 
or  of  a  mind.  Glance  at  the  history  of  states,  of  insti 
tutions,  of  language,  of  ideas.  Examine  the  successions  of 


196  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

forms  shown  by  paleontology,  the  history  of  the  globe  as 
set  forth  in  geology,  of  what  the  astronomer  is  able  to 
make  out  concerning  the  changes  of  stellar  systems. 
Everywhere  the  main  fact  is  growth  and  increasing  com 
plexity.  Death  and  corruption  are  mere  accidents  or  secon 
dary  phenomena.  Among  some  of  the  lower  organisms,  it 
is  a  moot  point  with  biologists  whether  there  be  anything 
which  ought  to  be  called  death.  Races,  at  any  rate,  do  not 
die  out  except  under  unfavorable  circumstances.  From 
these  broad  and  ubiquitous  facts  we  may  fairly  infer,  by 
the  most  unexceptionable  logic,  that  there  is  probably  in 
nature  some  agency  by  which  the  complexity  and  diversity 
of  things  can  be  increased;  and  that  consequently  the 
rule  of  mechanical  necessity  meets  in  some  way  with 
interference. 

(2)  By  thus  admitting  pure  spontaneity  or  life  as  a  char 
acter  of  the  universe,  acting  always  and  everywhere  though 
restrained  within  narrow  bounds  by  law,  producing  in 
finitesimal  departures  from  law  continually,  and  great  ones 
with  infinite  in  frequency,  I  account  for  all  the  variety  and 
diversity  of  the  universe,  in  the  only  sense  in  which  the 
really  sui  generis  and  new  can  be  said  to  be  accounted  for. 
The  ordinary  view  has  to  admit  the  inexhaustible  multi 
tudinous  variety  of  the  world,  has  to  admit  that  its  me 
chanical  law  cannot  account  for  this  in  the  least,  that 
variety  can  spring  only  from  spontaneity,  and  yet  denies 
without  any  evidence  or  reason  the  existence  of  this  spon 
taneity,  or  else  shoves  it  back  to  the  beginning  of  time  and 
supposes  it  dead  ever  since.  The  superior  logic  of  my  view 
appears  to  me  not  easily  controverted. 


DOCTRINE    OF   NECESSITY    EXAMINED  197 

(3)  When  I  ask  the  necessitarian  how  he  would  explain 
the  diversity  and  irregularity  of  the  universe,  he  replies  to 
me  out  of  the  treasury  of  his  wisdom  that  irregularity  is 
something  which  from  the  nature  of  things  we  must  not 
seek  to  explain.    Abashed  at  this,  I  seek  to  cover  my  con 
fusion  by  asking  how  he  would  explain  the  uniformity  and 
regularity  of  the  universe,  whereupon  he  tells  me  that  the 
laws  of  nature  are  immutable  and  ultimate  facts,  and  no 
account  is  to  be  given  of  them.     But  my  hypothesis  of 
spontaneity  does  explain  irregularity,  in  a  certain  sense; 
that  is,  it  explains  the  general  fact  of  irregularity,  though 
not,  of  course,  what  each  lawless  event  is  to  be.    At  the 
same  time,  by  thus  loosening  the  bond  of  necessity,  it  gives 
room  for  the  influence  of  another  kind  of  causation,  such 
as  seems  to  be  operative  in  the  mind  in  the  formation  of 
associations,  and  enables  us  to  understand  how  the  uni 
formity  of  nature  could  have  been  brought  about.    That 
single  events  should  be  hard  and  unintelligible,  logic  will 
permit  without  difficulty:    we  do  not  expect  to  make  the 
shock  of  a  personally  experienced  earthquake  appear  natural 
and  reasonable  by  any  amount  of  cogitation.     But  logic 
does  expect  things  general  to  be  understandable.    To  say 
that  there  is  a  universal  law,  and  that  it  is  a  hard,  ultimate, 
unintelligible  fact,  the  why  and  wherefore  of  which  can 
never  be  inquired  into,  at  this  a  sound  logic  will  revolt; 
and  will  pass  over  at  once  to  a  method  of  philosophizing 
which  does  not  thus  barricade  the  road  of  discovery. 

(4)  Necessitarianism  cannot  logically  stop  short  of  mak 
ing  the  whole  action  of  the  mind  a  part  of  the  physical 
universe.    Our  notion  that  we  decide  what  we  are  going  to 


I98  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

do,  if  as  the  necessitarian  says,  it  has  been  calculable  since 
the  earliest  times,  is  reduced  to  illusion.  Indeed,  conscious 
ness  in  general  thus  becomes  a  mere  illusory  aspect  of  a 
material  system.  What  we  call  red,  green,  and  violet  are 
in  reality  only  different  rates  of  vibration.  The  sole  reality 
is  the  distribution  of  qualities  of  matter  in  space  and  time. 
Brain-matter  is  protoplasm  in  a  certain  degree  and  kind  of 
complication,^ — a  certain  arrangement  of  mechanical  par 
ticles.  Its  feeling  is  but  an  inward  aspect,  a  phantom. 
For,  from  the  positions  and  velocities  of  the  particles  at  any 
one  instant,  and  the  knowledge  of  the  immutable  forces, 
the  positions  at  all  other  times  are  calculable;  so  that  the 
universe  of  space,  time,  and  matter  is  a  rounded  system 
uninterfered  with  from  elsewhere.  But  from  the  state  of 
feeling  at  any  instant,  there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  the 
states  of  feeling  at  all  other  instants  are  thus  exactly  cal 
culable;  so  that  feeling  is,  as  I  said,  a  mere  fragmentary 
and  illusive  aspect  of  the  universe.  This  is  the  way,  then, 
that  necessitarianism  has  to  make  up  its  accounts.  It  enters 
consciousness  under  the  head  of  sundries,  as  a  forgotten 
trifle;  its  scheme  of  the  universe  would  be  more  satisfactory 
if  this  little  fact  could  be  dropped  out  of  sight.  On  the 
other  hand,  by  supposing  the  rigid  exactitude  of  causation 
to  yield,  I  care  not  how  little,  —  be  it  but  by  a  strictly 
infinitesimal  amount,  —  we  gain  room  to  insert  mind  into 
our  scheme,  and  to  put  it  into  the  place  where  it  is  needed, 
into  the  position  which,  as  the  sole  self-intelligible  thing, 
it  is  entitled  to  occupy,  that  of  the  fountain  of  existence; 
and  in  so  doing  we  resolve  the  problem  of  the  connection  of 
soul  and  body. 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  199 

(5)  But  I  must  leave  undeveloped  the  chief  of  my  reasons, 
and  can  only  adumbrate  it.  The  hypothesis  of  chance- 
spontaneity  is  one  whose  inevitable  consequences  are  capable 
of  being  traced  out  with  mathematical  precision  into  con 
siderable  detail.  Much  of  this  I  have  done  and  find  the 
consequences  to  agree  with  observed  facts  to  an  extent 
which  seems  to  me  remarkable.  But  the  matter  and 
methods  of  reasoning  are  novel,  and  I  have  no  right  to 
promise  that  other  mathematicians  shall  find  my  deductions 
as  satisfactory  as  I  myself  do,  so  that  the  strongest  reason 
for  my  belief  must  for  the  present  remain  a  private  reason 
of  my  own,  and  cannot  influence  others.  I  mention  it  to 
explain  my  own  position;  and  partly  to  indicate  to  future 
mathematical  speculators  a  veritable  goldmine,  should  time 
and  circumstances  and  the  abridger  of  all  joys  prevent  my 
opening  it  to  the  world. 

If  now  I,  in  my  turn,  inquire  of  the  necessitarian  why 
he  prefers  to  suppose  that  all  specification  goes  back  to  the 
beginning  of  things,  he  will  answer  me  with  one  of  those 
last  three  arguments  which  I  left  unanswered. 

First,  he  may  say  that  chance  is  a  thing  absolutely  un 
intelligible,  and,  therefore,  that  we  never  can  be  entitled 
to  make  such  a  supposition.  But  does  not  this  objection 
smack  of  nai've  impudence?  It  is  not  mine,  it  is  his  own 
conception  of  the  universe  which  leads  abruptly  up  to  hard, 
ultimate,  inexplicable,  immutable  law,  on  the  one  hand,  and 
to  inexplicable  specification  and  diversification  of  circum 
stances  on  the  other.  My  view,  on  the  contrary,  hypothe- 
tises  nothing  at  all,  unless  it  be  hypothesis  to  say  that  all 
specification  came  about  in  some  sense,  and  is  not  to  be 


200  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

accepted  as  unaccountable.  To  undertake  to  account  for 
anything  by  saying  boldly  that  it  is  due  to  chance  would, 
indeed,  be  futile.  But  this  I  do  not  do.  I  make  use  of 
chance  chiefly  to  make  room  for  a  principle  of  generaliza 
tion,  or  tendency  to  form  habits,  which  I  hold  has  produced 
all  regularities.  The  mechanical  philosopher  leaves  the 
whole  specification  of  the  world  utterly  unaccounted  for, 
which  is  pretty  nearly  as  bad  as  to  boldly  attribute  it  to 
chance.  I  attribute  it  altogether  to  chance,  it  is  true,  but 
to  chance  in  the  form  of  a  spontaneity  which  is  to  some 
degree  regular.  It  seems  to  me  clear  at  any  rate  that  one 
of  these  two  positions  must  be  taken,  or  else  specification 
must  be  supposed  due  to  a  spontaneity  which  develops  itself 
in  a  certain  and  not  in  a  chance  way,  by  an  objective  logic 
like  that  of  Hegel.  This  last  way  I  leave  as  an  open  possi 
bility,  for  the  present;  for  it  is  as  much  opposed  to  the 
necessitarian  scheme  of  existence  as  my  own  theory  is. 

Secondly,  the  necessitarian  may  say  there  are,  at  any  rate, 
no  observed  phenomena  which  the  hypothesis  of  chance 
could  aid  in  explaining.  In  reply,  I  point  first  to  the  phe 
nomenon  of  growth  and  developing  complexity,  which  ap 
pears  to  be  universal,  and  which  though  it  may  possibly  be 
an  affair  of  mechanism  perhaps,  certainly  presents  all  the 
appearance  of  increasing  diversification.  Then,  there  is 
variety  itself,  beyond  comparison  the  most  obtrusive  char 
acter  of  the  universe:  no  mechanism  can  account  for  this. 
Then,  there  is  the  very  fact  the  necessitarian  most  insists 
upon,  the  regularity  of  the  universe  which  for  him  serves 
only  to  block  the  road  of  inquiry.  Then,  there  are  the 
regular  relationships  between  the  laws  of  nature,  —  simi- 


DOCTRINE    OF    NECESSITY    EXAMINED  201 

larities  and  comparative  characters,  which  appeal  to  our 
intelligence  as  its  cousins,  and  call  upon  us  for  a  reason. 
Finally,  there  is  consciousness,  feeling,  a  patent  fact  enough, 
but  a  very  inconvenient  one  to  the  mechanical  philosopher. 

Thirdly,  the  necessitarian  may  say  that  chance  is  not  a 
vera  causa,  that  we  cannot  know  positively  there  is  any 
such  element  in  the  universe.  But  the  doctrine  of  the  vera 
causa  has  nothing  to  do  with  elementary  conceptions. 
Pushed  to  that  extreme,  it  at  once  cuts  off  belief  in  the 
existence  of  a  material  universe;  and  without  that  necessi 
tarianism  could  hardly  maintain  its  ground.  Besides,  va 
riety  is  a  fact  which  must  be  admitted;  and  the  theory  of 
chance  merely  consists  in  supposing  this  diversification  does 
not  antedate  all  time.  Moreover,  the  avoidance  of  hy 
potheses  involving  causes  nowhere  positively  known  to  act 
—  is  only  a  recommendation  of  logic,  not  a  positive  com 
mand.  It  cannot  be  formulated  in  any  precise  terms  with 
out  at  once  betraying  its  untenable  character,  —  I  mean  as 
rigid  rule,  for  as  a  recommendation  it  is  wholesome  enough. 

I  believe  I  have  thus  subjected  to  fair  examination  all 
the  important  reasons  for  adhering  to  the  theory  of  uni 
versal  necessity,  and  have  shown  their  nullity.  I  earnestly 
beg  that  whoever  may  detect  any  flaw  in  my  reasoning  will 
point  it  out  to  me,  either  privately  or  publicly;  for  if  I  am 
wrong,  it  much  concerns  me  to  be  set  right  speedily.  If 
my  argument  remains  unrefuted,  it  will  be  time,  I  think,  to 
doubt  the  absolute  truth  of  the  principle  of  universal  law; 
and  when  once  such  a  doubt  has  obtained  a  living  root  in 
any  man's  mind,  my  cause  with  him,  I  am  persuaded,  is 
gained. 


III.    THE   LAW   OF   MIND1 

IN  an  article  published  in  The  Monist  for  January,  1891, 
I  endeavored  to  show  what  ideas  ought  to  form  the  warp 
of  a  system  of  philosophy,  and  particularly  emphasized 
that  of  absolute  chance.  In  the  number  of  April,  1892,  I 
argued  further  in  favor  of  that  way  of  thinking,  which  it 
will  be  convenient  to  christen  tychism  (from  rux^7,  chance). 
A  serious  student  of  philosophy  will  be  in  no  haste  to 
accept  or  reject  this  doctrine;  but  he  will  see  in  it  one  of 
the  chief  attitudes  which  speculative  thought  may  take, 
feeling  that  it  is  not  for  an  individual,  nor  for  an  age,  to 
pronounce  upon  a  fundamental  question  of  philosophy. 
That  is  a  task  for  a  whole  era  to  work  out.  I  have  begun 
by  showing  that  tychism  must  give  birth  to  an  evolutionary 
cosmology,  in  which  all  the  regularities  of  nature  and  of 
mind  are  regarded  as  products  of  growth,  and  to  a  Schelling- 
fashioned  idealism  which  holds  matter  to  be  mere  specialized 
and  partially  deadened  mind.  I  may  mention,  for  the  bene 
fit  of  those  who  are  curious  in  studying  mental  biographies, 
that  I  was  born  and  reared  in  the  neighborhood  of  Concord, 
—  I  mean  in  Cambridge,  —  at  the  time  when  Emerson, 
Hedge,  and  their  friends  were  disseminating  the  ideas  that 
they  had  caught  from  Schelling,  and  Schelling  from  Plotinus. 
from  Boehm,  or  from  God  knows  what  minds  stricken  with 
the  monstrous  mysticism  of  the  East.  But  the  atmosphere 

1  The   Monist,  July,    1892. 

202 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND  203 

of  Cambridge  held  many  an  antiseptic  against  Concord 
transcendentalism;  and  I  am  not  conscious  of  having  con 
tracted  any  of  that  virus.  Nevertheless,  it  is  probable  that 
some  cultured  bacilli,  some  benignant  form  of  the  disease 
was  implanted  in  my  soul,  unawares,  and  that  now,  after 
long  incubation,  it  comes  to  the  surface,  modified  by  mathe 
matical  conceptions  and  by  training  in  physical  investiga 
tions. 

The  next  step  in  the  study  of  cosmology  must  be  to  ex 
amine  the  general  law  of  mental  action.  In  doing  this,  I 
shall  for  the  time  drop  my  tychism  out  of  view,  in  order  to 
allow  a  free  and  independent  expansion  to  another  con 
ception  signalized  in  my  first  Monist  paper  as  one  of  the 
most  indispensable  to  philosophy,  though  it  was  not  there 
dwelt  upon;  I  mean  the  idea  of  continuity.  The  tendency 
to  regard  continuity,  in  the  sense  in  which  I  shall  define  it, 
as  an  idea  of  prime  importance  in  philosophy  may  con 
veniently  be  termed  synechism.  The  present  paper  is  in 
tended  chiefly  to  show  what  synechism  is,  and  what  it  leads 
to.  I  attempted,  a  good  many  years  ago,  to  develop  this 
doctrine  in  the  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy  (Vol.  II.) ; 
but  I  am  able  now  to  improve  upon  that  exposition,  in  which 
I  was  a  little  blinded  by  nominalistic  prepossessions.  I 
refer  to  it,  because  students  may  possibly  find  that  some 
points  not  sufficiently  explained  in  the  present  paper  are 
cleared  up  in  those  earlier  ones. 

WHAT   THE  LAW  IS 

Logical  analysis  applied  to  mental  phenomena  shows  that 
there  is  but  one  law  of  mind,  namely,  that  ideas  tend  to 


204  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

spread  continuously  and  to  affect  certain  others  which  stand 
to  them  in  a  peculiar  relation  of  affectibility.  In  this 
spreading  they  lose  intensity,  and  especially  the  power  of 
affecting  others,  but  gain  generality  and  become  welded  with 
other  ideas. 

I  set  down  this  formula  at  the  beginning,  for  convenience ; 
and  now  proceed  to  comment  upon  it. 

INDIVIDUALITY   OF   IDEAS 

We  are  accustomed  to  speak  of  ideas  as  reproduced,  as 
passed  from  mind  to  mind,  as  similar  or  dissimilar  to  one 
another,  and,  in  short,  as  if  they  were  substantial  things; 
nor  can  any  reasonable  objection  be  raised  to  such  expres 
sions.  But  taking  the  word  "  idea "  in  the  sense  of  an 
event  in  an  individual  consciousness,  it  is  clear  that  an  idea 
once  past  is  gone  forever,  and  any  supposed  recurrence  of 
it  is  another  idea.  These  two  ideas  are  not  present  in  the 
same  state  of  consciousness,  and  therefore  cannot  possibly 
be  compared.  To  say,  therefore,  that  they  are  similar  can 
only  mean  that  an  occult  power  from  the  depths  of  the  soul 
forces  us  to  connect  them  in  our  thoughts  after  they  are 
both  no  more.  We  may  note,  here,  in  passing,  that  of  the 
two  generally  recognized  principles  of  association,  contiguity 
and  similarity,  the  former  is  a  connection  due  to  a  power 
without,  the  latter  a  connection  due  to  a  power  within. 

But  what  can  it  mean  to  say  that  ideas  wholly  past  are 
thought  of  at  all,  any  longer?  They  are  utterly  unknow 
able.  What  distinct  meaning  can  attach  to  saying  that  an 
idea  in  the  past  in  any  way  affects  an  idea  in  the  future, 
from  which  it  is  completely  detached?  A  phrase  between 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND  205 

the  assertion  and  the  denial  of  which  there  can  in  no  case 
be  any  sensible  difference  is  mere  gibberish. 

I  will  not  dwell  further  upon  this  point,  because  it  is  a 
commonplace  of  philosophy. 

CONTINUITY  OF   IDEAS 

We  have  here  before  us  a  question  of  difficulty,  analogous 
to  the  question  of  nominalism  and  realism.  But  when  once 
it  has  been  clearly  formulated,  logic  leaves  room  for  one 
.  answer  only.  How  can  a  past  idea  be  present?  Can  it 
be  present  vicariously?  To  a  certain  extent,  perhaps;  but 
not  merely  so;  for  then  the  question  would  arise  how  the 
past  idea  can  be  related  to  its  vicarious  representation. 
The  relation,  being  between  ideas,  can  only  exist  in  some 
consciousness:  now  that  past  idea  was  in  no  consciousness 
but  that  past  consciousness  that  alone  contained  it;  and 
that  did  not  embrace  the  vicarious  idea. 

Some  minds  will  here  jump  to  the  conclusion  that  a  past 
idea  cannot  in  any  sense  be  present.  But  that  is  hasty 
and  illogical.  How  extravagant,  too,  to  pronounce  our 
whole  knowledge  of  the  past  to  be  mere  delusion!  Yet  it 
would  seem  that  the  past  is  as  completely  beyond  the 
bounds  of  possible  experience  as  a  Kantian  thing-in-itself. 

How  can  a  past  idea  be  present?  Not  vicariously.  Then, 
only  by  direct  perception.  In  other  words,  to  be  present, 
it  must  be  ipso  facto  present.  That  is,  it  cannot  be  wholly 
,  past;  it  can  only  be  going,  infinitesimally  past,  less  past 
than  any  assignable  past  date.  We  are  thus  brought  to 
the  conclusion  that  the  present  is  connected  with  the  past 
by  r  series  of  real  infinitesimal  steps. 


206  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

It  has  already  been  suggested  by  psychologists  that  con 
sciousness  necessarily  embraces  an  interval  of  time.  But 
if  a  finite  time  be  meant,  the  opinion  is  not  tenable.  If  the 
sensation  that  precedes  the  present  by  half  a  second  were 
still  immediately  before  me,  then,  on  the  same  principle 
the  sensation  preceding  that  would  be  immediately  present, 
and  so  on  ad  infinitum.  Now,  since  there  is  a  time,  say  a 
year,  at  the  end  of  which  an  idea  is  no  longer  ipso  facto 
present,  it  follows  that  this  is  true  of  any  finite  interval, 
however  short. 

But  yet  consciousness  must  essentially  cover  an  interval 
of  time;  for  if  it  did  not,  we  could  gain  no  knowledge  of 
time,  and  not  merely  no  veracious  cognition  of  it,  but  no 
conception  whatever.  We  are,  therefore,  forced  to  say 
that  we  are  immediately  conscious  through  an  infinitesimal 
interval  of  time. 

This  is  all  that  is  requisite.  For,  in  this  infinitesimal 
interval,  not  only  is  consciousness  continuous  in  a  subjec 
tive  sense,  that  is,  considered  as  a  subject  or  substance 
having  the  attribute  of  duration;  but  also,  because  it  is 
immediate  consciousness,  its  object  is  ipso  facto  continuous. 
In  fact,  this  infinitesimally  spread-out  consciousness  is  a 
direct  feeling  of  its  contents  as  spread  out.  This  will  be 
further  elucidated  below.  In  an  infinitesimal  interval  we 
directly  perceive  the  temporal  sequence  of  its  beginning, 
middle,  and  end,  —  not,  of  course,  in  the  way  of  recogni 
tion,  for  recognition  is  only  of  the  past,  but  in  the  way  of 
immediate  feeling.  Now  upon  this  interval  follows  another, 
whose  beginning  is  the  middle  of  the  former,  and  whose 
middle  is  the  end  of  the  former.  Here,  we  have  an  im- 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND  207 

mediate  perception  of  the  temporal  sequence  of  its  begin 
ning,  middle,  and  end,  or  say  of  the  second,  third,  and 
fourth  instants.  From  these  two  immediate  perceptions, 
we  gain  a  mediate,  or  inferential,  perception  of  the  relation 
of  all  four  instants.  This  mediate  perception  is  objectively, 
or  as  to  the  object  represented,  spread  over  the  four  in 
stants;  but  subjectively,  or  as  itself  the  subject  of  duration, 
it  is  completely  embraced  in  the  second  moment.  (The 
reader  will  observe  that  I  use  the  word  instant  to  mean  a 
point  of  time,  and  moment  to  mean  an  infinitesimal  dura 
tion.)  If  it  is  objected  that,  upon  the  theory  proposed, 
we  must  have  more  than  a  mediate  perception  of  the  succes 
sion  of  the  four  instants,  I  grant  it;  for  the  sum  of  the  two 
infinitesimal  intervals  is  itself  infinitesimal,  so  that  it  is 
immediately  perceived.  It  is  immediately  perceived  in  the 
whole  interval,  but  only  mediately  perceived  in  the  last  two- 
thirds  of  the  interval.  Now,  let  there  be  an  indefinite 
succession  of  these  inferential  acts  of  comparative  percep 
tion;  and  it  is  plain  that  the  last  moment  will  contain  ob 
jectively  the  whole  series.  Let  there  be,  not  merely  an 
indefinite  succession,  but  a  continuous  flow  of  inference 
through  a  finite  time;  and  the  result  will  be  a  mediate  ob 
jective  consciousness  of  the  whole  time  in  the  last  moment. 
In  this  last  moment,  the  whole  series  will  be  recognized, 
or  known  as  known  before,  except  only  the  last  moment, 
which  of  course  will  be  absolutely  unrecognizable  to  itself. 
Indeed,  even  this  last  moment  will  be  recognized  like  the 
rest,  or,  at  least,  be  just  beginning  to  be  so.  There  is  a 
little  elenchus,  or  appearance  of  contradiction,  here,  which 
the  ordinary  logic  of  reflection  quite  suffices  to  resolve. 


208  LOVE   AND    CHANCE 

INFINITY  AND   CONTINUITY,  IN   GENERAL 

Most  of  the  mathematicians  who  during  the  last  two 
generations  have  treated  the  differential  calculus  have  been 
of  the  opinion  that  an  infinitesimal  quantity  is  an  absurdity; 
although,  with  their  habitual  caution,  they  have  often  added 
"  or,  at  any  rate,  the  conception  of  an  infinitesimal  is  so 
difficult,  that  we  practically  cannot  reason  about  it  with 
confidence  and  security."  Accordingly,  the  doctrine  of 
limits  has  been  invented  to  evade  the  difficulty,  or,  as  some 
say,  to  explain  the  signification  of  the  word  "  infinitesimal." 
This  doctrine,  in  one  form  or  another,  is  taught  in  all  the 
text-books,  though  in  some  of  them  only  as  an  alternative 
view  of  the  matter;  it  answers  well  enough  the  purposes  of 
calculation,  though  even  in  that  application  it  has  its 
difficulties. 

The  illumination  of  the  subject  by  a  strict  notation  for 
the  logic  of  relatives  had  shown  me  clearly  and  evidently 
that  the  idea  of  an  infinitesimal  involves  no  contradiction, 
before  I  became  acquainted  with  the  writings  of  Dr.  Georg 
Cantor  (though  many  of  these  had  already  appeared  in  the 
Mathematische  Annalen  and  in  Borchardt's  Journal,  if  not 
yet  in  the  Ada  Mathematica,  all  mathematical  journals  of 
the  first  distinction),  in  which  the  same  view  is  defended 
with  extraordinary  genius  and  penetrating  logic. 

The  prevalent  opinion  is  that  finite  numbers  are  the  only 
ones  that  we  can  reason  about,  at  least,  in  any  ordinary 
mode  of  reasoning,  or,  as  some  authors  express  it,  they  are 
the  only  numbers  that  can  be  reasoned  about  mathemati 
cally.  But  this  is  an  irrational  prejudice.  I  long  ago 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  209 

showed  that  finite  collections  are  distinguished  from  infinite 
ones  only  by  one  circumstance  and  its  consequences,  namely, 
that  to  them  is  applicable  a  peculiar  and  unusual  mode  of 
reasoning  called  by  its  discovererr  De  Morgan,  the  "  syl 
logism  of  transposed  quantity." 

Balzac,  in  the  introduction  of  his  Physiologic  du  mariaget 
remarks  that  every  young  Frenchman  boasts  of  having  se 
duced  some  Frenchwoman.  Now,  as  a  woman  can  only  be 
seduced  once,  and  there  are  no  more  Frenchwomen  than 
Frenchmen,  it  follows,  if  these  boasts  are  true,  that  no 
French  women  escape  seduction.  If  their  number  be 
finite,  the  reasoning  holds.  But  since  the  population  is  con 
tinually  increasing,  and  the  seduced  are  on  the  average 
younger  than  the  seducers,  the  conclusion  need  not  be  true. 
In  like  manner,  De  Morgan,  as  an  actuary,  might  have 
argued  that  if  an  insurance  company  pays  to  its  insured  on 
an  average  more  than  they  have  ever  paid  it,  including 
interest,  it  must  lose  money.  But  every  modern  actuary 
would  see  a  fallacy  in  that,  since  the  business  is  continually 
on  the  increase.  But  should  war,  or  other  cataclysm,  cause 
the  class  of  insured  to  be  a  finite  one,  the  conclusion  would 
turn  out  painfully  correct,  after  all.  The  above  two  reason 
ings  are  examples  of  the  syllogism  of  transposed  quantity. 

The  proposition  that  finite  and  infinite  collections  are 
distinguished  by  the  applicability  to  the  former  of  the  syl 
logism  of  transposed  quantity  ought  to  be  regarded  as  the 
basal  one  of  scientific  arithmetic. 

If  a  person  does  not  know  how  to  reason  logically,  and 
I  must  say  that  a  great  many  fairly  good  mathematicians, 
—  yea,  distinguished  ones,  —  fall  under  this  category,  but 


210  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

simply  uses  a  rule  of  thumb  in  blindly  drawing  inferences 
like  other  inferences  that  have  turned  out  well,  he  will,  of 
course,  be  continually  falling  into  error  about  infinite  num 
bers.  The  truth  is  such  people  do  not  reason,  at  all.  But 
for  the  few  who  do  reason,  reasoning  about  infinite  numbers 
is  easier  than  about  finite  numbers,  because  the  complicated 
syllogism  of  transposed  quantity  is  not  called  for.  For 
example,  that  the  whole  is  greater  than  its  part  is  not  an 
axiom,  as  that  eminently  bad  reasoner,  Euclid,  made  it  to 
be.  It  is  a  theorem  readily  proved  by  means  of  a  syllogism 
of  transposed  quantity,  but  not  otherwise.  Of  finite  collec 
tions  it  is  true,  of  infinite  collections  false.  Thus,  a  part 
of  the  whole  numbers  are  even  numbers.  Yet  the  even 
numbers  are  no  fewer  than  all  the  numbers;  an  evident 
proposition  since  if  every  number  in  the  whole  series  of 
whole  numbers  be  doubled,  the  result  will  be  the  series  of 
even  numbers. 

1,  2,  3,  4,    5,    6,   etc. 

2,  4,  6,  8,  10,  12,  etc. 

So  for  every  number  there  is  a  distinct  even  number.  In 
fact,  there  are  as  many  distinct  doubles  of  numbers  as  there 
are  of  distinct  numbers.  But  the  doubles  of  numbers  are 
all  even  numbers. 

In  truth,  of  infinite  collections  there  are  but  two  grades 
of  magnitude,  the  endless  and  the  innumerable.  Just  as  a 
finite  collection  is  distinguished  from  an  infinite  one  by  the 
applicability  to  it  of  a  special  mode  of  reasoning,  the  syllo 
gism  of  transposed  quantity,  so,  as  I  showed  in  the  paper 
last  referred  to,  a  numerable  collection  is  distinguished  from 
an  innumerable  one  by  the  applicability  to  it  of  a  certain 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  211 

mode  of  reasoning,  the  Fermatian  inference,  or,  as  it  is 
sometimes  improperly  termed,  "  mathematical  induction." 
As  an  example  of  this  reasoning,  Euler's  demonstration 
of  the  binomial  theorem  for  integral  powers  may  be  given. 
The  theorem  is  that  (x  +  y)n,  where  «  is  a  whole  number, 
may  be  expanded  into  the  sum  of  a  series  of  terms  of  which 
the  first  is  xny°  and  each  of  the  others  is  derived  from  the 
next  preceding  by  diminishing  the  exponent  of  x  by  i  and 
multiplying  by  that  exponent  and  at  the  same  time  increas 
ing  the  exponent  of  y  by  i  and  dividing  by  that  increased 
exponent.  Now,  suppose  this  proposition  to  be  true  for  a 
certain  exponent,  «  =  If ,  then  it  must  also  be  true  for 
n  —  M  +  i.  For  let  one  of  the  terms  in  the  expansion  of 
(x  +  y)™  be  written  A&y*.  Then,  this  term  with  the  two 
following  will  be 

P  p-l       q+l  P        p  -  I        P-Z      «+2 

Axpy«  +  A  —L—  x       y       +  A  — - —  L x       y 

g  -Hi  g  +  ig  +  2 

Now,  when  (x  +  y)*  is  multiplied  by  x  +  y  to  give  (x  -f  y)*+1, 
we  multiply  first  by  x  and  then  by  y  instead  of  by  x  and  add 
the  two  results.  When  we  multiply  by  x,  the  second  of  the 
above  three  terms  will  be  the  only  one  giving  a  term  involv 
ing  xpy*+1  and  the  third  will  be  the  only  one  giving  a  term  in 
xp-iyv+z-  and  when  we  multiply  by  y  the  first  will  be  the  only 
term  giving  a  term  in  xpyq+1,  and  the  second  will  be  the  only 
term  giving  a  term  in  xp~lyq+z.  Hence,  adding  like  terms,  we 
find  that  the  coefficient  of  xpyq+1  in  the  expansion  of  (x  +  y)u+l 
will  be  the  sum  of  the  coefficients  of  the  first  two  of  the  above 
three  terms,  and  that  the  coefficient  of  xp~1y*+2  will  be  the 
sum  of  the  coefficients  of  the  last  two  terms.  Hence,  two 
successive  terms  in  the  expansion  of  (x  +  y)™+1  will  be 


212  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 


h*] 


.   />  +  q  +  I     P  a+i      A  />  +  ^  +  I      p        P-I  «+2 

-A*- f #  y      +  A- f £—  *      <y 

0+1  ?  +  I       9+  2 

It  is,  thus,  seen  that  the  succession  of  terms  follows  the  rule. 
Thus  if  any  integral  power  follows  the  rule,  so  also  does 
the  next  higher  power.  But  the  first  power  obviously 
follows  the  rule.  Hence,  all  powers  do  so. 

Such  reasoning  holds  good  of  any  collection  of  objects 
capable  of  being  ranged  in  a  series  which  though  it  may  be 
endless,  can  be  numbered  so  that  each  member  of  it  re 
ceives  a  definite  integral  number.  For  instance,  all  the 
whole  numbers  constitute  such  a  numerable  collection. 
Again,  all  numbers  resulting  from  operating  according  to 
any  definite  rule  with  any  finite  number  of  whole  num 
bers  form  such  a  collection.  For  they  may  be  arranged 
in  a  series  thus.  Let  F  be  the  symbol  of  operation.  First 
operate  on  i,  giving  F  (i).  Then,  operate  on  a  second  i, 
giving  F(I,I).  Next,  introduce  2,  giving  3rd,  F(2);  4th 
F(2,i);  5th,  F(i,2);  6th,  F(2,2).  Next  use  a  third  vari 
able  giving  7th,  F(I,I,I);  8th,  F(2,i,i);  9th,  F(i,2*i); 
loth,  F(2,2,i);  nth,  F(i,i,2);  i2th,  F(2,i,2);  13 th, 
F(i,2,2);  i4th,  F(2,2,2).  Next  introduce  3,  and  so  on, 
alternately  introducing  new  variables  and  new  figures;  and 
in  this  way  it  is  plain  that  every  arrangement  of  integral 
values  of  the  variables  will  receive  a  numbered  place  in 
the  series.2 

The  class  of  endless  but  numerable  collections  (so  called 
because  they  can  be  so  ranged  that  to  each  one  corresponds 

2  This  proposition  is  substantially  the  same  as  a  theorem  of  Cantor, 
though  it  is  enunciated  in  a  much  more  general  form. 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  213 

a  distinct  whole  number)  is  very  large.  But  there  are 
collections  which  are  certainly  innumerable.  Such  is  the 
collection  of  all  numbers  to  which  endless  series  of  decimals 
are  capable  of  approximating.  It  has  been  recognized  since 
the  time  of  Euclid  that  certain  numbers  are  surd  or  incom 
mensurable,  and  are  not  exactly  expressible  by  any  finite 
series  of  decimals,  nor  by  a  circulating  decimal.  Such  is 
the  ratio  of  the  circumference  of  a  circle  to  its  diameter, 
which  we  know  is  nearly  3.1415926.  The  calculation  of 
this  number  has  been  carried  to  over  700  figures  without 
the  slightest  appearance  of  regularity  in  their  sequence. 
The  demonstrations  that  this  and  many  other  numbers  are 
incommensurable  are  perfect.  That  the  entire  collection  of 
incommensurable  numbers  is  innumerable  has  been  clearly 
proved  by  Cantor.  I  omit  the  demonstration;  but  it  is  easy 
to  see  that  to  discriminate  one  from  some  other  would,  in 
general,  require  the  use  of  an  endless  series  of  numbers. 
Now  if  they  cannot  be  exactly  expressed  and  discriminated, 
clearly  they  cannot  be  ranged  in  a  linear  series. 

It  is  evident  that  there  are  as  many  points  on  a  line  or  in 
an  interval  of  time  as  there  are  of  real  numbers  in  all. 
These  are,  therefore,  innumerable  collections.  Many  mathe 
maticians  have  incautiously  assumed  that  the  points  on  a 
surface  or  in  a  solid  are  more  than  those  on  a  line.  But 
this  has  been  refuted  by  Cantor.  Indeed,  it  is  obvious  that 
for  every  set  of  values  of  coordinates  there  is  a  single  dis 
tinct  number.  Suppose,  for  instance,  the  values  of  the  co 
ordinates  all  lie  between  o  and  +  i.  Then  if  we  compose 
a  number  by  putting  in  the  first  decimal  place  the  first  figure 
of  the  first  coordinate,  in  the  second  the  first  figure  of  the 


214  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

second  coordinate,  and  so  on,  and  when  the  first  figures  are 
all  dealt  out  go  on  to  the  second  figures  in  like  manner, 
it  is  plain  that  the  values  of  the  coordinates  can  be  read  off 
from  the  single  resulting  number,  so  that  a  triad  or  tetrad  of 
numbers,  each  having  innumerable  values,  has  no  more 
values  than  a  single  incommensurable  number. 

Were  the  number  of  dimensions  infinite,  this  would  fail; 
and  the  collection  of  infinite  sets  of  numbers  having  each 
innumerable  variations,  might,  therefore,  be  greater  than 
the  simple  innumerable  collection,  and  might  be  called 
endlessly  infinite.  The  single  individuals  of  such  a  collec 
tion  could  not,  however,  be  designated,  even  approximately, 
so  that  this  is  indeed  a  magnitude  concerning  which  it  would 
be  possible  to  reason  only  in  the  most  general  way,  if  at  all. 

Although  there  are  but  two  grades  of  magnitudes  of  in 
finite  collections,  yet  when  certain  conditions  are  imposed 
upon  the  order  in  which  individuals  are  taken,  distinctions 
of  magnitude  arise  from  that  cause.  Thus,  if  a  simply 
endless  series  be  doubled  by  separating  each  unit  into  two 
parts,  the  successive  first  parts  and  also  the  second  parts 
being  taken  in  the  same  order  as  the  units  from  which  they 
are  derived,  this  double  endless  series  will,  so  long  as  it  is 
taken  in  that  order,  appear  as  twice  as  large  as  the  original 
series.  In  like  manner  the  product  of  two  innumerable 
collections,  that  is,  the  collection  of  possible  pairs  composed 
of  one  individual  of  each,  if  the  order  of  continuity  is  to  be 
maintained,  is,  by  virtue  of  that  order,  infinitely  greater 
than  either  of  the  component  collections. 

We  now  come  to  the  difficult  question.  What  is  con 
tinuity?  Kant  confounds  it  with  infinite  divisibility,  saying 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND  215 

that  the  essential  character  of  a  continuous  series  is  that 
between  any  two  members  of  it  a  third  can  always  be  found. 
This  is  an  analysis  beautifully  clear  and  definite;  but  un 
fortunately,  it  breaks  down  under  the  first  test.  For  ac 
cording  to  this,  the  entire  series  of  rational  fractions  ar 
ranged  in  the  order  of  their  magnitude,  would  be  an  infinite 
series,  although  the  rational  fractions  are  numerable,  while 
the  points  of  a  line  are  innumerable.  Nay,  worse  yet,  if 
from  that  series  of  fractions  any  two  with  all  that  lie  be 
tween  them  be  excised,  and  any  number  of  such  finite  gaps 
be  made,  Kant's  definition  is  still  true  of  the  series,  though 
it  has  lost  all  appearance  of  continuity. 

Cantor  defines  a  continuous  series  as  one  which  is  con 
catenated  and  perfect.  By  a  concatenated  series,  he  means 
such  a  one  that  if  any  two  points  are  given  in  it,  and  any 
finite  distance,  however  small,  it  is  possible  to  proceed  from 
the  first  point  to  the  second  through  a  succession  of  points 
of  the  series  each  at  a  distance  from  the  preceding  one  less 
than  the  given  distance.  This  is  true  of  the  series  of  ra 
tional  fractions  ranged  in  the  order  of  their  magnitude. 
By  a  perfect  series,  he  means  one  which  contains  every 
point  such  that  there  is  no  distance  so  small  that  this  point 
has  not  an  infinity  of  points  of  the  series  within  that  dis 
tance  of  it.  This  is  true  of  the  series  of  numbers  between 
o  and  i  capable  of  being  expressed  by  decimals  in  which 
only  the  digits  o  and  i  occur. 

It  must  be  granted  that  Cantor's  definition  includes  every 
series  that  is  continuous;  nor  can  it  be  objected  that  it 
includes  any  important  or  indubitable  case  of  a  series  not 
continuous.  Nevertheless,  it  has  some  serious  defects.  In 


216  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

the  first  place,  it  turns  upon  metrical  considerations;  while 
the  distinction  between  a  continuous  and  a  discontinuous 
series  is  manifestly  non-metrical.  In  the  next  place,  a  per 
fect  series  is  defined  as  one  containing  "  every  point "  of 
a  certain  description.  But  no  positive  idea  is  conveyed  of 
what  all  the  points  are:  that  is  definition  by  negation,  and 
cannot  be  admitted.  If  that  sort  of  thing  were  allowed, 
it  would  be  very  easy  to  say,  at  once,  that  the  continuous 
linear  series  of  points  is  one  which  contains  every  point  of 
the  line  between  its  extremities.  Finally,  Cantor's  defini 
tion  does  not  convey  a  distinct  notion  of  what  the  compo 
nents  of  the  conception  of  continuity  are.  It  ingeniously 
wraps  up  its  properties  in  two  separate  parcels,  but  does  not 
display  them  to  our  intelligence. 

Kant's  definition  expresses  one  simple  property  of  a  con 
tinuum;  but  it  allows  of  gaps  in  the  series.  To  mend  the 
definition,  it  is  only  necessary  to  notice  how  these  gaps  can 
occur.  Let  us  suppose,  then,  a  linear  series  of  points  ex 
tending  from  a  point,  A,  to  a  point,  B,  having  a  gap  from 
B  to  a  third  point,  C,  and  thence  extending  to  a  final  limit, 
D;  and  let  us  suppose  this  series  conforms  to  Kant's  defini 
tion.  Then,  of  the  two  points,  B  and  C,  one  or  both  must 
be  excluded  from  the  series;  for  otherwise,  by  the  definition, 
there  would  be  points  between  them.  That  is,  if  the  series 
contains  C,  though  it  contains  all  the  points  up  to  B,  it  can 
not  contain  B.  What  is  required,  therefore,  is  to  state  in 
non-metrical  terms  that  if  a  series  of  points  up  to  a  limit 
is  included  in  a  continuum  the  limit  is  included.  It  may 
be  remarked  that  this  is  the  property  of  a  continuum  to 
which  Aristotle's  attention  seems  to  have  been  directed 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND  217 

when  he  defines  a  continuum  as  something  whose  parts 
have  a  common  limit.  The  property  may  be  exactly  stated 
as  follows:  If  a  linear  series  of  points  is  continuous  be 
tween  two  points,  A  and  D,  and  if  an  endless  series  of 
points  be  taken,  the  first  of  them  between  A  and  D  and 
each  of  the  others  between  the  last  preceding  one  and  D, 
then  there  is  a  point  of  the  continuous  series  between  all 
that  endless  series  of  points  and  Z>,  and  such  that  every 
other  point  of  which  this  is  true  lies  between  this  point 
and  D.  For  example,  take  any  number  between  o  and  i, 
as  o.i;  then,  any  number  between  o.i  and  i,  as  o.n;  then 
any  number  between  o.n  and  i,  as  o.m;  and  so  on,  with 
out  end.  Then,  because  the  series  of  real  numbers  be 
tween  o  and  i  is  continuous,  there  must  be  a  least  real 
number,  greater  than  every  number  of  that  endless  series. 
This  property,  which  may  be  called  the  Aristotelicity  of  the 
series,  together  with  Kant's  property,  or  its  Kanticity, 
completes  the  definition  of  a  continuous  series. 

The  property  of  Aristotelicity  may  be  roughly  stated 
thus:  a  continuum  contains  the  end  point  belonging  to  every 
endless  series  of  points  which  it  contains.  An  obvious 
corollary  is  that  every  continuum  contains  its  limits.  But 
in  using  this  principle  it  is  necessary  to  observe  that  a  series 
may  be  continuous  except  in  this,  that  it  omits  one  or  both 
of  the  limits. 

Our  ideas  will  find  expression  more  conveniently  if,  in 
stead  of  points  upon  a  line,  we  speak  of  real  numbers. 
Every  real  number  is^  in  one  sense,  the  limit  of  a  series, 
for  it  can  be  indefinitely  approximated  to.  Whether  every 
real  number  is  a  limit  of  a  regular  series  may  perhaps  be 


2i 8  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

open  to  doubt.  But  the  series  referred  to  in  the  definition 
of  Aristotelicity  must  be  understood  as  including  all  series 
whether  regular  or  not.  Consequently,  it  is  implied  that 
between  any  two  points  an  innumerable  series  of  points 
can  be  taken. 

Every  number  whose  expression  in  decimals  requires  but 
a  finite  number  of  places  of  decimals  is  commensurable. 
Therefore,  incommensurable  numbers  suppose  an  infinitieth 
place  of  decimals.  The  word  infinitesimal  is  simply  the 
Latin  form  of  infinitieth;  that  is,  it  is  an  ordinal  formed 
from  infinitum,  as  centesimal  from  centum.  Thus,  con 
tinuity  supposes  infinitesimal  quantities.  There  is  nothing 
contradictory  about  the  idea  of  such  quantities.  In  adding 
and  multiplying  them  the  continuity  must  not  be  broken  up, 
and  consequently  they  are  precisely  like  any  other  quan 
tities,  except  that  neither  the  syllogism  of  transposed 
quantity,  nor  the  Fermatian  inference  applies  to  them. 

If  A  is  a  finite  quantity  and  i  an  infinitesimal,  then  in  a 
certain  sense  we  may  write  A  +  i  =  A.  That  is  to  say, 
this  is  so  for  all  purposes  of  measurement.  But  this  prin 
ciple  must  not  be  applied  except  to  get  rid  of  all  the  terms 
in  the  highest  order  of  infinitesimals  present.  As  a  mathe 
matician,  I  prefer  the  method  of  infinitesimals  to  that  of 
limits,  as  far  easier  and  less  infested  with  snares.  Indeed, 
the  latter,  as  stated  in  some  books,  involves  propositions 
that  are  false;  but  this  is  not  the  case  with  the  forms  of 
the  method  used  by  Cauchy,  Duhamel,  and  others.  As  they 
understand  the  doctrine  of  limits,  it  involves  the  notion  of 
continuity,  and,  therefore,  contains  in  another  shape  the 
very  same  ideas  as  the  doctrine  of  infinitesimals. 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  219 

Let  us  now  consider  an  aspect  of  the  Aristotelical  prin 
ciple  which  is  particularly  important  in  philosophy.  Sup 
pose  a  surface  to  be  part  red  and  part  blue;  so  that  every 
point  on  it  is  either  red  or  blue,  and,  of  course,  no  part 
can  be  both  red  and  blue.  What,  then,  is  the  color  of  the 
boundary  line  between  the  red  and  the  blue?  The  answer 
is  that  red  or  blue,  to  exist  at  all,  must  be  spread  over  a 
surface;  and  the  color  of  the  surface  is  the  color  of  the 
surface  in  the  immediate  neighborhood  of  the  point.  I 
purposely  use  a  vague  form  of  expression.  Now,  as  the 
parts  of  the  surface  in  the  immediate  neighborhood  of  any 
ordinary  point  upon  a  curved  boundary  are  half  of  them 
red  and  half  blue,  it  follows  that  the  boundary  is  half  red 
and  half  blue.  In  like  manner,  we  find  it  necessary  to 
hold  that  consciousness  essentially  occupies  time;  and  what 
is  present  to  the  mind  at  any  ordinary  instant,  is  what  is 
present  during  a  moment  in  which  that  instant  occurs. 
Thus,  the  present  is  half  past  and  half  to  come.  Again, 
the  color  of  the  parts  of  a  surface  at  any  finite  distance 
from  a  point,  has  nothing  to  do  with  its  color  just  at  that 
point;  and,  in  the  parallel,  the  feeling  at  any  finite  interval 
from  the  present  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  present  feeling, 
except  vicariously.  Take  another  case:  the  velocity  of  a 
particle  at  any  instant  of  time  is  its  mean  velocity  during 
an  infinitesimal  instant  in  which  that  time  is  contained. 
Just  so  my  immediate  feeling  is  my  feeling  through  an  in 
finitesimal  duration  containing  the  present  instant. 


220  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

ANALYSIS   OF  TIME 

One  of  the  most  marked  features  about  the  law  of  mind 
is  that  it  makes  time  to  have  a  definite  direction  of  flow 
from  past  to  future.  The  relation  of  past  to  future  is,  in 
reference  to  the  law  of  mind,  different  from  the  relation  of 
future  to  past.  This  makes  one  of  the  great  contrasts  be 
tween  the  law  of  mind  and  the  law  of  physical  force,  where 
there  is  no  more  distinction  between  the  two  opposite  direc 
tions  in  time  than  between  moving  northward  and  moving 
southward. 

In  order,  therefore,  to  analyze  the  law  of  mind,  we  must 
begin  by  asking  what  the  flow  of  time  consists  in.  Now, 
we  find  that  in  reference  to  any  individual  state  of  feeling, 
all  others  are  of  two  classes,  those  which  affect  this  one 
(or  have  a  tendency  to  affect  it,  and  what  this  means  we 
shall  inquire  shortly),  and  those  which  do  not.  The  present 
is  affectible  by  the  past  but  not  by  the  future. 

Moreover,  if  state  A  is  affected  by  state  B,  and  state  B 
by  state  C,  then  A  is  affected  by  state  C,  though  not  so  much 
t  so.  It  follows,  that  if  A  is  affectible  by  B,  B  is  not  affectible 
by  A. 

If,  of  two  states,  each  is  absolutely  unaffectible  by  the 
other,  they  are  to  be  regarded  as  parts  of  the  same  state. 
They  are  contemporaneous. 

To  say  that  a  state  is  between  two  states  means  that  it 
affects  one  and  is  affected  by  the  other.  Between  any  two 
states  in  this  sense  lies  an  innumerable  series  of  states  af 
fecting  one  another;  and  if  a  state  lies  between  a  given  state 
and  any  other  state  which  can  be  reached  by  inserting 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  221 

states  between  this  state  and  any  third  state,  these  inserted 
states  not  immediately  affecting  or  being  affected  by  either, 
then  the  second  rate  mentioned,  immediately  affects  or  is 
affected  by  the  first,  in  the  sense  that  in  the  one  the  other  is 
ipso  facto  present  in  a  reduced  degree. 

These  propositions  involve  a  definition  of  time  and  of  its 
flow.  Over  and  above  this  definition  they  involve  a  doc 
trine,  namely,  that  every  state  of  feeling  is  affectible  by 
every  earlier  state. 

THAT  FEELINGS   HAVE  INTENSIVE   CONTINUITY 

Time  with  its  continuity  logically  involves  some  other 
kind  of  continuity  than  its  own.  Time,  as  the  universal 
form  of  change,  cannot  exist  unless  there  is  something  to 
undergo  change,  and  to  undergo  a  change  continuous  in 
time,  there  must  be  a  continuity  of  changeable  qualities. 
Of  the  continuity  of  intrinsic  qualities  of  feeling  we  can  now 
form  but  a  feeble  conception.  The  development  of  the 
human  mind  has  practically  extinguished  all  feelings,  ex 
cept  a  few  sporadic  kinds,  sound,  colors,  smells,  warmth, 
etc.,  which  now  appear  to  be  disconnected  and  disparate. 
In  the  case  of  colors,  there  is  a  tridimensional  spread  of 
feelings.  Originally,  all  feelings  may  have  been  connected 
in  the  same  way,  and  the  presumption  is  that  the  number 
of  dimensions  was  endless.  For  development  essentially 
involves  a  limitation  of  possibilities.  But  given  a  number 
of  dimensions  of  feeling,  all  possible  varieties  are  obtainable 
by  varying  the  intensities  of  the  different  elements.  Accord 
ingly,  time  logically  supposes  a  continuous  range  of  in 
tensity  in  feeling.  It  follows,  then,  from  the  definition  of 


222  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

continuity,  that  when  any  particular  kind  of  feeling  is 
present,  an  infinitesimal  continuum  of  all  feelings  differing 
infinitesimally  from  that  is  present. 

THAT  FEELINGS  HAVE  SPATIAL  EXTENSION 

Consider  a  gob  of  protoplasm,  say  an  amoeba  or  a  slime- 
mould.  It  does  not  differ  in  any  radical  way  from  the 
contents  of  a  nerve-cell,  though  its  functions  may  be  less 
specialized.  There  is  no  doubt  that  this  slime-mould,  or 
this  amoeba,  or  at  any  rate  some  similar  mass  of  protoplasm 
feels.  That  is  to  say,  it  feels  when  it  is  in  its  excited  con 
dition.  But  note  how  it  behaves.  When  the  whole  is 
quiescent  and  rigid,  a  place  upon  it  is  irritated.  Just  at 
this  point,  an  active  motion  is  set  up,  and  this  gradually 
spreads  to  other  parts.  In  this  action,  no  unity  nor  relation 
to  a  nucleus,  or  other  unitary  organ  can  be  discerned.  It 
is  a  mere  amorphous  continuum  of  protoplasm,  with  feeling 
passing  from  one  part  to  another.  Nor  is  there  anything 
like  a  wave-motion.  The  activity  does  not  advance  to 
new  parts,  just  as  fast  as  it  leaves  old  parts.  Rather,  in 
the  beginning,  it  dies  out  at  a  slower  rate  than  that  at  which 
it  spreads.  And  while  the  process  is  going  on,  by  exciting 
the  mass  at  another  point,  a  second  quite  independent  state 
of  excitation  will  be  set  up.  In  some  places,  neither  ex 
citation  will  exist,  in  others  each  separately,  in  still  other 
places,  both  effects  will  be  added  together.  Whatever  there 
is  in  the  whole  phenomenon  to  make  us  think  there  is  feel 
ing  in  such  a  mass  of  protoplasm,  —  feeling,  but  plainly  no 
personality,  —  goes  logically  to  show  that  that  feeling  has 
a  subjective,  or  substantial,  spatial  extension,  as  the  excited 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  223 

state  has.  This  is,  no  doubt,  a  difficult  idea  to  seize,  for 
the  reason  that  it  is  a  subjective,  not  an  objective,  extension. 
It  is  not  that  we  have  a  feeling  of  bigness;  though  Pro 
fessor  James,  perhaps  rightly,  teaches  that  we  have.  It  is 
that  the  feeling,  as  a  subject  of  inhesion,  is  big.  Moreover, 
our  own  feelings  are  focused  in  attention  to  such  a  degree 
that  we  are  not  aware  that  ideas  are  not  brought  to  an  ab 
solute  unity;  just  as  nobody  not  instructed  by  special  ex 
periment  has  any  idea  how  very,  very  little  of  the  field  of 
vision  is  distinct.  Still,  we  all  know  how  the  attention 
wanders  about  among  our  feelings;  and  this  fact  shows 
that  those  feelings  that  are  not  co-ordinated  in  attention 
have  a  reciprocal  externality,  although  they  are  present  at 
the  same  time.  But  we  must  not  tax  introspection  to  make 
a  phenomenon  manifest  which  essentially  involves  exter 
nality. 

Since  space  is  continuous,  it  follows  that  there  must  be 
an  immediate  community  of  feeling  between  parts  of  mind 
infinitesimally  near  together.  Without  this,  I  believe  it 
would  have  been  impossible  for  minds  external  to  one 
another,  ever  to  become  co-ordinated,  and  equally  impossi 
ble  for  any  coordination  to  be  established  in  the  action  of 
the  nerve-matter  of  one  brain. 

AFFECTIONS   OF   IDEAS 

But  we  are  met  by  the  question  what  is  meant  by  saying 
that  one  idea  affects  another.  The  unravelment  of  this 
problem  requires  us  to  trace  out  phenomena  a  little  further. 

Three  elements  go  to  make  up  an  idea.  The  first  is  its 
intrinsic  quality  as  a  feeling.  The  second  is  the  energy 


224  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

with  which  it  affects  other  ideas,  an  energy  which  is  infinite 
in  the  here-and-nowness  of  immediate  sensation,  finite  and 
relative  in  the  recency  of  the  past.  The  third  element  is 
the  tendency  of  an  idea  to  bring  along  other  ideas  with  it. 

As  an  idea  spreads,  its  power  of  affecting  other  ideas  gets 
rapidly  reduced;  but  its  intrinsic  quality  remains  nearly 
unchanged.  It  is  long  years  now  since  I  last  saw  a  cardinal 
in  his  robes;  and  my  memory  of  their  color  has  become 
much  dimmed.  The  color  itself,  however,  is  not  remem 
bered  as  dim.  I  have  no  inclination  to  call  it  a  dull  red. 
Thus,  the  intrinsic  quality  remains  little  changed;  yet 
more  accurate  observation  will  show  a  slight  reduction  of 
it.  The  third  element,  on  the  other  hand,  has  increased. 
As  well  as  I  can  recollect,  it  seems  to  me  the  cardinals  I 
used  to  see  wore  robes  more  scarlet  than  vermillion  is, 
and  highly  luminous.  Still,  I  know  the  color  commonly 
called  cardinal  is  on  the  crimson  side  of  vermillion  and  of 
quite  moderate  luminosity,  and  the  original  idea  calls  up 
so  many  other  hues  with  it,  and  asserts  itself  so  feebly,  that 
I  am  unable  any  longer  to  isolate  it. 

A  finite  interval  of  time  generally  contains  an  innumer 
able  series  of  feelings;  and  when  these  become  welded  to 
gether  in  association,  the  result  is  a  general  idea.  For  we 
have  just  seen  how  by  continuous  spreading  an  idea  be 
comes  generalised. 

The  first  character  of  a  general  idea  so  resulting  is  that 
it  is  living  feeling.  A  continuum  of  this  feeling,  infinitesi 
mal  in  duration,  but  still  embracing  innumerable  parts, 
and  also,  though  infinitesimal,  entirely  unlimited,  is  im 
mediately  present.  And  in  its  absence  of  boundedness  a 


THE    LAW    OF   MIND 


225 


vague  possibility  of  more  than  is  present  is  directly  felt. 
Second,  in  the  presence  of  this  continuity  of  feeling, 
nominalistic  maxims  appear  futile.  There  is  no  doubt 
about  one  idea  affecting  another,  when  we  can  directly 
perceive  the  one  gradually  modified  and  shaping  itself  into 
the  other.  Nor  can  there  any  longer  be  any  difficulty  about 
one  idea  resembling  another,  when  we  can  pass  along  the 
continuous  field  of  quality  from  one  to  the  other  and  back 
again  to  the  point  which  we  had  marked. 


Past 


Future 


Third,  consider  the  insistency  of  an  idea.  The  insistency 
of  a  past  idea  with  reference  to  the  present  is  a  quantity 
which  is  less  the  further  back  that  past  idea  is,  and  rises  to 
infinity  as  the  past  idea  is  brought  up  into  coincidence  with 
the  present.  Here  we  must  make  one  of  those  inductive 
applications  of  the  law  of  continuity  which  have  produced 


226  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

such  great  results  in  all  the  positive  sciences.  We  must 
extend  the  law  of  insistency  into  the  future.  Plainly,  the 
insistency  of  a  future  idea  with  reference  to  the  present  is  a 
quantity  affected  by  the  minus  sign;  for  it  is  the  present 
that  affects  the  future,  if  there  be  any  effect,  not  the  future 
that  affects  the  present.  Accordingly,  the  curve  of  insis 
tency  is  a  sort  of  equilateral  hyperbola.  (See  the  figure.) 
Such  a  conception  is  none  the  less  mathematical,  that  its 
quantification  cannot  now  be  exactly  specified. 

Now  consider  the  induction  which  we  have  here  been  led 
into.  This  curve  says  that  feeling  which  has  not  yet 
emerged  into  immediate  consciousness  is  already  affectible 
and  already  affected.  In  fact,  this  is  habit,  by  virtue  of 
which  an  idea  is  brought  up  into  present  consciousness  by 
a  bond  that  had  already  been  established  between  it  and 
another  idea  while  it  was  still  in  juturo. 

We  can  now  see  what  the  affection  of  one  idea  by  an 
other  consists  in.  It  is  that  the  affected  idea  is  attached 
as  a  logical  predicate  to  the  affecting  idea  as  subject.  So 
when  a  feeling  emerges  into  immediate  consciousness,  it 
always  appears  as  a  modification  of  a  more  or  less  general 
object  already  in  the  mind.  The  word  suggestion  is  well 
adapted  to  expressing  this  relation.  The  future  is  suggested 
by,  or  rather  is  influenced  by  the  suggestions  of,  the  past. 

IDEAS  CANNOT  BE  CONNECTED  EXCEPT  BY  CONTINUITY 

That  ideas  can  nowise  be  connected  without  continuity 
is  sufficiently  evident  to  one  who  reflects  upon  the  matter. 
But  still  the  opinion  may  be  entertained  that  after  con 
tinuity  has  once  made  the  connection  of  ideas  possible, 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  227 

then  they  may  get  to  be  connected  in  other  modes  than 
through  continuity.  Certainly,  I  cannot  see  how  anyone 
can  deny  that  the  infinite  diversity  of  the  universe,  which 
we  call  chance,  may  bring  ideas  into  proximity  which  are 
not  associated  in  one  general  idea.  It  may  do  this  many 
times.  But  then  the  law  of  continuous  spreading  will  pro 
duce  a  mental  association;  and  this  I  suppose  is  an  abridged 
statement  of  the  way  the  universe  has  been  evolved.  But 
if  I  am  asked  whether  a  blind  avayKrj  cannot  bring  ideas 
together,  first  I  point  out  that  it  would  not  remain  blind. 
There  being  a  continuous  connection  between  the  ideas, 
they  would  infallibly  become  associated  in  a  living,  feeling, 
and  perceiving  general  idea.  Next,  I  cannot  see  what  the 
mustness  or  necessity  of  this  avayKfj  would  consist  in. 
In  the  absolute  uniformity  of  the  phenomenon,  says  the 
nominalist.  Absolute  is  well  put  in;  for  if  it  merely  hap 
pened  so  three  times  in  succession,  or  three  million  times 
in  succession,  in  the  absence  of  any  reason,  the  coincidence 
could  only  be  attributed  to  chance.  But  absolute  uni 
formity  must  extend  over  the  whole  infinite  future;  and  it 
is  idle  to  talk  of  that  except  as  an  idea.  No;  I  think  we 
can  only  hold  that  wherever  ideas  come  together  they  tend 
to  weld  into  general  ideas;  and  wherever  they  are  generally 
connected,  general  ideas  govern  the  connection;  and  these 
general  ideas  are  living  feelings  spread  out. 

MENTAL  LAW  FOLLOWS   THE  FORMS   OF   LOGIC 

The  three  main  classes  of  logical  inference  are  Deduction, 
Induction,  and  Hypothesis.  These  correspond  to  three 
chief  modes  of  action  of  the  human  soul.  In  deduction  the 


228  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

mind  is  under  the  dominion  of  a  habit  or  association  by 
virtue  of  which  a  general  idea  suggests  in  each  case  a  corre 
sponding  reaction.  But  a  certain  sensation  is  seen  to  in 
volve  that  idea.  Consequently,  that  sensation  is  followed 
by  that  reaction.  That  is  the  way  the  hind  legs  of  a  frog, 
separated  from  the  rest  of  the  body,  reason,  when  you 
pinch  them.  It  is  the  lowest  form  of  psychical  manifes 
tation. 

By  induction,  a  habit  becomes  established.  Certain  sen 
sations,  all  involving  one  general  idea,  are  followed  each 
by  the  same  reaction;  and  an  association  becomes  estab 
lished,  whereby  that  general  idea  gets  to  be  followed  uni 
formly  by  that  reaction. 

Habit  is  that  specialization  of  the  law  of  mind  whereby 
a  general  idea  gains  the  power  of  exciting  reactions.  But 
in  order  that  the  general  idea  should  attain  all  its  func 
tionality,  it  is  necessary,  also,  that  it  should  become  sug 
gestible  by  sensations.  That  is  accomplished  by  a  psychical 
process  having  the  form  of  hypothetic  inference.  By  hypo 
thetic  inference,  I  mean,  as  I  have  explained  in  other  writ 
ings,  an  induction  from  qualities.  For  example,  I  know 
that  the  kind  of  man  known  and  classed  as  a  "  mugwump  " 
has  certain  characteristics.  He  has  a  high  self-respect  and 
places  great  value  upon  social  distinction.  He  laments  the 
great  part  that  rowdyism  and  unrefined  good-fellowship 
play  in  the  dealings  of  American  politicians  with  their  con 
stituency.  He  thinks  that  the  reform  which  would  follow 
from  the  abandonment  of  the  system  by  which  the  dis 
tribution  of  offices  is  made  to  strengthen  party  organizations 
and  a  return  to  the  original  and  essential  conception  of 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  229 

office-filling  would  be  found  an  unmixed  good.  He  holds 
that  monetary  considerations  should  usually  be  the  decisive 
ones  in  questions  of  public  policy.  He  respects  the  prin 
ciple  of  individualism  and  of  laissez-faire  as  the  greatest 
agency  of  civilization.  These  views,  among  others,  I  know 
to  be  obtrusive  marks  of  a  "  mugwump."  Now,  suppose 
I  casually  meet  a  man  in  a  railway-train,  and  falling  into 
conversation  find  that  he  holds  opinions  of  this  sort;  I  am 
naturally  led  to  suppose  that  he  is  a  "  mugwump."  That 
is  hypothetic  inference.  That  is  to  say,  a  number  of  readily 
verifiable  marks  of  a  mugwump  being  selected,  I  find  this 
man  has  these,  and  infer  that  he  has  all  the  other  characters 
which  go  to  make  a  thinker  of  that  stripe.  Or  let  us  sup 
pose  that  I  meet  a  man  of  a  semi-clerical  appearance  and 
a  sub-pharisaical  sniff,  who  appears  to  look  at  things  from 
the  point  of  view  of  a  rather  wooden  dualism.  He  cites 
several  texts  of  scripture  and  always  with  particular  atten 
tion  to  their  logical  implications;  and  he  exhibits  a  stern 
ness,  almost  amounting  to  vindictiveness,  toward  evil-doers, 
in  general.  I  readily  conclude  that  he  is  a  minister  of  a 
certain  denomination.  Now  the  mind  acts  in  a  way  similar 
to  this,  every  time  we  acquire  a  power  of  co-ordinating  re 
actions  in  a  peculiar  way,  as  in  performing  any  act  requir 
ing  skill.  Thus,  most  persons  have  a  difficulty  in  moving 
the  two  hands  simultaneously  and  in  opposite  directions 
through  two  parallel  circles  nearly  in  the  medial  plane  of 
the  body.  To  learn  to  do  this,  it  is  necessary  to  attend, 
first,  to  the  different  actions  in  different  parts  of  the  motion, 
when  suddenly  a  general  conception  of  the  action  springs 
up  and  it  becomes  perfectly  easy.  We  think  the  motion 


230  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

we  are  trying  to  do  involves  this  action,  and  this,  and  this. 
Then,  the  general  idea  comes  which  unites  all  those  actions, 
and  thereupon  the  desire  to  perform  the  motion  calls  up 
the  general  idea.  The  same  mental  process  is  many  times 
employed  whenever  we  are  learning  to  speak  a  language 
or  are  acquiring  any  sort  of  skill. 

Thus,  by  induction,  a  number  of  sensations  followed  by 
one  reaction  become  united  under  one  general  idea  followed 
by  the  same  reaction;  while  by  the  hypothetic  process,  a 
number  of  reactions  called  for  by  one  occasion  get  united 
in  a  general  idea  which  is  called  out  by  the  same  occasion. 
By  deduction,  the  habit  fulfils  its  function  of  calling  out 
certain  reactions  on  certain  occasions. 

UNCERTAINTY  OF  MENTAL  ACTION 

The  inductive  and  hypothetic  forms  of  inference  are 
essentially  probable  inferences,  not  necessary;  while  deduc 
tion  may  be  either  necessary  or  probable. 

But  no  mental  action  seems  to  be  necessary  or  invariable 
in  its  character.  In  whatever  manner  the  mind  has  reacted 
under  a  given  sensation,  in  that  manner  it  is  the  more  likely 
to  react  again;  were  this,  however,  an  absolute  necessity, 
habits  would  become  wooden  and  ineradicable,  and  no  room 
being  left  for  the  formation  of  new  habits,  intellectual  life 
would  come  to  a  speedy  close.  Thus,  the  uncertainty  of 
the  mental  law  is  no  mere  defect  of  it,  but  is  on  the  con 
trary  of  its  essence.  The  truth  is,  the  mind  is  not  subject 
to  "  law,"  in  the  same  rigid  sense  that  matter  is.  It  only 
experiences  gentle  forces  which  merely  render  it  more  likely 
to  act  in  a  given  way  than  it  otherwise  would  be.  There 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  231 

always  remains  a  certain  amount  of  arbitrary  spontaneity 
in  its  action,  without  which  it  would  be  dead. 

Some  psychologists  think  to  reconcile  the  uncertainty  of 
reactions  with  the  principle  of  necessary  causation  by  means 
of  the  law  of  fatigue.  Truly  for  a  law,  this  law  of  fatigue 
is  a  little  lawless.  I  think  it  is  merely  a  case  of  the  general 
principle  that  an  idea  in  spreading  loses  its  insistency. 
Put  me  tarragon  into  my  salad,  when  I  have  not  tasted  it 
for  years,  and  I  exclaim  "  What  nectar  is  this!  "  But  add 
it  to  every  dish  I  taste  for  week  after  week,  and  a  habit  of 
expectation  has  been  created;  and  in  thus  spreading  into 
habit,  the  sensation  makes  hardly  any  more  impression  upon 
me;  or,  if  it  be  noticed,  it  is  on  a  new  side  from  which  it 
appears  as  rather  a  bore.  The  doctrine  that  fatigue  is  one 
of  the  primordial  phenomena  of  mind  I  am  much  disposed 
to  doubt.  It  seems  a  somewhat  little  thing  to  be  allowed 
as  an  exception  to  the  great  principle  of  mental  uniformiza- 
tion.  For  this  reason,  I  prefer  to  explain  it  in  the  manner 
here  indicated,  as  a  special  case  of  that  great  principle. 
To  consider  it  as  something  distinct  in  its  nature,  certainly 
somewhat  strengthens  the  necessitarian  position;  but  even 
if  it  be  distinct,  the  hypothesis  that  all  the  variety  and 
apparent  arbitrariness  of  mental  action  ought  to  be  ex 
plained  away  in  favor  of  absolute  determinism  does  not 
seem  to  me  to  recommend  itself  to  a  sober  and  sound  judg 
ment,  which  seeks  the  guidance  of  observed  facts  and  not 
that  of  prepossessions. 


232  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

RESTATEMENT   OF   THE   LAW 

Let  me  now  try  to  gather  up  all  these  odds  and  ends  of 
commentary  and  restate  the  law  of  mind,  in  a  unitary  way. 

First,  then,  we  find  that  when  we  regard  ideas  from  a 
nominalistic,  individualistic,  sensualistic  way,  the  simplest 
facts  of  mind  become  utterly  meaningless.  That  one  idea 
should  resemble  another  or  influence  another,  or  that  one 
state  of  mind  should  so  much  as  be  thought  of  in  another  is, 
from  that  standpoint,  sheer  nonsense. 

Second,  by  this  and  other  means  we  are  driven  to  per 
ceive,  what  is  quite  evident  of  itself,  that  instantaneous 
feelings  flow  together  into  a  continuum  of  feeling,  which 
has  in  a  modified  degree  the  peculiar  vivacity  of  feeling  and 
has  gained  generality.  And  in  reference  to  such  general 
ideas,  or  continua  of  feeling,  the  difficulties  about  resem 
blance  and  suggestion  and  reference  to  the  external,  cease 
to  have  any  force. 

Third,  these  general  ideas  are  not  mere  words,  nor  do 
they  consist  in  this,  that  certain  concrete  facts  will  every 
time  happen  under  certain  descriptions  of  conditions;  but 
they  are  just  as  much,  or  rather  far  more,  living  realities 
than  the  feelings  themselves  out  of  which  they  are  concreted. 
And  to  say  that  mental  phenomena  are  governed  by  law 
does  not  mean  merely  that  they  are  describable  by  a  general 
formula;  but  that  there  is  a  living  idea,  a  conscious  con 
tinuum  of  feeling,  which  pervades  them,  and  to  which  they 
are  docile. 

Fourth,  this  supreme  law,  which  is  the  celestial  and  liv 
ing  harmony,  does  not  so  much  as  demand  that  the  special 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  233 

ideas  shall  surrender  their  peculiar  arbitrariness  and  caprice 
entirely;  for  that  would  be  self-destructive.  It  only  re 
quires  that  they  shall  influence  and  be  influenced  by  one 
another. 

Fifth,  in  what  measure  this  unification  acts,  seems  to  be 
regulated  only  by  special  rules;  or,  at  least,  we  cannot  in 
our  present  knowledge  say  how  far  it  goes.  But  it  may 
be  said  that,  judging  by  appearances,  the  amount  of  arbi 
trariness  in  the  phenomena  of  human  minds  is  neither 
altogether  trifling  nor  very  prominent. 

PERSONALITY 

Having  thus  endeavored  to  state  the  law  of  mind,  in  gen 
eral,  I  descend  to  the  consideration  of  a  particular  phe 
nomenon  which  is  remarkably  prominent  in  our  own  con 
sciousnesses,  that  of  personality.  A  strong  light  is  thrown 
upon  this  subject  by  recent  observations  of  double  and 
multiple  personality.  The  theory  which  at  one  time  seemed 
plausible  that  two  persons  in  one  body  corresponded  to  the 
two  halves  of  the  brain  will,  I  take  it,  now  be  universally 
acknowledged  to  be  insufficient.  But  that  which  these 
cases  make  quite  manifest  is  that  personality  is  some  kind 
of  co-ordination  or  connection  of  ideas.  Not  much  to  say, 
this,  perhaps.  Yet  when  we  consider  that,  according  to  the 
principle  which  we  are  tracing  out,  a  connection  between 
ideas  is  itself  a  general  idea,  and  that  a  general  idea  is  a 
living  feeling,  it  is  plain  that  we  have  at  least  taken  an  ap 
preciable  step  toward  the  understanding  of  personality. 
This  personality,  like  any  general  idea,  is  not  a  thing  to 
be  apprehended  in  an  instant.  It  has  to  be  lived  in  time; 


234  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

nor  can  any  finite  time  embrace  it  in  all  its  fullness.  Yet 
in  each  infinitesimal  interval  it  is  present  and  living,  though 
specially  colored  by  the  immediate  feelings  of  that  moment. 
Personality,  so  far  as  it  is  apprehended  in  a  moment,  is 
immediate  self-consciousness. 

But  the  word  co-ordination  implies  somewhat  more  than 
this;  it  implies  a  teleological  harmony  in  ideas,  and  in  the 
case  of  personality  this  teleology  is  more  than  a  mere  pur 
posive  pursuit  of  a  predeterminate  end;  it  is  a  develop 
mental  teleology.  This  is  personal  character.  A  general 
idea,  living  and  conscious  now,  it  is  already  determinative 
of  acts  in  the  future  to  an  extent  to  which  it  is  not  now 
conscious. 

This  reference  to  the  future  is  an  essential  element  of 
personality.  Were  the  ends  of  a  person  already  explicit, 
there  would  be  no  room  for  development,  fdr  growth,  for 
life;  and  consequently  there  would  be  no  personality.  The 
mere  carrying  out  of  predetermined  purposes  is  mechanical. 
This  remark  has  an  application  to  the  philosophy  of  religion. 
It  is  that  a  genuine  evolutionary  philosophy,  that  is,  one 
that  makes  the  principle  of  growth  a  primordial  element 
of  the  universe,  is  so  far  from  being  antagonistic  to  the  idea 
of  a  personal  creator,  that  it  is  really  inseparable  from  that 
idea;  while  a  necessitarian  religion  is  in  an  altogether  false 
position  and  is  destined  to  become  disintegrated.  But  a 
pseudo-evolutionism  which  enthrones  mechanical  law  above 
the  principle  of  growth,  is  at  once  scientifically  unsatis 
factory,  as  giving  no  possible  hint  of  how  the  universe  has 
come  about,  and  hostile  to  all  hopes  of  personal  relations 
to  God. 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  235 

COMMUNICATION 

Consistently  with  the  doctrine  laid  down  in  the  beginning 
of  this  paper,  I  am  bound  to  maintain  that  an  idea  can  only 
be  affected  by  an  idea  in  continuous  connection  with  it. 
By  anything  but  an  idea,  it  cannot  be  affected  at  all.  This 
obliges  me  to  say,  as  I  do  say,  on  other  grounds,  that  what 
we  call  matter  is  not  completely  dead,  but  is  merely  mind 
hide-bound  with  habits.  It  still  retains  the  element  of 
diversification;  and  in  that  diversification  there  is  life. 
When  an  idea  is  conveyed  from  one  mind  to  another,  it  is 
by  forms  of  combination  of  the  diverse  elements  of  nature, 
say  by  some  curious  symmetry,  or  by  some  union  of  a  tender 
color  with  a  refined  odor.  To  such  forms  the  law  of  me 
chanical  energy  has  no  application.  If  they  are  eternal, 
it  is  in  the  spirit  they  embody;  and  their  origin  cannot  be 
accounted  for  by  any  mechanical  necessity.  They  are  em 
bodied  ideas;  and  so  only  can  they  convey  ideas.  Precisely 
how  primary  sensations,  as  colors  and  tones,  are  excited, 
we  cannot  tell,  in  the  present  state  of  psychology.  But  in 
our  ignorance,  I  think  that  we  are  at  liberty  to  suppose 
that  they  arise  in  essentially  the  same  manner  as  the  other 
feelings,  called  secondary.  As  far  as  sight  and  hearing 
are  in  question,  we  know  that  they  are  only  excited  by  vi 
brations  of  inconceivable  complexity;  and  the  chemical 
senses  are  probably  not  more  simple.  Even  the  least  psy 
chical  of  peripheral  sensations,  that  of  pressure,  has  in  its 
excitation  conditions  which,  though  apparently  simple,  are 
seen  to  be  complicated  enough  when  we  consider  the  mole 
cules  and  their  attractions.  The  principle  with  which  I 


236  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

set  out  requires  me  to  maintain  that  these  feelings  are 
communicated  to  the  nerves  by  continuity,  so  that  there 
must  be  something  like  them  in  the  excitants  themselves. 
If  this  seems  extravagant,  it  is  to  be  remembered  that  it  is 
the  sole  possible  way  of  reaching  any  explanation  of  sen 
sation,  which  otherwise  must  be  pronounced  a  general  fact, 
absolutely  inexplicable  and  ultimate.  Now  absolute  in- 
explicability  is  a  hypothesis  which  sound  logic  refuses  under 
any  circumstances  to  justify. 

I  may  be  asked  whether  my  theory  would  be  favorable 
or  otherwise  to  telepathy.  I  have  no  decided  answer  to 
give  to  this.  At  first  sight,  it  seems  unfavorable.  Yet 
there  may  be  other  modes  of  continuous  connection  between 
minds  other  than  those  of  time  and  space. 

The  recognition  by  one  person  of  another's  personality 
takes  place  by  means  to  some  extent  identical  with  the  means 
by  which  he  is  conscious  of  his  own  personality.  The  idea 
of  the  second  personality,  which  is  as  much  as  to  say  that 
second  personality  itself,  enters  within  the  field  of  direct 
consciousness  of  the  first  person,  and  is  as  immediately 
perceived  as  his  ego,  though  less  strongly.  At  the  same 
time,  the  opposition  between  the  two  persons  is  perceived, 
so  that  the  externality  of  the  second  is  recognized. 

The  psychological  phenomena  of  intercommunication  be 
tween  two  minds  have  been  unfortunately  little  studied.  So 
that  it  is  impossible  to  say,  for  certain,  whether  they  are 
favorable  to  this  theory  or  not.  But  the  very  extraordinary 
insight  which  some  persons  are  able  to  gain  of  others  from 
indications  so  slight  that  it  is  difficult  to  ascertain  what 
they  are,  is  certainly  rendered  more  comprehensible  by  the 
view  here  taken. 


THE    LAW    OF    MIND  237 

A  difficulty  which  confronts  the  synechistic  philosophy  is 
this.  In  considering  personality,  that  philosophy  is  forced 
to  accept  the  doctrine  of  a  personal  God;  but  in  considering 
communication,  it  cannot  but  admit  that  if  there  is  a  per 
sonal  God,  we  must  have  a  direct  perception  of  that  person 
and  indeed  be  in  personal  communication  with  him.  Now, 
if  that  be  the  case,  the  question  arises  how  it  is  possible  that 
the  existence  of  this  being  should  ever  have  been  doubted 
by  anybody.  The  only  answer  that  I  can  at  present  make 
is  that  facts  that  stand  before  our  face  and  eyes  and  stare 
us  in  the  face  are  far  from  being,  in  all  cases,  the  ones  most 
easily  discerned.  That  has  been  remarked  from  time  im 
memorial. 

CONCLUSION 

I  have  thus  developed  as  well  as  I  could  in  a  little  space 
the  synechistic  philosophy,  as  applied  to  mind.  I  think 
that  I  have  succeeded  in  making  it  clear  that  this  doctrine 
gives  room  for  explanations  of  many  facts  which  without  it 
are  absolutely  and  hopelessly  inexplicable;  and  further  that 
it  carries  along  with  it  the  following  doctrines:  ist,  a  logi 
cal  realism  of  the  most  pronounced  type;  2nd,  objective 
idealism;  3rd,  tychism,  with  its  consequent  thoroughgoing 
evolutionism.  We  also  notice  that  the  doctrine  presents  no 
hindrances  to  spiritual  influences,  such  as  some  philosophies 
are  felt  to  do. 


IV.    MAN'S    GLASSY   ESSENCE1 

IN  The  Monist  for  January,  1891,  I  tried  to  show  what 
conceptions  ought  to  form  the  brick  and  mortar  of  a  phi 
losophical  system.  Chief  among  these  was  that  of  absolute 
chance  for  which  I  argued  again  in  last  April's  number.2 
In  July,  I  applied  another  fundamental  idea,  that  of  con 
tinuity,  to  the  law  of  mind.  Next  in  order,  I  have  to  eluci 
date,  from  the  point  of  view  chosen,  the  relation  between 
the  psychical  and  physical  aspects  of  a  substance. 

The  first  step  towards  this  ought,  I  think,  to  be  the  fram 
ing  of  a  molecular  theory  of  protoplasm.  But  before  doing 
that,  it  seems  indispensable  to  glance  at  the  constitution 
of  matter,  in  general.  We  shall,  thus,  unavoidably  make  a 
long  detour;  but,  after  all,  our  pains  will  not  be  wasted, 
for  the  problems  of  the  papers  that  are  to  follow  in  the  series 
will  call  for  the  consideration  of  the  same  question. 

All  physicists  are  rightly  agreed  the  evidence  is  over 
whelming  which  shows  all  sensible  matter  is  composed  of 
molecules  in  swift  motion  and  exerting  enormous  mutual 
attractions,  and  perhaps  repulsions,  too.  Even  Sir  William 
Thomson,  Lord  Kelvin,  who  wishes  to  explode  action  at  a 
distance  and  return  to  the  doctrine  of  a  plenum,  not  only 
speaks  of  molecules,  but  undertakes  to  assign  definite  mag- 

1  The  Monist,  October,  1892. 

2  I  am  rejoiced  to  find,  since  my  last  paper  was  printed,  that  a  phil 
osopher  as  subtle  and  profound  as  Dr.   Edmund  Montgomery  has  long 
been  arguing  for  the  same  element  in  the  universe.    Other  world-renowned 
thinkers,  as  M.  Renouvier  and  M.  Delboeuf,  appear  to  share  this  opinion. 

238 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  239 

nitudes  to  them.  The  brilliant  Judge  Stallo,  a  man  who  did 
not  always  rightly  estimate  his  own  qualities  in  accepting 
tasks  for  himself,  declared  war  upon  the  atomic  theory  in 
a  book  well  worth  careful  perusal.  To  the  old  arguments 
in  favor  of  atoms  which  he  found  in  Fechner's  monograph, 
he  was  able  to  make  replies  of  considerable  force,  though 
they  were  not  sufficient  to  destroy  those  arguments.  But 
against  modern  proofs  he  made  no  headway  at  all.  These 
set  out  from  the  mechanical  theory  of  heat.  Rumford's 
experiments  showed  that  heat  is  not  a  substance.  Joule 
demonstrated  that  it  was  a  form  of  energy.  The  heating 
of  gases  under  constant  volume,  and  other  facts  instanced 
by  Rankine,  proved  that  it  could  not  be  an  energy  of  strain. 
This  drove  physicists  to  the  conclusion  that  it  was  a  mode 
of  motion.  Then  it  was  remembered  that  John  Bernoulli 
had  shown  that  the  pressure  of  gases  could  be  accounted 
for  by  assuming  their  molecules  to  be  moving  uniformly  in 
rectilinear  paths.  The  same  hypothesis  was  now  seen  to 
account  for  Avogadro's  law,  that  in  equal  volumes  of  dif 
ferent  kinds  of  gases  exposed  to  the  same  pressure  and 
temperature  are  contained  equal  numbers  of  molecules. 
Shortly  after,  it  was  found  to  account  for  the  laws  of  diffu 
sion  and  viscosity  of  gases,  and  for  the  numerical  relation 
between  these  properties.  Finally,  Crookes's  radiometer 
furnished  the  last  link  in  the  strongest  chain  of  evidence 
which  supports  any  physical  hypothesis. 

Such  being  the  constitution  of  gases,  liquids  must  clearly 
be  bodies  in  which  the  molecules  wander  in  curvilinear 
paths,  while  in  solids  they  move  in  orbits  or  quasi-orbits. 
(See  my  definition  solid  II,  i,  in  the  Century  Dictionary.} 


240  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

We  see  that  the  resistance  to  compression  and  to  inter- 
penetration  between  sensible  bodies  is,  by  one  of  the  prime 
propositions  of  the  molecular  theory,  due  in  large  measure 
to  the  kinetical  energy  of  the  particles,  which  must  be 
supposed  to  be  quite  remote  from  one  another,  on  the  aver 
age,  even  in  solids.  This  resistance  is  no  doubt  influenced 
by  finite  attractions  and  repulsions  between  the  molecules. 
All  the  impenetrability  of  bodies  which  we  can  observe  is, 
therefore,  a  limited  impenetrability  due  to  kinetic  and 
positional  energy.  This  being  the  case,  we  have  no  logical 
right  to  suppose  that  absolute  impenetrability,  or  the  ex 
clusive  occupancy  of  space,  belongs  to  molecules  or  to 
atoms.  It  is  an  unwarranted  hypothesis,  not  a  vera  causa* 
Unless  we  are  to  give  up  the  theory  of  energy,  finite  posi 
tional  attractions  and  repulsions  between  molecules  must 
be  admitted.  Absolute  impenetrability  would  amount  to 
an  infinite  repulsion  at  a  certain  distance.  No  analogy  of 
known  phenomena  exists  to  excuse  such  a  wanton  violation 
of  the  principle  of  continuity  as  such  a  hypothesis  is.  In 
short,  we  are  logically  bound  to  adopt  the  Boscovichian  idea 
that  an  atom  is  simply  a  distribution  of  component  potential 
energy  throughout  space  (this  distribution  being  absolutely 
rigid),  combined  with  inertia.  The  potential  energy  be 
longs  to  two  molecules,  and  is  to  be  conceived  as  different 
between  molecules  A  and  B  from  what  it  is  between  mole 
cules  A  and  C.  The  distribution  of  energy  is  not  neces 
sarily  spherical.  Nay,  a  molecule  may  conceivably  have 
more  than  one  center;  it  may  even  have  a  central  curve, 

3  By  a  vera  causa,  in  the  logic  of  science,  is  meant  a  state  of  things 
known  to  exist  in  some  cases  and  supposed  to  exist  in  other  cases,  because 
it  would  account  for  observed  phenomena. 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  241 

returning  into  itself.  But  I  do  not  think  there  are  any 
observed  facts  pointing  to  such  multiple  or  linear  centers. 
On  the  other  hand,  many  facts  relating  to  crystals,  espe 
cially  those  observed  by  Voigt,4  go  to  show  that  the  distribu 
tion  of  energy  is  harmonical  but  not  concentric.  We  can 
easily  calculate  the  forces  which  such  atoms  must  exert 
upon  one  another  by  considering 5  that  they  are  equivalent 
to  aggregations  of  pairs  of  electrically  positive  and  negative 
points  infinitely  near  to  one  another.  About  such  an  atom 
there  would  be  regions  of  positive  and  of  negative  potential, 
and  the  number  and  distribution  of  such  regions  would 
determine  the  valency  of  the  atom,  a  number  which  it  is 
easy  to  see  would  in  many  cases  be  somewhat  indeterminate. 
I  must  not  dwell  further  upon  this  hypothesis,  at  present. 
In  another  paper,  its  consequences  will  be  further  con 
sidered. 

I  cannot  assume  that  the  students  of  philosophy  who 
read  this  magazine  are  thoroughly  versed  in  modern  molec 
ular  physics,  and,  therefore,  it  is  proper  to  mention  that 
the  governing  principle  in  this  branch  of  science  is  Clausius's 
law  of  the  virial.  I  will  first  state  the  law,  and  then  explain 
the  peculiar  terms  of  the  statement.  This  statement  is  that 
the  total  kinetic  energy  of  the  particles  of  a  system  in  sta 
tionary  motion  is  equal  to  the  total  virial.  By  a  system 
is  here  meant  a  number  of  particles  acting  upon  one  an 
other.6  Stationary  motion  is  a  quasi-orbital  motion  among 

4  Wiedemann,  Annalen,  1887-1889. 

5  See    Maxwell     on    Spherical    Harmonics,    in    his    Ekctritity    and 
Magnetism. 

6  The  word  system  has  three  peculiar  meanings  in  mathematics.    (4.) 
It  means  an  orderly  exposition  of  the  truths  of  astronomy,  and  hence 


242  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

a  system  of  particles  so  that  none  of  them  are  removed  to 
indefinitely  great  distances  nor  acquire  indefinitely  great 
velocities.  The  kinetic  energy  of  a  particle  is  the  work 
which  would  be  required  to  bring  it  to  rest,  independently 
of  any  forces  which  may  be  acting  upon  it.  The  virial  of 
a  pair  of  particles  is  half  the  work  which  the  force  which 
actually  operates  between  them  would  do  if,  being  inde 
pendent  of  the  distance,  it  were  to  bring  them  together. 
The  equation  of  the  virial  is 


Here  m  is  the  mass  of  a  particle,  v  its  velocity,  R  is  the 
attraction  between  two  particles,  and  r  is  the  distance  be 
tween  them.  The  sign  2  on  the  left  hand  side  signifies 
that  the  values  of  mv2  are  to  be  summed  for  all  the  par 
ticles,  and  SS  on  the  right  hand  side  signifies  that  the 
values  of  Rr  are  to  be  summed  for  all  the  pairs  of  particles. 
If  there  is  an  external  pressure  P  (as  from  the  atmosphere) 
upon  the  system,  and  the  volume  of  vacant  space  within 
the  boundary  of  that  pressure  is  F,  then  the  virial  must  be 
understood  as  including  f  PF,  so  that  the  equation  is 


There  is  strong  (if  not  demonstrative)  reason  for  thinking 
that  the  temperature  of  any  body  above  the  absolute  zero 
(—273°  C.),  is  proportional  to  the  average  kinetic  energy 

a  theory  of  the  motions  of  the  stars;  as  the  Ptolemaic  system,  the  Coper- 
nican  system.  This  is  much  like  the  sense  in  which  we  speak  of  the 
Calvinistic  system  of  theology,  the  Kantian  system  of  philosophy,  etc. 
(J?.)  It  means  the  aggregate  of  the  planets  considered  as  all  moving  in 
somewhat  the  same  way,  as  the  solar  system;  and  hence  any  aggregate 
of  particles  moving  under  mutual  forces.  (C.)  It  means  a  number  of 
forces  acting  simultaneously  upon  a  number  of  particles. 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  243 

of  its  molecules,  or  say  ad,  where  a  is  a  constant  and  0  is 
the  absolute  temperature.  Hence,  we  may  write  the  equa 
tion 

a6  =  J^raT2  =  fPF  +  iSJRr 

where  the  heavy  lines  above  the  different  expressions  signify 
that  the  average  values  for  single  molecules  are  to  be  taken. 
In  1872,  a  student  in  the  University  of  Ley  den,  Van  der 
Waals,  propounded  in  his  thesis  for  the  doctorate  a  special 
ization  of  the  equation  of  the  virial  which  has  since  attracted 
great  attention.  Namely,  he  writes  it 


The  quantity  b  is  the  volume  of  a  molecule,  which  he  sup 
poses  to  be  an  impenetrable  body,  and  all  the  virtue  of  the 
equation  lies  in  this  term  which  makes  the  equation  a  cubic 
in  V,  which  is  required  to  account  for  the  shape  of  certain 
isothermal  curves.7  But  if  the  idea  of  an  impenetrable 
atom  is  illogical,  that  of  an  impenetrable  molecule  is  almost 
absurd.  For  the  kinetical  theory  of  matter  teaches  us  that 
a  molecule  is  like  a  solar  system  or  star-cluster  in  miniature. 
Unless  we  suppose  that  in  all  heating  of  gases  and  vapors 
internal  work  is  performed  upon  the  molecules,  implying 
that  their  atoms  are  at  considerable  distances,  the  whole 
kinetical  theory  of  gases  falls  to  the  ground.  As  for  the 
term  added  to  P,  there  is  no  more  than  a  partial  and  roughly 
approximative  justification  for  it.  Namely,  let  us  imagine 

7  But,  in  fact,  an  inspection  of  these  curves  is  sufficient  to  show  that 
they  are  of  a  higher  degree  than  the  third.  For  they  have  the  line  V=  o, 
or  some  line  V  a  constant  for  an  asymptote,  while  for  small  values  of 
P,  the  values  of  d2p/(dV)2  are  positive. 


244  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

two  spheres  described  round  a  particle  as  their  center, 
the  radius  of  the  larger  being  so  great  as  to  include  all  the 
particles  whose  action  upon  the  center  is  sensible,  while 
the  radius  of  the  smaller  is  so  large  that  a  good  many  mole 
cules  are  included  within  it.  The  possibility  of  describing 
such  a  sphere  as  the  outer  one  implies  that  the  attraction 
of  the  particles  varies  at  some  distances  inversely  as  some 
higher  power  of  the  distance  than  the  cube,  or,  to  speak 
more  clearly,  that  the  attraction  multiplied  by  the  cube 
of  the  distance  diminishes  as  the  distance  increases;  for  the 
number  of  particles  at  a  given  distance  from  any  one  par 
ticle  is  proportionate  to  the  square  of  that  distance  and 
each  of  these  gives  a  term  of  the  virial  which  is  the  product 
of  the  attraction  into  the  distance.  Consequently,  unless 
the  attraction  multiplied  by  the  cube  of  the  distance  di 
minished  so  rapidly  with  the  distance  as  soon  to  become  in 
sensible,  no  such  outer  sphere  as  is  supposed  could  be  de 
scribed.  However,  ordinary  experience  shows  that  such  a 
sphere  is  possible ;  and  consequently  there  must  be  distances 
at  which  the  attraction  does  thus  rapidly  diminish  as  the 
distance  increases.  The  two  spheres,  then,  being  so  drawn, 
consider  the  virial  of  the  central  particle  due  to  the  particles 
between  them.  Let  the  density  of  the  substance  be  in 
creased,  say,  N  times.  Then,  for  every  turn,  Rr,  of  the 
virial  before  the  condensation,  there  will  be  N  terms  of  the 
same  magnitude  after  the  condensation.  Hence,  the  virial 
of  each  particle  will  be  proportional  to  the  density,  and  the 
equation  of  the  virial  becomes 

aO  =  PV  +  =' 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  245 

This  omits  the  virial  within  the  inner  sphere,  the  radius  of 
which  is  so  taken  that  within  that  distance  the  number  of 
particles  is  not  proportional  to  the  number  in  a  large  sphere. 
For  Van  der  Waals  this  radius  is  the  diameter  of  his  hard 
molecules,  which  assumption  gives  his  equation.  But  it  is 
plain  that  the  attraction  between  the  molecules  must  to 
a  certain  extent  modify  their  distribution,  unless  some  pe 
culiar  conditions  are  fulfilled.  The  equation  of  Van  der 
Waals  can  be  approximately  true,  therefore,  only  for  a  gas. 
In  a  solid  or  liquid  condition,  in  which  the  removal  of  a 
small  amount  of  pressure  has  little  effect  on  the  volume, 
and  where  consequently  the  virial  must  be  much  greater 
than  PV,  the  virial  must  increase  with  the  volume.  For 
suppose  we  had  a  substance  in  a  critical  condition  in  which 
an  increase  of  the  volume  would  diminish  the  virial  more 
than  it  would  increase  | PV.  If  we  were  forcibly  to  diminish 
the  volume  of  such  a  substance,  when  the  temperature  be 
came  equalized,  the  pressure  which  it  could  withstand  would 
be  less  than  before,  and  it  would  be  still  further  condensed, 
and  this  would  go  on  indefinitely  until  a  condition  were 
reached  in  which  an  increase  of  volume  would  increase 
\PV  more  than  it  would  decrease  the  virial.  In  the  case 
of  solids,  at  least,  P  may  be  zero;  so  that  the  state  reached 
would  be  one  in  which  the  virial  increases  with  the  volume, 
or  the  attraction  between  the  particles  does  not  increase  so 
fast  with  a  diminution  of  their  distance  as  it  would  if  the 
attraction  were  inversely  as  the  distance. 

Almost  contemporaneously  with  Van  der  Waals's  paper, 
another  remarkable  thesis  for  the  doctorate  was  presented 
at  Paris  by  Amagat.  It  related  to  the  elasticity  and  ex- 


246  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

pansion  of  gases,  and  to  this  subject  the  superb  experi 
menter,  its  author,  has  devoted  his  whole  subsequent  life. 
Especially  interesting  are  his  observations  of  the  volumes  of 
ethylene  and  of  carbonic  acid  at  temperatures  from  20°  to 
1 00°  and  at  pressures  ranging  from  an  ounce  to  5000  pounds 
to  the  square  inch.  As  soon  as  Amagat  had  obtained  these 
results,  he  remarked  that  the  "  coefficient  of  expansion  at 
constant  volume,"  as  it  is  absurdly  called,  that  is,  the  rate 
of  variation  of  the  pressure  with  the  temperature,  was  very 
nearly  constant  for  each  volume.  This  accords  with  the 
equation  of  the  virial,  which  gives 

dp  _    a,  _  d2Rr 
d6      v~      dO   ' 

IsTow,  the  virial  must  be  nearly  independent  of  the  tempera 
ture,  and,  therefore,  the  last  term  almost  disappears.  The 
virial  would  not  be  quite  independent  of  the  temperature, 
because  if  the  temperature  (i.e.,  the  square  of  the  velocity 
of  the  molecules)  is  lowered,  and  the  pressure  correspond 
ingly  lowered,  so  as  to  make  the  volume  the  same,  the  at 
tractions  of  the  molecules  will  have  more  time  to  produce 
their  effects,  and  consequently,  the  pairs  of  molecules  the 
closest  together  will  be  held  together  longer  and  closer; 
so  that  the  virial  will  generally  be  increased  by  a  decrease 
of  temperature.  Now,  Amagat's  experiments  do  show  an 
excessively  minute  effect  of  this  sort,  at  least,  when  the 
volumes  are  not  too  small.  However,  the  observations  are 
well  enough  satisfied  by  assuming  the  "  coefficient  of  ex 
pansion  at  constant  volume  "  to  consist  wholly  of  the  first 
term,  a/V.  Thus,  Amagat's  experiments  enable  us  to  de- 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  247 

termine  the  values  of  a  and  thence  to  calculate  the  virial; 
and  this  we  find  varies  for  carbonic  acid  gas  nearly  inversely 
to  F°*9.  There  is,  thus,  a  rough  approximation  to  satisfy 
ing  Van  der  Waals's  equation.  But  the  most  interesting 
result  of  Amagat's  experiments,  for  our  purpose  at  any 
rate,  is  that  the  quantity  a,  though  nearly  constant  for  any 
one  volume,  differs  considerably  with  the  volume,  nearly 
doubling  when  the  volume  is  reduced  fivefold.  This  can 
only  indicate  that  the  mean  kinetic  energy  of  a  given  mass 
of  the  gas  for  a  given  temperature  is  greater  the  more  the 
gas  is  compressed.  But  the  laws  of  mechanics  appear  to 
enjoin  that  the  mean  kinetic  energy  of  a  moving  particle 
shall  be  constant  at  any  given  temperature.  The  only 
escape  from  contradiction,  then,  is  to  suppose  that  the 
mean  mass  of  a  moving  particle  diminishes  upon  the  con 
densation  of  the  gas.  In  other  words,  many  of  the  mole 
cules  are  dissociated,  or  broken  up  into  atoms  or  sub- 
molecules.  The  idea  that  dissociation  should  be  favored 
by  diminishing  the  volume  will  be  pronounced  by  physicists, 
at  first  blush,  as  contrary  to  all  our  experience.  But  it 
must  be  remembered  that  the  circumstances  we  are  speaking 
of,  that  of  a  gas  under  fifty  or  more  atmospheres  pressure, 
are  also  unusual.  That  the  "  coefficient  of  expansion  under 
constant  volume  "  when  multiplied  by  the  volumes  should 
increase  with  a  decrement  of  the  volume  is  also  quite  con 
trary  to  ordinary  experience;  yet  it  undoubtedly  takes  place 
in  all  gases  under  great  pressure.  Again,  the  doctrine  of 
Arrhenius  8  is  now  generally  accepted,  that  the  molecular 

8  Anticipated  by  Clausius  as  long  ago  as  1857;  and  by  Williamson  in 
1851. 


248  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

conductivity  of  an  electrolyte  is  proportional  to  the  dis 
sociation  of  ions.  Now  the  molecular  conductivity  of  a 
fused  electrolyte  is  usually  superior  to  that  of  a  solution. 
Here  is  a  case,  then,  in  which  diminution  of  volume  is  ac 
companied  by  increased  dissociation. 

The  truth  is  that  several  different  kinds  of  dissociation 
have  to  be  distinguished.  In  the  first  place,  there  is  the 
dissociation  of  a  chemical  molecule  to  form  chemical  mole 
cules  under  the  regular  action  of  chemical  laws.  This  may 
be  a  double  decomposition,  as  when  iodhydric  acid  is  dis 
sociated,  according  to  the  formula 

II; 


or,  it  may  be  a  simple  decomposition,  as  when  pentachloride 
of  phosphorus  is  dissociated  according  to  the  formula 


All  these  dissociations  require,  according  to  the  laws  of 
thermo-chemistry,  an  elevated  temperature.  In  the  second 
place,  there  is  the  dissociation  of  a  physically  polymerous 
molecule,  that  is,  of  several  chemical  molecules  joined  by 
physical  attractions.  This  I  am  inclined  to  suppose  is  a 
common  concomitant  of  the  heating  of  solids  and  liquids; 
for  in  these  bodies  there  is  no  increase  of  compressibility 
with  the  temperature  at  all  comparable  with  the  increase 
of  the  expansibility.  But,  in  the  third  place,  there  is  the 
dissociation  with  which  we  are  now  concerned,  which  must 
be  supposed  to  be  a  throwing  off  of  unsaturated  sub-mole 
cules  or  atoms  from  the  molecule.  The  molecule  may,  as 
I  have  said,  be  roughly  likened  to  a  solar  system.  As  such, 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  249 

molecules  are  able  to  produce  perturbations  of  one  another's 
internal  motions;  and  in  this  way  a  planet,  i.e.,  a  sub-mole 
cule,  will  occasionally  get  thrown  off  and  wander  about  by 
itself,  till  it  finds  another  unsaturated  sub-molecule  with 
which  it  can  unite.  Such  dissociation  by  perturbation  will 
naturally  be  favored  by  the  proximity  of  the  molecules  to 
one  another. 

Let  us  now  pass  to  the  consideration  of  that  special  sub 
stance,  or  rather  class  of  substances,  whose  properties  form 
the  chief  subject  of  botany  and  of  zoology,  as  truly  as  those 
of  the  silicates  form  the  chief  subject  of  mineralogy:  I  mean 
the  life-slimes,  or  protoplasm.  Let  us  begin  by  cataloguing 
the  general  characters  of  these  slimes.  They  one  and  all 
exist  in  two  states  of  aggregation,  a  solid  or  nearly  solid 
state  and  a  liquid  or  nearly  liquid  state;  but  they  do  not 
pass  from  the  former  to  the  latter  by  ordinary  fusion.  They 
are  readily  decomposed  by  heat,  especially  in  the  liquid 
state;  nor  will  they  bear  any  considerable  degree  of  cold. 
All  their  vital  actions  take  place  at  temperatures  very  little 
below  the  point  of  decomposition.  This  extreme  instability 
is  one  of  numerous  facts  which  demonstrate  the  chemical 
complexity  of  protoplasm.  Every  chemist  will  agree  that 
they  are  far  more  complicated  than  the  albumens.  Now, 
albumen  is  estimated  to  contain  in  each  molecule  about  a 
thousand  atoms;  so  that  it  is  natural  to  suppose  that  the 
protoplasms  contain  several  thousands.  We  know  that 
while  they  are  chiefly  composed  of  oxygen,  hydrogen,  car 
bon,  and  nitrogen,  a  large  number  of  other  elements  enter 
into  living  bodies  in  small  proportions;  and  it  is  likely  that 
most  of  these  enter  into  the  composition  of  protoplasms. 


250  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

Now,  since  the  numbers  of  chemical  varieties  increase  at 
an  enormous  rate  with  the  number  of  atoms  per  molecule, 
so  that  there  are  certainly  hundreds  of  thousands  of  sub 
stances  whose  molecules  contain  twenty  atoms  or  fewer, 
we  may  well  suppose  that  the  number  of  protoplasmic 
substances  runs  into  the  billions  or  trillions.  Professor 
Cayley  has  given  a  mathematical  theory  of  "  trees,"  with 
a  view  of  throwing  a  light  upon  such  questions;  and  in  that 
light  the  estimate  of  trillions  (in  the  English  sense)  seems 
immoderately  moderate.  It  is  true  that  an  opinion  has 
been  emitted,  and  defended  among  biologists,  that  there  is 
but  one  kind  of  protoplasm;  but  the  observations  of  biolo 
gists,  themselves,  have  almost  exploded  that  hypothesis, 
which  from  a  chemical  standpoint  appears  utterly  incredible. 
The  anticipation  of  the  chemist  would  decidedly  be  that 
enough  different  chemical  substances  having  protoplasmic 
characters  might  be  formed  to  account,  not  only  for  the 
differences  between  nerve-slime  and  muscle-slime,  between 
whale-slime  and  lion-slime,  but  also  for  those  minuter  per 
vasive  variations  which  characterize  different  breeds  and 
single  individuals. 

Protoplasm,  when  quiescent,  is,  broadly  speaking,  solid; 
but  when  it  is  disturbed  in  an  appropriate  way,  or  some 
times  even  spontaneously  without  external  disturbance,  it 
becomes,  broadly  speaking,  liquid.  A  moner  in  this  state 
is  seen  under  the  microscope  to  have  streams  within  its 
matter;  a  slime-mould  slowly  flows  by  force  of  gravity. 
The  liquefaction  starts  from  the  point  of  disturbance  and 
spreads  through  the  mass.  This  spreading,  however,  is  not 
uniform  in  all  directions;  on  the  contrary,  it  takes  at  one 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  251 

time  one  course,  at  another  another,  through  the  homo 
geneous  mass,  in  a  manner  that  seems  a  little  mysterious. 
The  cause  of  disturbance  being  removed,  these  motions 
gradually  (with  higher  kinds  of  protoplasm,  quickly)  cease, 
and  the  slime  returns  to  its  solid  condition. 

The  liquefaction  of  protoplasm  is  accompanied  by  a  me 
chanical  phenomenon.  Namely,  some  kinds  exhibit  a  ten 
dency  to  draw  themselves  up  into  a  globular  form.  This 
happens  particularly  with  the  contents  of  muscle-cells.  The 
prevalent  opinion,  founded  on  some  of  the  most  exquisite 
experimental  investigations  that  the  history  of  science  can 
show,  is  undoubtedly  that  the  contraction  of  muscle-cells 
is  due  to  osmotic  pressure;  and  it  must  be  allowed  that 
that  is  a  factor  in  producing  the  effect.  But  it  does  not 
seem  to  me  that  it  satisfactorily  accounts  even  for  the  phe 
nomena  of  muscular  contraction;  and  besides,  even  naked 
slimes  often  draw  up  in  the  same  way.  In  this  case,  we 
seem  to  recognize  an  increase  of  the  surface-tension.  In 
some  cases,  too,  the  reverse  action  takes  place,  extraordinary 
pseudopodia  being  put  forth,  as  if  the  surface-tension  were 
diminished  in  spots.  Indeed,  such  a  slime  always  has  a  sort 
of  skin,  due  no  doubt  to  surface-tension,  and  this  seems  to 
give  way  at  the  point  where  a  pseudopodium  is  put  forth. 

Long-continued  or  frequently  repeated  liquefaction  of 
the  protoplasm  results  in  an  obstinate  retention  of  the  solid 
state,  which  we  call  fatigue.  On  the  other  hand,  repose 
in  this  state,  if  not  too  much  prolonged,  restores  the  lique- 
fiability.  These  are  both  important  functions. 

The  life-slimes  have,  further,  the  peculiar  property  of 
growing.  Crystals  also  grow;  their  growth,  however,  con- 


252  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

sists  merely  in  attracting  matter  like  their  own  from  the 
circumambient  fluid.  To  suppose  the  growth  of  protoplasm 
of  the  same  nature,  would  be  to  suppose  this  substance  to 
be  spontaneously  generated  in  copious  supplies  wherever 
food  is  in  solution.  Certainly,  it  must  be  granted  that 
protoplasm  is  but  a  chemical  substance,  and  that  there  is 
no  reason  why  it  should  not  be  formed  synthetically  like 
any  other  chemical  substance.  Indeed,  Clifford  has  clearly 
shown  that  we  have  overwhelming  evidence  that  it  is  so 
formed.  But  to  say  that  such  formation  is  as  regular  and 
frequent  as  the  assimilation  of  food  is  quite  another  matter. 
It  is  more  consonant  with  the  facts  of  observation  to  sup 
pose  that  assimilated  protoplasm  is  formed  at  the  instant  of 
assimilation,  under  the  influence  of  the  protoplasm  already 
present.  For  each  slime  in  its  growth  preserves  its  distinc 
tive  characters  with  wonderful  truth,  nerve-slime  growing 
nerve-slime  and  muscle-slime  muscle-slime,  lion-slime  grow 
ing  lion-slime,  and  all  the  varieties  of  breeds  and  even  in 
dividual  characters  being  preserved  in  the  growth.  Now 
it  is  too  much  to  suppose  there  are  billions  of  different  kinds 
of  protoplasm  floating  about  wherever  there  is  food. 

The  frequent  liquefaction  of  protoplasm  increases  its 
power  of  assimilating  food;  so  much  so,  indeed,  that  it  is 
questionable  whether  in  the  solid  form  it  possesses  this 
power. 

The  life-slime  wastes  as  well  as  grows;  and  this  too  takes 
place  chiefly  if  not  exclusively  in  its  liquid  phases. 

Closely  connected  with  growth  is  reproduction;  and 
though  in  higher  forms  this  is  a  specialized  function,  it  is 
universally  true  that  wherever  there  is  protoplasm,  there  is, 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  253 

will  be,  or  has  been  a  power  of  reproducing  that  same  kind 
of  protoplasm  in  a  separated  organism.  Reproduction 
seems  to  involve  the  union  of  two  sexes;  though  it  is  not 
demonstrable  that  this  is  always  requisite. 

Another  physical  property  of  protoplasm  is  that  of  taking 
habits.  The  course  which  the  spread  of  liquefaction  has 
taken  in  the  past  is  rendered  thereby  more  likely  to  be  taken 
in  the  future;  although  there  is  no  absolute  certainly  that 
the  same  path  will  be  followed  again. 

Very  extraordinary,  certainly,  are  all  these  properties  of 
protoplasm;  as  extraordinary  as  indubitable.  But  the  one 
which  has  next  to  be  mentioned,  while  equally  undeniable, 
is  infinitely  more  wonderful.  It  is  that  protoplasm  feels. 
We  have  no  direct  evidence  that  this  is  true  of  protoplasm 
universally,  and  certainly  some  kinds  feel  far  more  than 
others.  But  there  is  a  fair  analogical  inference  that  all 
protoplasm  feels.  It  not  only  feels  but  exercises  all  the 
functions  of  mind. 

Such  are  the  properties  of  protoplasm.  The  problem  is 
to  find  a  hypothesis  of  the  molecular  constitution  of  this 
compound  which  will  account  for  these  properties,  one 
and  all. 

Some  of  them  are  obvious  results  of  the  excessively  com 
plicated  constitution  of  the  protoplasm  molecule.  All  very 
complicated  substances  are  unstable;  and  plainly  a  mole 
cule  of  several  thousand  atoms  may  be  separated  in  many 
ways  into  two  parts  in  each  of  which  the  polar  chemical 
forces  are  very  nearly  saturated.  In  the  solid  protoplasm, 
as  in  other  solids,  the  molecules  must  be  supposed  to  be 
moving  as  it  were  in  orbits,  or,  at  least,  so  as  not  to  wander 


254  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

indefinitely.  But  this  solid  cannot  be  melted,  for  the  same 
reason  that  starch  cannot  be  melted;  because  an  amount  of 
heat  insufficient  to  make  the  entire  molecules  wander  is 
sufficient  to  break  them  up  completely  and  cause  them  to 
form  new  and  simpler  molecules.  But  when  one  of  the 
molecules  is  disturbed,  even  if  it  be  not  quite  thrown  out 
of  its  orbit  at  first,  sub-molecules  of  perhaps  several  hun 
dred  atoms  each  are  thrown  off  from  it.  These  will  soon 
acquire  the  same  mean  kinetic  energy  as  the  others,  and, 
therefore,  velocities  several  times  as  great.  They  will 
naturally  begin  to  wander,  and  in  wandering  will  perturb 
a  great  many  other  molecules  and  cause  them  in  their  turn 
to  behave  like  the  one  originally  deranged.  So  many  mole 
cules  will  thus  be  broken  up,  that  even  those  that  are  in 
tact  will  no  longer  be  restrained  within  orbits,  but  will  wan 
der  about  freely.  This  is  the  usual  condition  of  a  liquid, 
as  modern  chemists  understand  it;  for  in  all  electrolytic 
liquids  there  is  considerable  dissociation. 

But  this  process  necessarily  chills  the  substance,  not 
merely  on  account  of  the  heat  of  chemical  combination, 
but  still  more  because  the  number  of  separate  particles 
being  greatly  increased,  the  mean  kinetic  energy  must  be 
less.  The  substance  being  a  bad  conductor,  this  heat  is 
not  at  once  restored.  Now  the  particles  moving  more 
slowly,  the  attractions  between  them  have  time  to  take 
effect,  and  they  approach  the  condition  of  equilibrium. 
But  their  dynamic  equilibrium  is  found  in  the  restoration 
of  the  solid  condition,  which,  therefore,  takes  place,  if  the 
disturbance  is  not  kept  up. 

When  a  body  is  in  the  solid  condition,  most  of  its  mole- 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  255 

cules  must  be  moving  at  the  same  rate,  or,  at  least,  at  certain 
regular  sets  of  rates;  otherwise  the  orbital  motion  would  not 
be  preserved.  The  distances  of  neighboring  molecules 
must  always  be  kept  between  a  certain  maximum  and  a 
certain  minimum  value.  But  if,  without  absorption  of 
heat,  the  body  be  thrown  into  a  liquid  condition,  the  dis 
tances  of  neighboring  molecules  will  be  far  more  unequally 
distributed,  and  an  effect  upon  the  virial  will  result.  The 
chilling  of  protoplasm  upon  its  liquefaction  must  also  be 
taken  into  account.  The  ordinary  effect  will  no  doubt  be 
to  increase  the  cohesion  and  with  that  the  surface-tension, 
so  that  the  mass  will  tend  to  draw  itself  up.  But  in  special 
cases,  the  virial  will  be  increased  so  much  that  the  surface- 
tension  will  be  diminished  at  points  where  the  temperature 
is  first  restored.  In  that  case,  the  outer  film  will  give  way 
and  the  tension  at  other  places  will  aid  in  causing  the  gen 
eral  fluid  to  be  poured  out  at  those  points,  forming 
pseudopodia. 

When  the  protoplasm  is  in  a  liquid  state,  and  then  only, 
a  solution  of  food  is  able  to  penetrate  its  mass  by  diffusion. 
The  protoplasm  is  then  considerably  dissociated;  and  so  is 
the  food,  like  all  dissolved  matter.  If  then  the  separated 
and  unsaturated  sub-molecules  of  the  food  happen  to  be 
of  the  same  chemical  species  as  sub-molecules  of  the  proto 
plasm,  they  may  unite  with  other  sub-molecules  of  the 
protoplasm  to  form  new  molecules,  in  such  a  fashion  that 
when  the  solid  state  is  resumed,  there  may  be  more  mole 
cules  of  protoplasm  than  there  were  at  the  beginning.  It 
is  like  the  jackknife  whose  blade  and  handle,  after  having 
been  severally  lost  and  replaced,  were  found  and  put  to 
gether  to  make  a  new  knife. 


256  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

We  have  seen  that  protoplasm  is  chilled  by  liquefaction, 
and  that  this  brings  it  back  to  the  solid  state,  when  the  heat 
is  recovered.  This  series  of  operations  must  be  very  rapid 
in  the  case  of  nerve-slime  and  even  of  muscle-slime,  and 
may  account  for  the  unsteady  or  vibratory  character  of 
their  action.  Of  course,  if  assimilation  takes  place,  the 
heat  of  combination,  which  is  probably  trifling,  is  gained. 
On  the  other  hand,  if  work  is  done,  whether  by  nerve  or  by 
muscle,  loss  of  energy  must  take  place.  In  the  case  of 
the  muscle,  the  mode  by  which  the  instantaneous  part  of 
the  fatigue  is  brought  about  is  easily  traced  out.  If  when 
the  muscle  contracts  it  be  under  stress,  it  will  contract  less 
than  it  otherwise  would  do,  and  there  will  be  a  loss  of  heat. 
It  is  like  an  engine  which  should  work  by  dissolving  salt 
in  water  and  using  the  contraction  during  the  solution  to 
lift  a  weight,  the  salt  being  recovered  afterwards  by  dis 
tillation.  But  the  major  part  of  fatigue  has  nothing  to  do 
with  the  correlation  of  forces.  A  man  must  labor  hard  to 
do  in  a  quarter  of  an  hour  the  work  which  draws  from  him 
enough  heat  to  cool  his  body  by  a  single  degree.  Mean 
time,  he  will  be  getting  heated,  he  will  be  pouring  out  extra 
products  of  combustion,  perspiration,  etc.,  and  he  will  be 
driving  the  blood  at  an  accelerated  rate  through  minute 
tubes  at  great  expense.  Yet  all  this  will  have  little  to  do 
with  his  fatigue.  He  may  sit  quietly  at  his  table  writing, 
doing  practically  no  physical  work  at  all,  and  yet  in  a  few 
hours  be  terribly  fagged.  This  seems  to  be  owing  to  the 
deranged  sub-molecules  of  the  nerve-slime  not  having  had 
time  to  settle  back  into  their  proper  combinations.  When 
such  sub-molecules  are  thrown  out,  as  they  must  be  from 
time  to  time,  there  is  so  much  waste  of  material. 


I 

MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  257 

In  order  that  a  sub-molecule  of  food  may  be  thoroughly 
and  firmly  assimilated  into  a  broken  molecule  of  proto 
plasm,  it  is  necessary  not  only  that  it  should  have  precisely 
the  right  chemical  composition,  but  also  that  it  should  be 
at  precisely  the  right  spot  at  the  right  time  and  should  be 
moving  in  precisely  the  right  direction  with  precisely  the 
right  velocity.  If  all  these  conditions  are  not  fulfilled,  it 
will  be  more  loosely  retained  than  the  other  parts  of  the 
molecule;  and  every  time  it  comes  round  into  the  situation 
in  which  it  was  drawn  in,  relatively  to  the  other  parts  of 
that  molecule  and  to  such  others  as  were  near  enough  to 
be  factors  in  the  action,  it  will  be  in  special  danger  of  being 
thrown  out  again.  Thus,  when  a  partial  liquefaction  of 
the  protoplasm  takes  place  many  times  to  about  the  same 
extent,  it  will,  each  time,  be  pretty  nearly  the  same  mole 
cules  that  were  last  drawn  in  that  are  now  thrown  out. 
They  will  be  thrown  out,  too,  in  about  the  same  way,  as  to 
position,  direction  of  motion,  and  velocity,  in  which  they 
were  drawn  in;  and  this  will  be  in  about  the  same  course 
that  the  ones  last  before  them  were  thrown  out.  Not  ex 
actly,  however;  for  the  very  cause  of  their  being  thrown 
off  so  easily  is  their  not  having  fulfilled  precisely  the  con 
ditions  of  stable  retention.  Thus,  the  law  of  habit  is  ac 
counted  for,  and  with  it  its  peculiar  characteristic  of  not 
acting  with  exactitude. 

It  seems  to  me  that  this  explanation  of  habit,  aside  from 
the  question  of  its  truth  or  falsity,  has  a  certain  value  as  an 
addition  to  our  little  store  of  mechanical  examples  of  actions 
analogous  to  habit.  All  the  others,  so  far  as  I  know,  are 
either  statical  or  else  involve  forces  which,  taking  only  the 


258  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

sensible  motions  into  account,  violate  the  law  of  energy. 
It  is  so  with  the  stream  that  wears  its  own  bed.  Here,  the 
sand  is  carried  to  its  most  stable  situation  and  left  there. 
The  law  of  energy  forbids  this;  for  when  anything  reaches 
a  position  of  stable  equilibrium,  its  momentum  will  be  at 
a  maximum,  so  that  it  can  according  to  this  law  only  be 
left  at  rest  in  an  unstable  situation.  In  all  the  statical 
illustrations,  too,  things  are  brought  into  certain  states  and 
left  there.  A  garment  receives  folds  and  keeps  them;  that 
is,  its  limit  of  elasticity  is  exceeded.  This  failure  to  spring 
back  is  again  an  apparent  violation  of  the  law  of  energy; 
for  the  substance  will  not  only  not  spring  back  of  itself 
(which  might  be  due  to  an  unstable  equilibrium  being 
reached)  but  will  not  even  do  so  when  an  impulse  that  way 
is  applied  to  it.  Accordingly,  Professor  James  says,  "  the 
phenomena  of  habit  .  .  .  are  due  to  the  plasticity  of  the 
.  .  .  materials."  Now,  plasticity  of  materials  means  the 
having  of  a  low  limit  of  elasticity.  (See  the  Century 
Dictionary,  under  solid.)  But  the  hypothetical  constitu 
tion  of  protoplasm  here  proposed  involves  no  forces  but 
attractions  and  repulsions  strictly  following  the  law  of 
energy.  The  action  here,  that  is,  the  throwing  of  an  atom 
out  of  its  orbit  in  a  molecule,  and  the  entering  of  a  new 
atom  into  nearly,  but  not  quite  the  same  orbit,  is  somewhat 
similar  to  the  molecular  actions  which  may  be  supposed 
to  take  place  in  a  solid  strained  beyond  its  limit  of  elasticity. 
Namely,  in  that  case  certain  molecules  must  be  thrown  out 
of  their  orbits,  to  settle  down  again  shortly  after  into  new 
orbits.  In  short,  the  plastic  solid  resembles  protoplasm  in 
being  partially  and  temporarily  liquefied  by  a  slight  me- 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  259 

chanical  force.  But  the  taking  of  a  set  by  a  solid  body 
has  but  a  moderate  resemblance  to  the  taking  of  a  habit, 
inasmuch  as  the  characteristic  feature  of  the  latter,  its 
inexactitude  and  want  of  complete  deter minacy,  is  not  so 
marked  in  the  former,  if  it  can  be  said  to  be  present  there, 
at  all. 

The  t^uth  is  that  though  the  molecular  explanation  of 
habit  is  pretty  vague  on  the  mathematical  side,  there  can 
be  no  doubt  that  systems  of  atoms  having  polar  forces 
would  act  substantially  in  that  manner,  and  the  explanation 
is  even  too  satisfactory  to  suit  the  convenience  of  an  advo 
cate  of  tychism.  For  it  may  fairly  be  urged  that  since  the 
phenomena  of  habit  may  thus  result  from  a  purely  me 
chanical  arrangement,  it  is  unnecessary  to  suppose  that 
habit-taking  is  a  primordial  principle  of  the  universe.  But 
one  fact  remains  unexplained  mechanically,  which  concerns 
not  only  the  facts  of  habit,  but  all  cases  of  actions  appar 
ently  violating  the  law  of  energy;  it  is  that  all  these  phe 
nomena  depend  upon  aggregations  of  trillions  of  molecules 
in  one  and  the  same  condition  and  neighborhood;  and  it  is 
by  no  means  clear  how  they  could  have  all  been  brought 
and  left  in  the  same  place  and  state  by  any  conservative 
forces.  But  let  the  mechanical  explanation  be  as  perfect 
as  it  may,  the  state  of  things  which  it  supposes  presents 
evidence  of  a  primordial  habit-taking  tendency.  For  it 
shows  us  like  things  acting  in  like  ways  because  they  are 
alike.  Now,  those  who  insist  on  the  doctrine  of  necessity 
will  for  the  most  part  insist  that  the  physical  world  is  en 
tirely  individual.  Yet  law  involves  an  element  of  gener 
ality.  Now  to  say  that  generality  is  primordial,  but  gen- 


260  ,  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

eralization  not,  is  like  saying  that  diversity  is  primordial 
but  diversification  not.  It  turns  logic  upside  down.  At 
any  rate,  it  is  clear  that  nothing  but  a  principle  of  habit, 
itself  due  to  the  growth  by  habit  of  an  infinitesimal  chance 
tendency  toward  habit-taking,  is  the  only  bridge  that  can 
span  the  chasm  between  the  chance-medley  of  chaos  and 
the  cosmos  of  order  and  law. 

I  shall  not  attempt  a  molecular  explanation  of  the  phe 
nomena  of  reproduction,  because  that  would  require  a  sub 
sidiary  hypothesis,  and  carry  me  away  from  my  main 
object.  Such  phenomena,  universally  diffused  though  they 
be,  appear  to  depend  upon  special  conditions;  and  we  do 
not  find  that  all  protoplasm  has  reproductive  powers. 

But  what  is  to  be  said  of  the  property  of  feeling?  If 
consciousness  belongs  to  all  protoplasm,  by  what  mechani 
cal  constitution  is  this  to  be  accounted  for?  The  slime 
is  nothing  but  a  chemical  compound.  There  is  no  inherent 
impossibility  in  its  being  formed  synthetically  in  the  labora 
tory,  out  of  its  chemical  elements;  and  if  it  were  so  made, 
it  would  present  all  the  characters  of  natural  protoplasm. 
No  doubt,  then,  it  would  feel.  To  hesitate  to  admit  this 
would  be  puerile  and  ultra-puerile.  By  what  element  of 
the  molecular  arrangement,  then,  would  that  feeling  be 
caused?  This  question  cannot  be  evaded  or  pooh-poohed. 
Protoplasm  certainly  does  feel;  and  unless  we  are  to  accept 
a  weak  dualism,  the  property  must  be  shown  to  arise  from 
some  peculiarity  of  the  mechanical  system.  Yet  the  at 
tempt  to  deduce  it  from  the  three  laws  of  mechanics,  ap 
plied  to  never  so  ingenious  a  mechanical  contrivance,  would 
obviously  be  futile.  It  can  never  be  explained,  unless  we 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  261 

admit  that  physical  events  are  but  degraded  or  undeveloped 
forms  of  psychical  events.  But  once  grant  that  the  phe 
nomena  of  matter  are  but  the  result  of  the  sensibly  com 
plete  sway  of  habits  upon  mind,  and  it  only  remains  to 
explain  why  in  the  protoplasm  these  habits  are  to  some 
slight  extent  broken  up,  so  that  according  to  the  law  of 
mind,  in  that  special  clause  of  it  sometimes  called  the  prin 
ciple  of  accommodation,9  feeling  becomes  intensified.  Now 
the  manner  in  which  habits  generally  get  broken  up  is  this. 
Reactions  usually  terminate  in  the  removal  of  a  stimulus; 
for  the  excitation  continues  as  long  as  the  stimulus  is  pres 
ent.  Accordingly,  habits  are  general  ways  of  behavior 
which  are  associated  with  the  removal  of  stimuli.  But 
when  the  expected  removal  of  the  stimulus  fails  to  occur, 
the  excitation  continues  and  increases,  and  non-habitual 
reactions  take  place;  and  these  tend  to  weaken  the  habit. 
If,  then,  we  suppose  that  matter  never  does  obey  its  ideal 
laws  with  absolute  precision,  but  that  there  are  almost  in 
sensible  fortuitous  departures  from  regularity,  these  will 
produce,  in  general,  equally  minute  effects.  But  proto 
plasm  is  in  an  excessively  unstable  condition;  and  it  is  the 
characteristic  of  unstable  equilibrium,  that  near  that  point 
excessively  minute  causes  may  produce  startlingly  large 
effects.  Here,  then,  the  usual  departures  from  regularity 
will  be  followed  by  others  that  are  very  great;  and  the  large 
fortuitous  departures  from  law  so  produced,  will  tend  still 
further  to  break  up  the  laws,  supposing  that  these  are  of 


9  "  Physiologically,  .  .  .  accommodation  means  the  breaking  up  of  a 
habit.  .  .  .  Psychologically,  it  means  reviving  consciousness."  Baldwin, 
Psychology,  Part  III,  ch.  i.,  §  5. 


262  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

the  nature  of  habits.  Now,  this  breaking  up  of  habit  and 
renewed  fortuitous  spontaneity  will,  according  to  the  law 
of  mind,  be  accompanied  by  an  intensification  of  feeling. 
The  nerve-protoplasm  is,  without  doubt,  in  the  most  un 
stable  condition  of  any  kind  of  matter;  and  consequently, 
there  the  resulting  feeling  is  the  most  manifest. 

Thus  we  see  that  the  idealist  has  no  need  to  dread  a 
mechanical  theory  of  life.  On  the  contrary,  such  a  theory, 
fully  developed,  is  bound  to^  call  in  a  tychistic  idealism  as 
its  indispensable  adjunct.  Wherever  chance-spontaneity 
is  found,  there,  in  the  same  proportion,  feeling  exists.  In 
fact,  chance  is  but  the  outward  aspect  of  that  which  within 
itself  is  feeling.  I  long  ago  showed  that  real  existence,  or 
thing-ness,  consists  in  regularities.  So,  that  primeval  chaos 
in  which  there  was  no  regularity  was  mere  nothing,  from 
a  physical  aspect.  Yet  it  was  not  a  blank  zero;  for  there 
was  an  intensity  of  consciousness  there  in  comparison  with 
which  all  that  we  ever  feel  is  but  as  the  struggling  of  a 
molecule  or  two  to  throw  off  a  little  of  the  force  of  law  to 
an  endless  and  innumerable  diversity  of  chance  utterly  un 
limited. 

But  after  some  atoms  of  the  protoplasm  have  thus  become 
partially  emancipated  from  law,  what  happens  next  to  them? 
To  understand  this,  we  have  to  remember  that  no  mental 
tendency  is  so  easily  strengthened  by  the  action  of  habit 
as  is  the  tendency  to  take  habits.  Now,  in  the  higher  kinds 
of  protoplasm,  especially,  the  atoms  in  question  have  not 
only  long  belonged  to  one  molecule  or  another  of  the  par 
ticular  mass  of  slime  of  which  they  are  parts;  but  before 
that,  they  were  constituents  of  food  of  a  protoplasmic  con- 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  263 

stitution.  During  all  this  time,  they  have  been  liable  to 
lose  habits  and  to  recover  them  again;  so  that  now,  when 
the  stimulus  is  removed,  and  the  foregone  habits  tend  to 
reassert  themselves,  they  do  so  in  the  case  of  such  atoms 
with  great  promptness.  Indeed,  the  return  is  so  prompt 
that  there  is  nothing  but  the  feeling  to  show  conclusively 
that  the  bonds  of  law  have  ever  been  relaxed. 

In  short,  diversification  is  the  vestige  of  chance-spon 
taneity;  and  wherever  diversity  is  increasing,  there  chance 
must  be  operative.  On  the  other  hand,  wherever  uniformity 
is  increasing,  habit  must  be  operative.  But  wherever  ac 
tions  take  place  under  an  established  uniformity,  there  so 
much  feeling  as  there  may  be  takes  the  mode  of  a  sense  of 
reaction.  That  is  the  manner  in  which  I  am  led  to  define 
the  relation  between  the  fundamental  elements  of  conscious 
ness  and  their  physical  equivalents. 

It  remains  to  consider  the  physical  relations  of  general 
ideas.  It  may  be  well  here  to  reflect  that  if  matter  has  no 
existence  except  as  a  specialization  of  mind,  it  follows  that 
whatever  affects  matter  according  to  regular  laws  is  itself 
matter.  But  all  mind  is  directly  or  indirectly  connected 
with  all  matter,  and  acts  in  a  more  or  less  regular  way; 
so  that  all  mind  more  or  less  partakes  of  the  nature  of 
matter.  Hence,  it  would  be  a  mistake  to  conceive  of  the 
psychical  and  the  physical  aspects  of  matter  as  two  aspects 
absolutely  distinct.  Viewing  a  thing  from  the  outside,  con 
sidering  its  relations  of  action  and  reaction  with  other 
things,  it  appears  as  matter.  Viewing  it  from  the  inside, 
looking  at  its  immediate  character  as  feeling,  it  appears  as 
consciousness.  These  two  views  are  combined  when  we 


264-  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

remember  that  mechanical  laws  are  nothing  but  acquired 
habits,  like  all  the  regularities  of  mind,  including  the  ten 
dency  to  take  habits,  itself;  and  that  this  action  of  habit 
is  nothing  but  generalization,  and  generalization  is  nothing 
but  the  spreading  of  feelings.  But  the  question  is,  how  do 
general  ideas  appear  in  the  molecular  theory  of  protoplasm? 

The  consciousness  of  a  habit  involves  a  general  idea.  In 
each  action  of  that  habit  certain  atoms  get  thrown  out  of 
their  orbit,  and  replaced  by  others.  Upon  all  the  different 
occasions  it  is  different  atoms  that  are  thrown  off,  but  they 
are  analogous  from  a  physical  point  of  view,  and  there  is 
an  inward  sense  of  their  being  analogous.  Every  time 
one  of  the  associated  feelings  recurs,  there  is  a  more  or  less 
vague  sense  that  there  are  others,  that  it  has  a  general 
character,  and  of  about  what  this  general  character  is.  We 
ought  not,  I  think,  to  hold  that  in  protoplasm  habit  never 
acts  in  any  other  than  the  particular  way  suggested  above. 
On  the  contrary,  if  habit  be  a  primary  property  of  mind, 
it  must  be  equally  so  of  matter,  as  a  kind  of  mind.  We 
can  hardly  refuse  to  admit  that  wherever  chance  motions 
have  general  characters,  there  is  a  tendency  for  this  gener 
ality  to  spread  and  to  perfect  itself.  In  that  case,  a  general 
idea  is  a  certain  modification  of  consciousness  which  accom 
panies  any  regularity  or  general  relation  between  chance 
actions. 

The  consciousness  of  a  general  idea  has  a  certain  "  unity 
of  the  ego,"  in  it,  which  is  identical  when  it  passes  from 
one  mind  to  another.  It  is,  therefore,  quite  analogous  to 
a  person;  and,  indeed,  a  person  is  only  a  particular  kind 
of  general  idea.  Long  age,  in  the  Journal  oj  Speculative 


MAN'S    GLASSY    ESSENCE  265 

Philosophy  (Vol.  II,  p.  156),  I  pointed  out  that  a  person 
is  nothing  but  a  symbol  involving  a  general  idea;  but  my 
views  were,  then,  too  nominalistic  to  enable  me  to  see  that 
every  general  idea  has  the  unified  living  feeling  of  a  person. 
All  that  is  necessary,  upon  this  theory,  to  the  existence 
of  a  person  is  that  the  feelings  out  of  which  he  is  constructed 
should  be  in  close  enough  connection  to  influence  one  an 
other.  Here  we  can  draw  a  consequence  which  it  may  be 
possible  to  submit  to  experimental  test.  Namely,  if  this 
be  the  case,  there  should  be  something  like  personal  con 
sciousness  in  bodies  of  men  who  are  in  intimate  and  in 
tensely  sympathetic  communion.  It  is  true  that  when  the 
generalization  of  feeling  has  been  carried  so  far  as  to  in 
clude  all  within  a  person,  a  stopping-place,  in  a  certain 
sense,  has  been  attained;  and  further  generalization  will 
have  a  less  lively  character.  But  we  must  not  think  it  will 
cease.  Esprit  de  corps,  national  sentiment,  sympathy,  are 
no  mere  metaphors.  None  of  us  can  fully  realize  what  the 
minds  of  corporations  are,  any  more  than  one  of  my  brain- 
cells  can  know  what  the  whole  brain  is  thinking.  But  the 
law  of  mind  clearly  points  to  the  existence  of  such  per 
sonalities,  and  there  are  many  ordinary  observations  which, 
if  they  were  critically  examined  and  supplemented  by  special 
experiments,  might,  as  first  appearances  promise,  give  evi 
dence  of  the  influence  of  such  greater  persons  upon  indi 
viduals.  It  is  often  remarked  that  on  one  day  half  a  dozen 
people,  strangers  to  one  another,  will  take  it  into  their  heads 
to  do  one  and  the  same  strange  deed,  whether  it  be  a  physi 
cal  experiment,  a  crime,  or  an  act  of  virtue.  When  the 
thirty  thousand  young  people  of  the  society  for  Christian 


266  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

Endeavor  were  in  New  York,  there  seemed  to  me  to  be  some 
mysterious  diffusion  of  sweetness  and  light.  If  such  a  fact 
is  capable  of  being  made  out  anywhere,  it  should  be  in  the 
church.  The  Christians  have  always  been  ready  to  risk 
their  lives  for  the  sake  of  having  prayers  in  common,  of 
getting  together  and  praying  simultaneously  with  great 
energy,  and  especially  for  their  common  body,  for  "  the 
whole  state  of  Christ's  church  militant  here  in  earth,"  as 
one  of  the  missals  has  it.  This  practice  they  have  been 
keeping  up  everywhere,  weekly,  for  many  centuries. 
Surely,  a  personality  ought  to  have  developed  in  that  church, 
in  that  "  bride  of  Christ,"  as  they  call  it,  or  else  there  is  a 
strange  break  in  the  action  of  mind,  and  I  shall  have  to 
acknowledge  my  views  are  much  mistaken.  Would  not  the 
societies  for  psychical  research  be  more  likely  to  break 
through  the  clouds,  in  seeking  evidences  of  such  corporate 
personality,  than  in  seeking  evidences  of  telepathy,  which, 
upon  the  same  theory,  should  be  a  far  weaker  phenomenon? 


V.   EVOLUTIONARY   LOVE1 

AT  FIRST  BLUSH.      COUNTER-GOSPELS 

PHILOSOPHY,  when  just  escaping  from  its  golden  pupa-skin, 
mythology,  proclaimed  the  great  evolutionary  agency  of  the 
universe  to  be  Love.  Or,  since  this  pirate-lingo,  English, 
is  poor  in  such-like  words,  let  us  say  Eros,  the  exuberance- 
love.  Afterwards,  Empedocles  set  up  passionate-love  and 
hate  as  the  two  co-ordinate  powers  of  the  universe.  In  some 
passages,  kindness  is  the  word.  But  certainly,  in  any  sense 
in  which  it  has  an  opposite,  to  be  senior  partner  of  that 
opposite,  is  the  highest  position  that  love  can  attain.  Never 
theless,  the  ontological  gospeller,  in  whose  days  those  views 
were  familiar  topics,  made  the  One  Supreme  Being,  by 
whom  all  things  have  been  made  out  of  nothing,  to  be 
cherishing-love.  What,  then,  can  he  say  to  hate?  Never 
mind,  at  this  time,  what  the  scribe  of  the  apocalypse,  if  he 
were  John,  stung  at  length  by  persecution  into  a  rage  unable 
to  distinguish  suggestions  of  evil  from  visions  of  heaven, 
and  so  become  the  Slanderer  of  God  to  men,  may  have 
dreamed.  The  question  is  rather  what  the  sane  John 
thought,  or  ought  to  have  thought,  in  order  to  carry  out 
his  idea  consistently.  His  statement  that  God  is  love  seems 
aimed  at  that  saying  of  Ecclesiastes  that  we  cannot  tell 
whether  God  bears  us  love  or  hatred.  "  Nay,"  says  John, 
"we  can  tell,  and  very  simply!  We  know  and  have 

1  The  Monist,  January,   1893. 

267 


268  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

trusted  the  love  which  God  hath  in  us.  God  is  love." 
There  is  no  logic  in  this,  unless  it  means  that  God  loves  all 
men.  In  the  preceding  paragraph,  he  had  said,  "  God  is 
light  and  in  him  is  no  darkness  at  all."  We  are  to  under 
stand,  then,  that  as  darkness  is  merely  the  defect  of  light, 
so  hatred  and  evil  are  mere  imperfect  stages  of  ayawrj 
and  ayaOov,  love  and  loveliness.  This  concords  with  that 
utterance  reported  in  John's  Gospel:  "  God  sent  not  the 
Son  into  the  world  to  judge  the  world;  but  that  the  world 
should  through  him  be  saved.  He  that  believeth  on  him  is 
not  judged:  he  that  believeth  not  hath  been  judged  al 
ready.  .  .  .  And  this  is  the  judgment,  that  the  light  is 
come  into  the  world,  and  that  men  loved  darkness  rather 
than  the  light."  That  is  to  say,  God  visits  no  punishment 
on  them;  they  punish  themselves,  by  their  natural  affinity 
for  the  defective.  Thus,  the  love  that  God  is,  is  not  a  love 
of  which  hatred  is  the  contrary;  otherwise  Satan  would  be 
a  co-ordinate  power;  but  it  is  a  love  which  embraces  hatred 
as  an  imperfect  stage  of  it,  an  Anteros  —  yea,  even  needs 
hatred  and  hatefulness  as  its  object.  For  self-love  is  no 
love;  so  if  God's  self  is  love,  that  which  he  loves  must  be 
defect  of  love;  just  as  a  luminary  can  light  up  only  that 
which  otherwise  would  be  dark.  Henry  James,  the  Sweden- 
borgian,  says:  "  It  is  no  doubt  very  tolerable  finite  or 
creaturely  love  to  love  one's  own  in  another,  to  love  another 
for  his  conformity  to  one's  self:  but  nothing  can  be  in 
more  flagrant  contrast  with  the  creative  Love,  all  whose 
tenderness  ex  vi  termini  must  be  reserved  only  for  what 
intrinsically  is  most  bitterly  hostile  and  negative  to  itself." 
This  is  from  Substance  and  Shadow:  an  Essay  on  the 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  269 

Physics  of  Creation.  It  is  a  pity  he  had  not  filled  his  pages 
with  things  like  this,  as  he  was  able  easily  to  do,  instead  of 
scolding  at  his  reader  and  at  people  generally,  until  the 
physics  of  creation  was  well-nigh  forgot.  I  must  deduct, 
however,  from  what  I  just  wrote:  obviously  no  genius  could 
make  his  every  sentence  as  sublime  as  one  which  discloses 
for  the  problem  of  evil  its  everlasting  solution. 

The  movement  of  love  is  circular,  at  one  and  the  same 
impulse  projecting  creations  into  independency  and  draw 
ing  them  into  harmony.  This  seems  complicated  when 
stated  so;  but  it  is  fully  summed  up  in  the  simple  formula 
we  call  the  Golden  Rule.  This  does  not,  of  course,  say, 
Do  everything  possible  to  gratify  the  egoistic  impulses  of 
others,  but  it  says,  Sacrifice  your  own  perfection  to  the 
perfectionment  of  your  neighbor.  Nor  must  it  for  a  mo 
ment  be  confounded  with  the  Benthamite,  or  Helvetian,  or 
Beccarian  motto,  Act  for  the  greatest  good  of  the  greatest 
number.  Love  is  not  directed  to  abstractions  but  to  per 
sons;  not  to  persons  we  do  not  know,  nor  to  numbers  of 
people,  but  to  our  own  dear  ones,  our  family  and  neighbors. 
"  Our  neighbor,"  we  remember,  is  one  whom  we  live  near, 
not  locally  perhaps,  but  in  life  and  feeling. 

Everybody  can  see  that  the  statement  of  St.  John  is  the 
formula  of  an  evolutionary  philosophy,  which  teaches  that 
growth  comes  only  from  love,  from  —  I  will  not  say  self- 
sacrifice,  but  from  the  ardent  impulse  to  fulfil  another's 
highest  impulse.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  I  have  an  idea 
that  interests  me.  It  is  my  creation.  It  is  my  creature; 
for  as  shown  in  last  Jury's  Monist,  it  is  a  little  person.  I 
love  it;  and  I  will  sink  myself  in  perfecting  it.  It  is  not 


2yo  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

by  dealing  out  cold  justice  to  the  circle  of  my  ideas  that 
I  can  make  them  grow,  but  by  cherishing  and  tending  them 
as  I  would  the  flowers  in  my  garden.  The  philosophy  we 
draw  from  John's  gospel  is  that  this  isthe  way  mind  de^ 
velops;  and  as  for  the  cosmos,  only  so"  far  as  it  yet  is  mind, 
anoTsb  has  life,  is  it  capable  of  furtherjeypjution.  Love, 
reoognlzSig  germs  of  loveliness  in  the  hateful,  gradually 
warms  it  into  life,  and  makes  it  lovely.  That  is  the  sort 
of  evolution  which  every  careful  student  of  my  essay  The 
Law  of  Mind,  must  see  that  synechism  calls  for. 

The  nineteenth  century  is  now  fast  sinking  into  the  grave, 
and  we  all  begin  to  review  its  doings  and  to  think  what 
character  it  is  destined  to  bear  as  compared  with  other 
centuries  in  the  minds  of  future  historians.  It  will  be 
called,  I  guess,  the  Economical  Century;  for  political 
economy  has  more  direct  relations  with  all  the  branches  of 
its  activity  than  has  any  other  science.  Well,  political 
economy  has  its  formula  of  redemption,  too.  It  is  this: 
Intelligence  in  the  service  of  greed  ensures  the  justest 
prices,  the  fairest  contracts,  the  most  enlightened  conduct 
of  all  the  dealings  between  men,  and  leads  to  the  summum 
bonum,  food  in  plenty  and  perfect  comfort.  Food  for 
whom?  Why,  for  the  greedy  master  of  intelligence.  I  do 
not  mean  to  say  that  this  is  one  of  the  legitimate  conclu 
sions  of  political  economy,  the  scientific  character  of  which 
I  fully  acknowledge.  But  the  study  of  doctrines,  them 
selves  true,  will  often  temporarily  encourage  generalizations 
extremely  false,  as  the  study  of  physics  has  encouraged 
necessitarianism.  What  I  say,  then,  is  that  the  great  at 
tention  paid  to  economical  questions  during  our  century 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  271 

has  induced  an  exaggeration  of  the  beneficial  effects  of 
greed  and  of  the  unfortunate  results  of  sentiment,  until 
there  has  resulted  a  philosophy  which  comes  unwittingly 
to  this,  that  greed  is  the  great  agent  in  the  elevation  of 
the  human  race  and  in  the  evolution  of  the  universe. 

I  open  a  handbook  of  political  economy,  —  the  most 
typical  and  middling  one  I  have  at  hand,  —  and  there  find 
some  remarks  of  which  I  will  here  make  a  brief  analysis. 
I  omit  qualifications,  sops  thrown  to  Cerberus,  phrases  to 
placate  Christian  prejudice,  trappings  which  serve  to  hide 
from  author  and  reader  alike  the  ugly  nakedness  of  the 
greed-god.  But  I  have  surveyed  my  position.  The  author 
enumerates  "three  motives  to  human  action: 

The  love  of  self; 

The  love  of  a  limited  class  having  common  interests  and 
feelings  with  one's  self; 

The  love  of  mankind  at  large." 

Remark,  at  the  outset,  what  obsequious  title  is  bestowed 
on  greed,  —  "the  love  of  self."  Love!  The  second  mo 
tive  is  love.  In  place  of  "  a  limited  class  "  put  "  certain 
persons,"  and  you  have  a  fair  description.  Taking  "  class  " 
in  the  old-fashioned  sense,  a  weak  kind  of  love  is  described. 
In  the  sequel,  there  seems  to  be  some  haziness  as  to  the 
delimitation  of  this  motive.  By  the  love  of  mankind  at 
large,  the  author  does  not  mean  that  deep,  subconscious 
passion  that  is  properly  so  called;  but  merely  public-spirit, 
perhaps  little  more  than  a  fidget  about  pushing  ideas.  The 
author  proceeds  to  a  comparative  estimate  of  the  worth  of 
these  motives.  Greed,  says  he,  but  using,  of  course,  an 
other  word,  "  is  not  so  great  an  evil  as  is  commonly  sup- 


272  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

posed.  .  .  .  Every  man  can  promote  his  own  interests  a 
great  deal  more  effectively  than  he  can  promote  any  one 
else's,  or  than  any  one  else  can  promote  his."  Besides,  as 
he  remarks  on  another  page,  the  more  miserly  a  man  is, 
the  more  good  he  does.  The  second  motive  "  is  the  most 
dangerous  one  to  which  society  is  exposed."  Love  is  all 
very  pretty:  "  no  higher  or  purer  source  of  human  happi 
ness  exists."  (Ahem!)  But  it  is  a  "source  of  enduring 
injury,"  and,  in  short,  should  be  overruled  by  something 
wiser.  What  is  this  wiser  motive?  We  shall  see. 

As  for  public  spirit,  it  is  rendered  nugatory  by  the  "  dif 
ficulties  in  the  way  of  its  effective  operation."  For  ex 
ample,  it  might  suggest  putting  checks  upon  the  fecundity 
of  the  poor  and  the  vicious;  and  "  no  measure  of  repression 
would  be  too  severe,"  in  the  case  of  criminals.  The  hint 
is  broad.  But  unfortunately,  you  cannot  induce  legisla 
tures  to  take  such  measures,  owing  to  the  pestiferous  "  ten 
der  sentiments  of  man  towards  man."  It  thus  appears, 
that  public-spirit,  or  Benthamism,  is  not  strong  enough  to 
be  the  effective  tutor  of  love,  (I  am  skipping  to  another 
page),  which  must,  therefore,  be  handed  over  to  "  the  mo 
tives  which  animate  men  in  the  pursuit  of  wealth,"  in  which 
alone  we  can  confide,  and  which  "  are  in  the  highest  degree 
beneficent."  2  Yes,  in  the  "  highest  degree  "  without  ex 
ception  are  they  beneficent  to  the  being  upon  whom  all  their 
blessings  are  poured  out,  namely,  the  Self,  whose  "  sole 
object,"  says  the  writer  in  accumulating  wealth  'is  his  in- 

2  How  can  a  writer  have  any  respect  for  science,  as  such,  who  is 
capable  of  confounding  with  the  scientific  propositions  of  political  econ 
omy,  which  have  nothing  to  say  concerning  what  is  "  beneficent,"  such 
brummagem  generalisations  as  this? 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  273 

dividual  "  sustenance  and  enjoyment."  Plainly,  the  author 
holds  the  notion  that  some  other  motive  might  be  in  a  higher 
degree  beneficent  even  for  the  man's  self  to  be  a  paradox 
wanting  in  good  sense.  He  seeks  to  gloze  and  modify  his 
doctrine;  but  he  lets  the  perspicacious  reader  see  what  his 
animating  principle  is;  and  when,  holding  the  opinions  I 
have  repeated,  he  at  the  same  time  acknowledges  that  so 
ciety  could  not  exist  upon  a  basis  of  intelligent  greed  alone, 
he  simply  pigeon-holes  himself  as  one  of  the  eclectics  of 
inharmonious  opinions.  He  wants  his  mammon  flavored 
with  a  soupgon  of  god. 

The  economists  accuse  those  to  whom  the  enunciation 
of  their  atrocious  villainies  communicates  a  thrill  of  horror 
of  being  sentimentalists.  It  may  be  so:  I  willingly  confess 
to  having  some  tincture  of  sentimentalism  in  me,  God  be 
thanked!  Ever  since  the  French  Revolution  brought  this 
leaning  of  thought  into  ill-repute,  —  and  not  altogether 
undeservedly,  I  must  admit,  true,  beautiful,  and  good  as 
that  great  movement  was,  —  it  has  been  the  tradition  to 
picture  sentimentalists  as  persons  incapable  of  logical 
thought  and  unwilling  to  look  facts  in  the  eyes.  This  tra 
dition  may  be  classed  with  the  French  tradition  that  an 
Englishman  says  godam  at  every  second  sentence,  the 
English  tradition  that  an  American  talks  about  "  Brit 
ishers,"  and  the  American  tradition  that  a  Frenchman 
carries  forms  of  etiquette  to  an  inconvenient  extreme,  in 
short  with  all  those  traditions  which  survive  simply  because 
the  men  who  use  their  eyes  and  ears  are  few  and  far  be 
tween.  Doubtless  some  excuse  there  was  for  all  those 
opinions  in  days  gone  by;  and  sentimentalism,  when  it 


274  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

was  the  fashionable  amusement  to  spend  one's  evenings 
in  a  flood  of  tears  over  a  woeful  performance  on  a  candle- 
litten  stage,  sometimes  made  itself  a  little  ridiculous.  But 
what  after  all  is  sentimentalism?  It  is  an  ism,  a  doctrine, 
namely,  the  doctrine  that  great  respect  should  be  paid  to 
the  natural  judgments  of  the  sensible  heart.  This  is  what 
sentimentalism  precisely  is;  and  I  entreat  the  reader  to 
consider  whether  to  contemn  it  is  not  of  all  blasphemies  the 
most  degrading.  Yet  the  nineteenth  century  has  steadily 
contemned  it,  because  it  brought  about  the  Reign  of  Ter 
ror.  That  it  did  so  is  true.  Still,  the  whole  question  is 
one  of  how  much.  The  Reign  of  Terror  was  very  bad;  but 
now  the  Gradgrind  banner  has  been  this  century  long 
flaunting  in  the  face  of  heaven,  with  an  insolence  to  pro 
voke  the  very  skies  to  scowl  and  rumble.  Soon  a  flash  and 
quick  peal  will  shake  economists  quite  out  of  their  com 
placency,  too  late.  The  twentieth  century,  in  its  latter 
half,  shall  surely  see  the  deluge- tempest  burst  upon  the 
social  order,  —  to  clear  upon  a  world  as  deep  in  ruin  as 
that  greed-philosophy  has  long  plunged  it  into  guilt.  No 
post-thermidorian  high  jinks  then! 

So  a  miser  is  a  beneficent  power  in  a  community,  is  he? 
With  the  same  reason  precisely,  only  in  a  much  higher  de 
gree,  you  might  pronounce  the  Wall  Street  sharp  to  be  a 
good  angel,  who  takes  money  from  heedless  persons  not 
likely  to  guard  it  properly,  who  wrecks  feeble  enterprises 
better  stopped,  and  who  administers  wholesome  lessons  to 
unwary  scientific  men,  by  passing  worthless  checks  upon 
them,  —  as  you  did,  the  other  day,  to  me,  my  millionaire 
Master  in  glomery,  when  you  thought  you  saw  your  way 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  275 

to  using  my  process  without  paying  for  it,  and  of  so  be 
queathing  to  your  children  something  to  boast  of  their 
father  about,  —  and  who  by  a  thousand  wiles  puts  money 
at  the  service  of  intelligent  greed,  in  his  own  person.  Ber 
nard  Mandeville,  in  his  Fable  of  the  Bees,  maintains 
that  private  vices  of  all  descriptions  are  public  benefits, 
and  proves  it,  too,  quite  as  cogently  as  the  economist  proves 
his  point  concerning  the  miser.  He  even  argues,  with  no 
slight  force,  that  but  for  vice  civilization  would  never 
have  existed.  In  the  same  spirit,  it  has  been  strongly 
maintained  and  is  to-day  widely  believed  that  all  acts  of 
charity  and  benevolence,  private  and  public,  go  seriously 
to  degrade  the  human  race. 

The  Origin  of  Species  of  Darwin  merely  extends 
politico-economical  views  of  progress  to  the  entire  realm  of 
animal  and  vegetable  life.  The  vast  majority  of  our  con 
temporary  naturalists  hold  the  opinion  that  the  true  cause 
of  those  exquisite  and  marvellous  adaptations  of  nature 
for  which,  when  I  was  a  boy,  men  used  to  extol  the  divine 
wisdom  is  that  creatures  are  so  crowded  together  that  those 
of  them  that  happen  to  have  the  slightest  advantage  force 
those  less  pushing  into  situations  unfavorable  to  multipli 
cation  or  even  kill  them  before  they  reach  the  age  of  re 
production.  Among  animals,  the  mere  mechanical  indi 
vidualism  is  vastly  reenforced  as  a  power  making  for  good 
by  the  animal's  ruthless  greed.  As  Darwin  puts  it  on  his 
title-page,  it  is  the  struggle  for  existence;  and  he  should 
have  added  for  his  motto:  Every  individual  for  himself, 
and  the  Devil  take  the  hindmost!  Jesus,  in  his  sermon 
on  the  Mount,  expressed  a  different  opinion. 


276  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

Here,  then,  is  the  issue.  The  gospel  of  Christ  says  that 
progress  comes  from  every  individual  merging  his  individu 
ality  in  sympathy  with  his  neighbors.  On  the  other  side, 
the  conviction  of  the  nineteenth  century  is  that  progress 
takes  place  by  virtue  of  every  individual's  striving  for  him 
self  with  all  his  might  and  trampling  his  neighbor  under 
foot  whenever  he  gets  a  chance  to  do  so.  This  may  ac 
curately  be  called  the  Gospel  of  Greed. 

Much  is  to  be  said  on  both  sides.  I  have  not  concealed, 
I  could  not  conceal,  my  own  passionate  predilection.  Such 
a  confession  will  probably  shock  my  scientific  brethren. 
Yet  the  strong  feeling  is  in  itself,  I  think,  an  argument  of 
some  weight  in  favor  of  the  agapastic  theory  of  evolu 
tion,  —  so  far  as  it  may  be  presumed  to  bespeak  the  nor 
mal  judgment  of  the  Sensible  Heart.  Certainly,  if  it  were 
possible  to  believe  in  agapasm  without  believing  it  warmly, 
that  fact  would  be  an  argument  against  the  truth  of  the 
doctrine.  At  any  rate,  since  the  warmth  of  feeling  exists, 
it  should  on  every  account  be  candidly  confessed;  especially 
since  it  creates  a  liability  to  onesidedness  on  my  part 
against  which  it  behooves  my  readers  and  me  to  be  severally 
on  our  guard. 

SECOND    THOUGHTS.      IRENICA. 

Let  us  try  to  define  the  logical  affinities  of  the  different 
theories  of  evolution.  Natural  selection,  as  conceived  by 
Darwin,  is  a  mode  of  evolution  in  which  the  only  positive 
agent  of  change  in  the  whole  passage  from  moner  to  man 
is  fortuitous  variation.  To  secure  advance  in  a  definite 
direction  chance  has  to  be  seconded  by  some  action  that 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  277 

shall  hinder  the  propagation  of  some  varieties  or  stimulate 
that  of  others.  In  natural  selection,  strictly  so  called,  it 
is  the  crowding  out  of  the  weak.  In  sexual  selection,  it  is 
the  attraction  of  beauty,  mainly. 

The  Origin  of  Species  was  published  toward  the  end 
of  the  year  1859.  The  preceding  years  since  1846  had  been 
one  of  the  most  productive  seasons,  —  or  if  extended  so 
as  to  cover  the  great  book  we  are  considering,  the  most  pro 
ductive  period  of  equal  length  in  the  entire  history  of 
science  from  its  beginnings  until  now.  The  idea  that  chance 
.begets  order,  which  is  one  of  the  corner-stones  of  modern 
physics  (although  Dr.  Carus  considers  it  "  the  weakest 
point  in  Mr.  Peirce's  system,")  was  at  that  time  put  into 
its  clearest  light.  Quetelet  had  opened  the  discussion  by  his 
Letters  on  the  Application  of  Probabilities  to  the  Moral 
and  Political  Sciencest  a  work  which  deeply  impressed 
the  best  minds  of  that  day,  and  to  which  Sir  John  Herschel 
had  drawn  general  attention  in  Great  Britain.  In  1857,  the 
first  volume  of  Buckle's  History  of  Civilisation  had 
created  a  tremendous  sensation,  owing  to  the  use  he  made  of 
this  same  idea.  Meantime,  the  "  statistical  method  "  had, 
under  that  very  name,  been  applied  with  brilliant  success 
to  molecular  physics.  Dr.  John  Herapath,  an  English 
chemist,  had  in  1847  outlined  the  kinetical  theory  of  gases 
in  his  Mathematical  Physics;  and  the  interest  the  theory 
excited  had  been  refreshed  in  1856  by  notable  memoirs  by 
Clausius  and  Kronig.  In  the  very  summer  preceding  Dar 
win's  publication,  Maxwell  had  read  before  the  British 
Association  the  first  and  most  important  of  his  researches 
on  this  subject.  The  consequence  was  that  the  idea  that 


278  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

fortuitous  events  may  result  in  a  physical  law,  and  further 
that  this  is  the  way  in  which  those  laws  which  appear  to 
conflict  with  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy 
are  to  be  explained,  had  taken  a  strong  hold  upon  the  minds 
of  all  who  were  abreast  of  the  leaders  of  thought.  By  such 
minds,  it  was  inevitable  that  the  Origin  of  Species,  whose 
teaching  was  simply  the  application  of  the  same  principle 
to  the  explanation  of  another  "  non-conservative  w  action, 
that  of  organic  development,  should  be  hailed  and  wel 
comed.  The  sublime  discovery  of  the  conservation  of  energy 
by  Helmholtz  in  1847,  and  that  of  the  mechanical  theory  of 
heat  by  Clausius  and  by  Rankine,  independently,  in  1850, 
had  decidedly  overawed  all  those  who  might  have  been 
inclined  to  sneer  at  physical  science.  Thereafter  a  belated 
poet  still  harping  upon  "  science  peddling  with  the  names 
of  things  "  would  fail  of  his  effect.  Mechanism  was  now 
known  to  be  all,  or  very  nearly  so.  All  this  time,  utilitari 
anism, —  that  improved  substitute  for  the  Gospel,  —  was 
in  its  fullest  feather;  and  was  a  natural  ally  of  an  indi 
vidualistic  theory.  Dean  ManselFs  injudicious  advocacy 
had  led  to  mutiny  among  the  bondsmen  of  Sir  William 
Hamilton,  and  the  nominalism  of  Mill  had  profited  ac 
cordingly;  and  although  the  real  science  that  Darwin  was 
leading  men  to  was  sure  some  day  to  give  a  death-blow  to 
the  sham-science  of  Mill,  yet  there  were  several  elements 
of  the  Darwinian  theory  which  were  sure  to  charm  the 
followers  of  Mill.  Another  thing:  anaesthetics  had  been  in 
use  for  thirteen  years.  Already,  people's  acquaintance  with 
suffering  had  dropped  off  very  much;  and  as  a  consequence, 
that  unlovely  hardness  by  which  our  times  are  so  contrasted 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  279 

with  those  that  immediately  preceded  them,  had  already 
set  in,  and  inclined  people  to  relish  a  ruthless  theory.  The 
reader  would  quite  mistake  the  drift  of  what  I  am  saying 
if  he  were  to  understand  me  as  wishing  to  suggest  that 
any  of  those  things  (except  perhaps  Mai  thus)  influenced 
Darwin  himself.  What  I  mean  is  that  his  hypothesis,  while 
without  dispute  one  of  the  most  ingenious  and  pretty  ever 
devised,  and  while  argued  with  a  wealth  of  knowledge,  a 
strength  of  logic,  a  charm  of  rhetoric,  and  above  all  with 
a  certain  magnetic  genuineness  that  was  almost  irresisti 
ble,  did  not  appear,  at  first,  at  all  near  to  being  proved; 
and  to  a  sober  mind  its  case  looks  less  hopeful  now  than 
it  did  twenty  years  ago;  but  the  extraordinarily  favorable 
reception  it  met  with  was  plainly  owing,  in  large  measure, 
to  its  ideas  being  those  toward  which  the  age  was  favorably 
disposed,  especially,  because  of  the  encouragement  it  gave 
to  the  greed-philosophy. 

Diametrically  opposed  to  evolution  by  chance,  are  those 
theories  which  attribute  all  progress  to  an  inward  necessary 
principle,  or  other  form  of  necessity.  Many  naturalists 
have  thought  that  if  an  egg  is  destined  to  go  through  a 
certain  series  of  embryological  transformations,  from  which 
it  is  perfectly  certain  not  to  deviate,  and  if  in  geological 
time  almost  exactly  the  same  forms  appear  successively, 
one  replacing  another  in  the  same  order,  the  strong  pre 
sumption  is  that  this  latter  succession  was  as  predeterminate 
and  certain  to  take  place  as  the  former.  So,  Nageli,  for 
instance,  conceives  that  it  somehow  follows  from  the  first 
law  of  motion  and  the  peculiar,  but  unknown,  molecular 
constitution  of  protoplasm,  that  forms  must  complicate 


28o  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

themselves  more  and  more.  Kolliker  makes  one  form 
generate  another  after  a  certain  maturation  has  been  ac 
complished.  Weismann,  too,  though  he  calls  himself  a 
Darwinian,  holds  that  nothing  is  due  to  chance,  but  that 
all  forms  are  simple  mechanical  resultants  of  the  heredity 
from  two  parents.3  It  is  very  noticeable  that  all  these  dif 
ferent  sectaries  seek  to  import  into  their  science  a  mechani 
cal  necessity  to  which  the  facts  that  come  under  their  ob 
servation  do  not  point.  Those  geologists  who  think  that  the 
variation  of  species  is  due  to  cataclysmic  alterations  of 
climate  or  of  the  chemical  constitution  of  the  air  and  water 
are  also  making  mechanical  necessity  chief  factor  of 
evolution. 

Evolution  by  sporting  and  evolution  by  mechanical  neces 
sity  are  conceptions  warring  against  one  another.  A  third 
method,  which  supersedes  their  strife,  lies  enwrapped  in 
the  theory  of  Lamarck.  According  to  his  view,  all  that 
distinguishes  the  highest  organic  forms  from  the  most 
rudimentary  has  been  brought  about  by  little  hypertrophies 
or  atrophies  which  have  affected  individuals  early  in  their 
lives,  and  have  been  transmitted  to  their  offspring.  Such 
a  transmission  of  acquired  characters  is  of  the  general 
nature  of  habit-taking,  and  this  is  the  representative  and 
derivative  within  the  physiological  domain  of  the  law  of 
mind.  Its  action  is  essentially  dissimilar  to  that  of  a  physi 
cal  force;  and  that  is  the  secret  of  the  repugnance  of  such 
necessitarians  as  Weismann  to  admitting  its  existence.  The 
Lamarckians  further  suppose  that  although  some  of  the 

3  I  am  happy  to  find  that  Dr.  Carus,  too,  ranks  Weismann  among  the 
opponents  of  Darwin,  notwithstanding  his  flying  that  flag. 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  281 

modifications  of  form  so  transmitted  were  originally  due  to 
mechanical  causes,  yet  the  chief  factors  of  their  first  produc 
tion  were  the  straining  of  endeavor  and  the  overgrowth 
superinduced  by  exercise,  together  with  the  opposite  actions. 
Now,  endeavor,  since  it  is  directed  toward  an  end,  is  es 
sentially  psychical,  even  though  it  be  sometimes  uncon 
scious;  and  the  growth  due  to  exercise,  as  I  argued  in  my 
last  paper,  follows  a  law  of  a  character  quite  contrary  to 
that  of  mechanics. 

Lamarckian  evolution  is  thus  evolution  by  the  force  of 
habit.  —  That  sentence  slipped  off  my  pen  while  one  of 
those  neighbors  whose  function  in  the  social  cosmos  seems 
to  be  that  of  an  Interrupter,  was  asking  me  a  question.  Of 
course,  it  is  nonsense.  Habit  is  mere  inertia,  a  resting  on 
one's  oars,  not  a  propulsion.  Now  it  is  energetic  pro- 
jaculation  (lucky  there  is  such  a  word,  or  this  untried 
hand  might  have  been  put  to  inventing  one)  by  which  in 
the  typical  instances  of  Lamarckian  evolution  the  new 
elements  of  form  are  first  created.  Habit,  however,  forces 
them  to  take  practical  shapes,  compatible  with  the  struc 
tures  they  affect,  and  in  the  form  of  heredity  and  other 
wise,  gradually  replaces  the  spontaneous  energy  that  sus 
tains  them.  Thus,  habit  plays  a  double  part;  it  serves  to 
establish  the  new  features,  and  also  to  bring  them  into 
harmony  with  the  general  morphology  and  function  of  the 
animals  and  plants  to  which  they  belong.  But  if  the  reader 
will  now  kindly  give  himself  the  trouble  of  turning  back  a 
page  or  two,  he  will  see  that  this  account  of  Lamarckian 
evolution  coincides  with  the  general  description  of  the 
action  of  love,  to  which,  I  suppose,  he  yielded  his  assent. 


282  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

Remembering  that  all  matter  is  really  mind,  remember 
ing,  too,  the  continuity  of  mind,  let  us  ask  what  aspect 
Lamarckian  evolution  takes  on  within  the  domain  of  con 
sciousness.  Direct  endeavor  can  achieve  almost  nothing, 
It  is  as  easy  by  taking  thought  to  add  a  cubit  to  one's 
stature,  as  it  is  to  produce  an  idea  acceptable  to  any  of 
the  Muses  by  merely  straining  for  it,  before  it  is  ready  to 
come.  We  haunt  in  vain  the  sacred  well  and  throne  of 
Mnemosyne;  the  deeper  workings  of  the  spirit  take  place 
in  their  own  slow  way,  without  our  connivance.  Let  but 
their  bugle  sound,  and  we  may  then  make  our  effort,  sure 
of  an  oblation  for  the  altar  of  whatsoever  divinity  its  savor 
gratifies.  Besides  this  inward  process,  there  is  the  operation 
of  the  environment,  which  goes  to  break  up  habits  destined 
to  be  broken  up  and  so  to  render  the  mind  lively.  Every 
body  knows  that  the  long  continuance  of  a  routine  of  habit 
makes  us  lethargic,  while  a  succession  of  surprises  wonder 
fully  brightens  the  ideas.  Where  there  is  a  motion,  where 
history  is  a-making,  there  is  the  focus  of  mental  activity, 
and  it  has  been  said  that  the  arts  and  sciences  reside  within 
the  temple  of  Janus,  waking  when  that  is  open,  but  slum 
bering  when  it  is  closed.  Few  psychologists  have  per 
ceived  how  fundamental  a  fact  this  is.  A  portion  of  mind 
abundantly  commissured  to  other  portions  works  almost 
mechanically.  It  sinks  to  a  condition  of  a  railway  junction. 
But  a  portion  of  mind  almost  isolated,  a  spiritual  peninsula, 
or  cul-de-sac,  is  like  a  railway  terminus.  Now  mental 
commissures  are  habits.  Where  they  abound,  originality  is 
not  needed  and  is  not  found;  but  where  they  are 
in  defect,  spontaneity  is  set  free.  Thus,  the  first 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  283 

step  in  the  Lamarckian  evolution  of  mind  is  the  putting  of 
sundry  thoughts  into  situations  in  which  they  are  free  to 
play.  As  to  growth  by  exercise,  I  have  already  shown,  in 
discussing  Man's  Glassy  Essence,  in  last  October's 
Monist,  what  its  modus  operandi  must  be  conceived  to  be, 
at  least,  until  a  second  equally  definite  hypothesis  shall 
have  been  offered.  Namely,  it  consists  of  the  flying 
asunder  of  molecules,  and  the  reparation  of  the  parts  by 
new  matter.  It  is,  thus,  a  sort  of  reproduction.  It  takes 
place  only  during  exercise,  because  the  activity  of  proto 
plasm  consists  in  the  molecular  disturbance  which  is  its 
necessary  condition.  Growth  by  exercise  takes  place  also 
in  the  mind.  Indeed,  that  is  what  it  is  to  learn.  But  the 
most  perfect  illustration  is  the  development  of  a  philosophi 
cal  idea  by  being  put  into  practice.  The  conception  which 
appeared,  at  first,  as  unitary,  splits  up  into  special  cases; 
and  into  each  of  these  new  thought  must  enter  to  make  a 
practicable  idea.  This  new  thought,  however,  follows 
pretty  closely  the  model  of  the  parent  conception;  and  thus 
a  homogeneous  development  takes  place.  The  parallel 
between  this  and  the  course  of  molecular  occurrences  is 
apparent.  Patient  attention  will  be  able  to  trace  all  these 
elements  in  the  transaction  called  learning. 

Three  modes  of  evolution  have  thus  been  brought  be 
fore  us;  evolution  by  fortuitous  variation,  evolution  by 
mechanical  necessity,  and  evolution  by  creative  love.  We 
may  term  them  tychastic  evolution,  or  tychasm,  anancastic 
evolution,  or  anancasm,  and  agapastic  evolution,  or  aga- 
pasm.  The  doctrines  which  represent  these  as  severally  of 
principal  importance,  we  may  term  tychasticism,  anancas- 


284  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

tkism,  and  agapasticism.  On  the  other  hand  the  mere 
propositions  that  absolute  chance,  mechanical  necessity, 
and  the  law  of  love,  are  severally  operative  in  the  cosmos, 
may  receive  the  names  of  tychism,  anancism,  and  agapism. 

All  three  modes  of  evolution  are  composed  of  the  same 
general  elements.  Agapasm  exhibits  them  the  most  clearly. 
The  good  result  is  here  brought  to  pass,  first,  by  the  be 
stowal  of  spontaneous  energy  by  the  parent  upon  the  off 
spring,  and,  second,  by  the  disposition  of  the  latter  to  catch 
the  general  idea  of  those  about  it  and  thus  to  subserve 
the  general  purpose.  In  order  to  express  the  relation 
that  tychasm  and  anancasm  bear  to  agapasm,  let  me  bor 
row  a  word  from  geometry.  An  ellipse  crossed  by  a 
straight  line  is  a  sort  of  cubic  curve;  for  a  cubic  is  a  curve 
which  is  cut  thrice  by  a  straight  line;  now  a  straight  line 
might  cut  the  ellipse  twice  and  its  associated  straight  line 
a  third  time.  Still  the  ellipse  with  the  straight  line  across 
it  would  not  have  the  characteristics  of  a  cubic.  It  would 
have,  for  instance,  no  contrary  flexure,  which  no  true  cubic 
wants;  and  it  would  have  two  nodes,  which  no  true  cubic 
has.  The  geometers  say  that  it  is  a  degenerate  cubic.  Just 
so,  tychasm  and  anancasm  are  degenerate  forms  of 
agapasm. 

Men  who  seek  to  reconcile  the  Darwinian  idea  with 
Christianity  will  remark  that  tychastic  evolution,  like  the 
agapastic,  depends  upon  a  reproductive  creation,  the  forms 
preserved  being  those  that  use  the  spontaneity  conferred 
upon  them  in  such  wise  as  to  be  drawn  into  harmony  with 
their  original,  quite  after  the  Christian  scheme.  Very 
good!  This  only  shows  that  just  as  love  cannot  have  a 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  285 

contrary,  but  must  embrace  what  is  most  opposed  to  it,  as  a 
degenerate  case  of  it,  so  tychasm  is  a  kind  of  agapasm. 
Only,  in  the  tychastic  evolution  progress  is  solely  owing  to 
the  distribution  of  the  napkin-hidden  talent  of  the  re 
jected  servant  among  those  not  rejected,  just  as  ruined 
gamesters  leave  their  money  on  the  table  to  make  those 
not  yet  ruined  so  much  the  richer.  It  makes  the  felicity 
of  the  lambs  just  the  damnation  of  the  goats,  transposed 
to  the  other  side  of  the  equation.  In  genuine  agapasm, 
on  the  other  hand,  advance  takes  place  by  virtue  of  a  posi 
tive  sympathy  among  the  created  springing  from  continuity 
of  mind.  This  is  the  idea  which  tychasticism  knows  not 
how  to  manage. 

The  anancasticist  might  here  interpose,  claiming  that 
the  mode  of  evolution  for  which  he  contends  agrees  with 
agapasm  at  the  point  at  which  tychasm  departs  from  it. 
For  it  makes  development  go  through  certain  phases,  having 
its  inevitable  ebbs  and  flows,  yet  tending  on  the  whole  to  a 
foreordained  perfection.  Bare  existence  by  this  its  destiny 
betrays  an  intrinsic  affinity  for  the  good.  Herein,  it  must 
be  admitted,  anancasm  shows  itself  to  be  in  a  broad  accep- 
tion  a  species  of  agapasm.  Some  forms  of  it  might  easily 
be  mistaken  for  the  genuine  agapasm.  The  Hegelian  phil 
osophy  is  such  an  anancasticism.  With  its  revelatory  re 
ligion,  with  its  synechism  (however  imperfectly  set  forth), 
with  its  "  reflection/'  the  whole  idea  of  the  theory  is  superb, 
almost  sublime.  Yet,  after  all,  living  freedom  is  practically 
omitted  from  its  method.  The  whole  movement  is  that 
of  a  vast  engine,  impelled  by  a  vis  a  tergo,  with  a  blind  and 
mysterious  fate  of  arriving  at  a  lofty  goal.  I  mean  that 


286  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

such  an  engine  it  would  be,  if  it  really  worked;  but  in  point 
of  fact,  it  is  a  Keely  motor.  Grant  that  it  really  acts  as 
it  professes  to  act,  and  there  is  nothing  to  do  but  accept  the 
philosophy.  But  never  was  there  seen  such  an  example  of 
a  long  chain  of  reasoning,  —  shall  I  say  with  a  flaw  in 
every  link?  —  no,  with  every  link  a  handful  of  sand, 
squeezed  into  shape  in  a  dream.  Or  say,  it  is  a  pasteboard 
model  of  a  philosophy  that  in  reality  does  not  exist.  If  we 
use  the  one  precious  thing  it  contains,  the  idea  of  it,  in 
troducing  the  tychism  which  the  arbitrariness  of  its  every 
step  suggests,  and  make  that  the  support  of  a  vital  free 
dom  which  is  the  breath  of  the  spirit  of  love,  we  may  be 
able  to  produce  that  genuine  agapasticism,  at  which  Hegel 
was  aiming. 

A   THIRD  ASPECT.      DISCRIMINATION 

In  the  very  nature  of  things,  the  line  of  demarcation  be 
tween  the  three  modes  of  evolution  is  not  perfectly  sharp. 
That  does  not  prevent  its  being  quite  real;  perhaps  it  is 
rather  a  mark  of  its  reality.  There  is  in  the  nature  of  things 
no  sharp  line  of  demarcation  between  the  three  funda 
mental  colors,  red,  green,  and  violet.  But  for  all  that  they 
are  really  different.  The  main  question  is  whether  three 
radically  different  evolutionary  elements  have  been  opera 
tive  ;  and  the  second  question  is  what  are  the  most  striking 
characteristics  of  whatever  elements  have  been  operative. 

I  propose  to  devote  a  few  pages  to  a  very  slight  examina 
tion  of  these  questions  in  their  relation  to  the  historical 
development  of  human  thought.  I  first  formulate  for  the 
reader's  convenience  the  briefest  possible  definitions  of  the 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  287 

three  conceivable  modes  of  development  of  thought^  dis 
tinguishing  also  two  varieties  of  anancasm  and  three  of 
agapasm.  The  tychastic  development  of  thought,  then, 
will  consist  in  slight  departures  from  habitual  ideas  in  dif 
ferent  directions  indifferently,  quite  purposeless  and  quite 
unconstrained  whether  by  outward  circumstances  or  by 
force  of  logic,  these  new  departures  being  followed  by  un 
foreseen  results  which  tend  to  fix  some  of  them  as  habits 
more  than  others.  The  anancastic  development  of  thought 
will  consist  of  new  ideas  adopted  without  foreseeing  whither 
they  tend,  but  having  a  character  determined  by  causes 
either  external  to  the  mind,  such  as  changed  circumstances 
of  life,  or  internal  to  the  mind  as  logical  developments  of 
ideas  already  accepted,  such  as  generalizations.  The  aga- 
pastic  development  of  thought  is  the  adoption  of  certain 
mental  tendencies,  not  altogether  heedlessly,  as  in  tychasm, 
nor  quite  blindly  by  the  mere  force  of  circumstances  or  of 
logic,  as  in  anancasm,  but  by  an  immediate  attraction  for 
the  idea  itself,  whose  nature  is  divined  before  the  mind 
possesses  it,  by  the  power  of  sympathy,  that  is,  by  virtue 
of  the  continuity  of  mind;  and  this  mental  tendency  may 
be  of  three  varieties,  as  follows:  First,  it  may  affect  a 
whole  people  or  community  in  its  collective  personality, 
and  be  thence  communicated  to  such  individuals  as  are  in 
powerfully  sympathetic  connection  with  the  collective 
people,  although  they  may  be  intellectually  incapable  of 
attaining  the  idea  by  their  private  understandings  or  even 
perhaps  of  consciously  apprehending  it.  Second,  it  may 
affect  a  private  person  directly,  yet  so  that  he  is  only  enabled 
to  apprehend  the  idea,  or  to  appreciate  its  attractiveness, 


288  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

by  virtue  of  his  sympathy  with  his  neighbors,  under  the  in 
fluence  of  a  striking  experience  or  development  of  thought. 
The  conversion  of  St.  Paul  may  be  taken  as  an  example  of 
what  is  meant.  Third,  it  may  affect  an  individual,  inde 
pendently  of  his  human  affections,  by  virtue  of  an  attraction 
it  exercises  upon  his  mind,  even  before  he  has  comprehended 
it.  This  is  the  phenomenon  which  has  been  well  called  the 
divination  of  genius;  for  it  is  due  to  the  continuity  between 
the  man's  mind  and  the  Most  High. 

Let  us  next  consider  by  means  of  what  tests  we  can  dis 
criminate  between  these  different  categories  of  evolution. 
No  absolute  criterion  is  possible  in  the  nature  of  things, 
since  in  the  nature  of  things  there  is  no  sharp  line  of  de 
marcation  between  the  different  classes.  Nevertheless, 
quantitative  symptoms  may  be  found  by  which  a  sagacious 
and  sympathetic  judge  of  human  nature  may  be  able  to 
estimate  the  approximate  proportions  in  which  the  different 
kinds  of  influence  are  commingled. 

So  far  as  the  historical  evolution  of  human  thought  has 
been  tychastic,  it  should  have  proceeded  by  insensible  or 
minute  steps;  for  such  is  the  nature  of  chances  when  so 
multiplied  as  to  show  phenomena  of  regularity.  For  ex 
ample,  assume  that  of  the  native-born  white  adult  males 
of  the  United  States  in  1880,  one-fourth  part  were  below 
5  feet  4  inches  in  stature  and  one- fourth  part  above  5  feet 
8  inches.  Then  by  the  principles  of  probability,  among  the 
whole  population,  we  should  expect 

216  under  4  feet  6  inches,  216  above  6  feet  6  inches 

48      "      4    "    5      "  48      "      6    "    7      " 

9      "      4    "    4      "  9      "      6     "     8      " 

less  than  2      "      4    "    3      "      less  than  2      "      6    "    9      " 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  289 

I  set  down  these  figures  to  show  how  insignificantly  few 
are  the  cases  in  which  anything  very  far  out  of  the  common 
run  presents  itself  by  chance.  Though  the  stature  of  only 
every  second  man  is  included  within  the  four  inches  be 
tween  5  feet  4  inches  and  5  feet  8  inches,  yet  if  this  interval 
be  extended  by  thrice  four  inches  above  and  below,  it  will 
embrace  all  our  8  millions  odd  of  native-born  adult  white 
males  (of  1880),  except  only  9  taller  and  9  shorter. 

The  test  of  minute  variation,  if  not  satisfied,  absolutely 
negatives  ty chasm.  If  it  is  satisfied,  we  shall  find  that  it 
negatives  anancasm  but  not  agapasm.  We  want  a  positive 
test,  satisfied  by  tychasm,  only.  Now  wherever  we  find 
men's  thought  taking  by  imperceptible  degrees  a  turn  con 
trary  to  the  purposes  which  animate  them,  in  spite  of  their 
highest  impulses,  there,  we  may  safely  conclude,  there  has 
been  a  tychastic  action. 

Students  of  the  history  of  mind  there  be  of  an  erudition 
to  fill  an  imperfect  scholar  like  me  with  envy  edulcorated 
by  joyous  admiration,  who  maintain  that  ideas  when  just 
started  are  and  can  be  little  more  than  freaks,  since  they 
cannot  yet  have  been  critically  examined,  and  further  that 
everywhere  and  at  all  times  progress  has  been  so  gradual 
that  it  is  difficult  to  make  out  distinctly  what  original  step 
any  given  man  has  taken.  It  would  follow  that  tychasm 
has  been  the  sole  method  of  intellectual  development.  I 
have  to  confess  I  cannot  read  history  so;  I  cannot  help 
thinking  that  while  tychasm  has  sometimes  been  operative, 
at  others  great  steps  covering  nearly  the  same  ground  and 
made  by  different  men  independently,  have  been  mistaken 
for  a  succession  of  small  steps,  and  further  that  students 


290  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

have  been  reluctant  to  admit  a  real  entitative  "  spirit "  of 
an  age  or  of  a  people,  under  the  mistaken  and  unscrutinized 
impression  that  they  should  thus  be  opening  the  door  to  wild 
and  unnatural  hypotheses.  I  find,  on  the  contrary,  that, 
however  it  may  be  with  the  education  of  individual  minds, 
the  historical  development  of  thought  has  seldom  been 
of  a  tychastic  nature,  and  exclusively  in  backward  and 
barbarizing  movements.  I  desire  to  speak  with  the  extreme 
modesty  which  befits  a  student  of  logic  who  is  required  to 
survey  so  very  wide  a  field  of  human  thought  that  he  can 
cover  it  only  by  a  reconnaissance,  to  which  only  the  greatest 
skill  and  most  adroit  methods  can  impart  any  value  at  all; 
but,  after  all,  I  can  only  express  my  own  opinions  and  not 
those  of  anybody  else;  and  in  my  humble  judgment,  the 
largest  example  of  tychasm  is  afforded  by  the  history  of 
Christianity,  from  about  its  establishment  by  Constantine, 
to,  say,  the  time  of  the  Irish  monasteries,  an  era  or  eon  of 
about  500  years.  Undoubtedly  the  external  circumstance 
which  more  than  all  others  at  first  inclined  men  to  accept 
Christianity  in  its  loveliness  and  tenderness,  was  the  fearful 
extent  to  which  society  was  broken  up  into  units  by  the  un 
mitigated  greed  and  hard-heartedness  into  which  the 
Romans  had  seduced  the  world.  And  yet  it  was  that  very 
same  fact,  more  than  any  other  external  circumstance,  that 
fostered  that  bitterness  against  the  wicked  world  of  which 
the  primitive  gospel  of  Mark  contains  not  a  single  trace. 
At  least,  I  do  not  detect  it  in  the  remark  about  the  blas 
phemy  against  the  Holy  Ghost,  where  nothing  is  said  about 
vengeance,  nor  even  in  that  speech  where  the  closing  lines  of 
Isaiah  are  quoted,  about  the  worm  and  the  fire  that  feed 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  291 

upon  the  "carcasses  of  the  men  that  have  transgressed 
against  me."  But  little  by  little  the  bitterness  increases 
until  in  the  last  book  of  the  New  Testament,  its  poor  dis 
tracted  author  represents  that  all  the  time  Christ  was  talk 
ing  about  having  come  to  save  the  world,  the  secret  design 
was  to  catch  the  entire  human  race,  with  the  exception  of  a 
paltry  144,000,  and  souse  them  all  in  a  brimstone  lake, 
and  as  the  smoke  of  their  torment  went  up  forever  and  ever, 
to  turn  and  remark,  "  There  is  no  curse  any  more."  Would 
it  be  an  insensible  smirk  or  a  fiendish  grin  that  should 
accompany  such  an  utterance?  I  wish  I  could  believe  St. 
John  did  not  write  it;  but  it  is  his  gospel  which  tells  about 
the  "  resurrection  unto  condemnation,"  —  that  is  of  men's 
being  resuscitated  just  for  the  sake  of  torturing  them;  — 
and,  at  any  rate,  the  Revelation  is  a  very  ancient  composi 
tion.  One  can  understand  that  the  early  Christians  were 
like  men  trying  with  all  their  might  to  climb  a  steep  declivity 
of  smooth  wet  clay;  the  deepest  and  truest  element  of 
their  life,  animating  both  heart  and  head,  was  universal 
love;  but  they  were  continually,  and  against  their  wills, 
slipping  into  a  party  spirit,  every  slip  serving  as  a  precedent, 
in  a  fashion  but  too  familiar  to  every  man.  This  party  feel 
ing  insensibily  grew  until  by  about  A.D.  330  the  luster  of 
the  pristine  integrity  that  in  St.  Mark  reflects  the  wh.te 
spirit  of  light  was  so  far  tarnished  that  Eusebius,  (the  Jared 
Sparks  of  that  day),  in  the  preface  to  his  History,  could  an 
nounce  his  intention  of  exaggerating  everything  that  tended 
to  the  glory  of  the  church  and  of  suppressing  whatever 
might  disgrace  it.  His  Latin  contemporary  Lactantius  is 
worse,  still;  and  so  the  darkling  went  on  increasing  until 


292  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

before  the  end  of  the  century  the  great  library  of  Alexan 
dria  was  destroyed  by  Theophilus, 4  until  Gregory  the  Great, 
two  centuries  later,  burnt  the  great  library  of  Rome,  pro 
claiming  that  "Ignorance  is  the  mother  of  devotion," 
(which  is  true,  just  as  oppression  and  injustice  is  the 
mother  of  spirituality),  until  a  sober  description  of  the 
state  of  the  church  would  be  a  thing  our  not  too  nice  news 
papers  would  treat  as  "  unfit  for  publication."  All  this 
movement  is  shown  by  the  application  of  the  test  given 
above  to  have  been  tychastic.  Another  very  much  like 
it  on  a  small  scale,  only  a  hundred  times  swifter,  for  the 
study  of  which  there  are  documents  by  the  library-full, 
is  to  be  found  in  the  history  of  the  French  Revolution. 

Anancastic  evolution  advances  by  successive  strides 
with  pauses  between.  The  reason  is  that  in  this  process 
a  habit  of  thought  having  been  overthrown  is  supplanted  by 
the  next  strongest.  Now  this  next  strongest  is  sure  to  be 
widely  disparate  from  the  first,  and  as  often  as  not  is  its 
direct  contrary.  It  reminds  one  of  our  old  rule  of  making 
the  second  candidate  vice-president.  This  character,  there 
fore,  clearly  distinguishes  anancasm  from  tychasm.  The 
character  which  distinguishes  it  from  agapasm  is  its  pur- 
poselessness.  But  external  and  internal  anancasm  have  to 
be  examined  separately.  Development  under  the  pressure 
of  external  circumstances,  or  cataclysmine  evolution, 
is  in  most  cases  unmistakable  enough.  It  has  number 
less  degrees  of  intensity,  from  the  brute  force,  the  plain  war, 
which  has  more  than  once  turned  the  current  of  the  world's 
thought,  down  to  the  hard  fact  of  evidence,  or  what  has  been 

*  See  Draper's  History  of  Intellectual  Development,  chap.  x. 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  293 

taken  for  it,  which  has  been  known  to  convince  men  by 
hordes.  The  only  hesitation  than  can  subsist  in  the  presence 
of  such  a  history  is  a  quantitative  one.  Never  are  external 
influences  the  only  ones  which  affect  the  mind,  and  therefore 
it  must  be  a  matter  of  judgment  for  which  it  would  scarcely 
be  worth  while  to  attempt  to  set  rules,  whether  a  given 
movement  is  to  be  regarded  as  principally  governed  from 
without  or  not.  In  the  rise  of  medieval  thought,  I  mean 
scholasticism  and  the  synchronistic  art  developments,  un 
doubtedly  the  crusades  and  the  discovery  of  the  writings  of 
Aristotle  were  powerful  influences.  The  development  of 
scholasticism  from  Roscellin  to  Albertus  Magnus  closely 
follows  the  successive  steps  in  the  knowledge  of  Aristotle. 
Prantl  thinks  that  that  is  the  whole  story,  and  few  men 
have  thumbed  more  books  than  Carl  Prantl.  He  has  done 
good  solid  work,  notwithstanding  his  slap-dash  judgments. 
But  we  shall  never  make  so  much  as  a  good  beginning 
of  comprehending  scholasticism  until  the  whole  has  been 
systematically  explored  and  digested  by  a  company  of  stu 
dents  regularly  organized  and  held  under  rule  for  that  pur 
pose.  But  as  for  the  period  we  are  now  specially  consider 
ing,  that  which  synchronised  the  Romanesque  architecture, 
the  literature  is  easily  mastered.  It  does  not  quite  justify 
PrantPs  dicta  as  to  the  slavish  dependence  of  these  authors 
upon  their  authorities.  Moreover,  they  kept  a  definite 
purpose  steadily  before  their  minds,  throughout  all  their 
studies.  I  am,  therefore,  unable  to  offer  this  period  of 
scholasticism  as  an  example  of  pure  external  anancasm, 
which  seems  to  be  the  fluorine  of  the  intellectual  elements. 
Perhaps  the  recent  Japanese  reception  of  western  ideas  is 


294  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

the  purest  instance  of  it  in  history.  Yet  in  combination 
with  other  elements,  nothing  is  commoner.  If  the  devel 
opment  of  ideas  under  the  influence  of  the  study  of  external 
facts  be  considered  as  external  anancasm,  —  it  is  on  the 
border  between  the  external  and  the  internal  forms,  —  it 
is,  of  course,  the  principal  thing  in  modern  learning.  But 
Whewell,  whose  masterly  comprehension  of  the  history  of 
science  critics  have  been  too  ignorant  properly  to  appreciate, 
clearly  shows  that  it  is  far  from  being  the  overwhelmingly 
preponderant  influence,  even  there. 

Internal  anancasm,  or  logical  groping,  which  advances 
upon  a  predestined  line  without  being  able  to  foresee  whither 
it  is  to  be  carried  nor  to  steer  its  course,  this  is  the  rule  of 
development  of  philosophy.  Hegel  first  made  the  world 
understand  this;  and  he  seeks  to  make  logic  not  merely 
the  subjective  guide  and  monitor  of  thought,  which  was  all 
it  had  been  ambitioning  before,  but  to  be  the  very  main 
spring  of  thinking,  and  not  merely  of  individual  thinking  but 
of  discussion,  of  the  history  of  the  development  of  thought, 
of  all  history,  of  all  development.  This  involves  a  positive, 
clearly  demonstrable  error.  Let  the  logic  in  question  be 
of  whatever  kind  it  may,  a  logic  of  necessary  inference  or 
a  logic  of  probable  inference  (the  theory  might  perhaps 
be  shaped  to  fit  either),  in  any  case  it  supposes  that  logic  is 
sufficient  of  itself  to  determine  what  conclusion  follows 
from  given  premises;  for  unless  it  will  do  so  much,  it  will 
not  suffice  to  explain  why  an  individual  train  of  reasoning 
should  take  just  the  course  it  does  take,  to  say  nothing 
of  other  kinds  of  development.  It  thus  supposes  that  from 
given  premises,  only  one  conclusion  can  logically  be  drawn, 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  295 

and  that  there  is  no  scope  at  all  for  free  choice.  That  from 
given  premises  only  one  conclusion  can  logically  be  drawn, 
is  one  of  the  false  notions  which  have  come  from  logicians' 
confining  their  attention  to  that  Nantucket  of  thought,  the 
logic  of  non-relative  terms.  In  the  logic  of  relatives,  it 
does  not  hold  good. 

One  remark  occurs  to  me.  If  the  evolution  of  history  is 
in  considerable  part  of  the  nature  of  internal  anancasm,  it 
resembles  the  development  of  individual  men;  and  just  as 
33  years  is  a  rough  but  natural  unit  of  time  for  individuals, 
being  the  average  age  at  which  man  has  issue,  so  there 
should  be  an  approximate  period  at  the  end  of  which  one 
great  historical  movement  ought  to  be  likely  to  be  sup 
planted  by  another.  Let  us  see  if  we  can  make  out  any 
thing  of  the  kind.  Take  the  governmental  development  of 
Rome  as  being  sufficiently  long  and  set  down  the  principal 
dates. 

B.C.  753,  Foundation  of  Rome. 

B.C.  510,  Expulsion   of   the   Tarquins. 

B.C.      27,  Octavius  assumes  title  Augustus. 

A.D.  476,  End  of  Western  Empire. 

A.D.  962,  Holy  Roman  Empire. 

A.D.  1453,  Fall  of  Constantinople. 

The  last  event  was  one  of  the  most  significant  in  history, 
especially  for  Italy.  The  intervals  are  243,  483,  502,  486, 
491  years.  All  are  rather  curiously  near  equal,  except  the 
first  which  is  half  the  others.  Successive  reigns  of  kings 
would  not  commonly  be  so  near  equal.  Let  us  set  down 
a  few  dates  in  the  history  of  thought. 


296  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

B.C.  585,  Eclipse  of  Thales.  Beginning  of  Greek  phi 
losophy. 

A.D.      30,  The  crucifixion. 

A.D.  529,  Closing  of  Athenian  schools.  End  of  Greek 
philosophy. 

A.D.  1125,  (Approximate)  Rise  of  the  Universities  of 
Bologna  and  Paris. 

A.D.  1543,  Publication  of  the  "  De  Revolutionibus "  of 
Copernicus.  Beginning  of  Modern  Science. 

The  intervals  are  615,  499,  596,  418,  years.  In  the  history 
of  metaphysics,  we  may  take  the  following: 

B.C.  322,  Death  of  Aristotle. 
A.D.  1274,  Death  of  Aquinas. 
A.D.  1804,  Death  of  Kant. 

The  intervals  are  1595  and  530  years.  The  former  is  about 
thrice  the  latter. 

From  these  figures,  no  conclusion  can  fairly  be  drawn. 
At  the  same  time,  they  suggest  that  perhaps  there  may  be 
a  rough  natural  era  of  about  500  years.  Should  there  be 
any  independent  evidence  of  this,  the  intervals  noticed  may 
gain  some  significance. 

The  agapastic  development  of  thought  should,  if  it  exists, 
be  distinguished  by  its  purposive  character,  this  purpose 
being  the  development  of  an  idea.  We  should  have  a  direct 
agapic  or  sympathetic  comprehension  and  recognition  of  it, 
by  virtue  of  the  continuity  of  thought.  I  here  take  it  for 
granted  that  such  continuity  of  thought  has  been  sufficiently 
proved  by  the  arguments  used  in  my  paper  on  the  "  Law 
of  Mind  "  in  The  Monist  of  last  July.  Even  if  those  argu 
ments  are  not  quite  convincing  in  themselves,  yet  if  they 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  297 

are  reenforced  by  an  apparent  agapasm  in  the  history  of 
thought,  the  two  propositions  will  lend  one  another  mutual 
aid.  The  reader  will,  I  trust,  be  too  well  grounded  in  logic 
to  mistake  such  mutual  support  for  a  vicious  circle  in  reason 
ing.  If  it  could  be  shown  directly  that  there  is  such  an 
entity  as  the  "  spirit  of  an  age  "  or  of  a  people,  and  that 
mere  individual  intelligence  will  not  account  for  all  the 
phenomena,  this  would  be  proof  enough  at  once  of  agapas- 
ticism  and  of  synechism.  I  must  acknowledge  that  I  am 
unable  to  produce  a  cogent  demonstration  of  this;  but  I 
am,  I  believe,  able  to  adduce  such  arguments  as  will  serve 
to  confirm  those  which  have  been  drawn  from  other  facts. 
I  believe  that  all  the  greatest  achievements  of  mind  have 
been  beyond  the  powers  of  unaided  individuals;  and  I  find, 
apart  from  the  support  this  opinion  receives  from  synechistic 
considerations,  and  from  the  purposive  character  of  many 
great  movements,  direct  reason  for  so  thinking  in  the  sub 
limity  of  the  ideas  and  in  their  occurring  simultaneously 
and  independently  to  a  number  of  individuals  of  no  ex 
traordinary  general  powers.  The  pointed  Gothic  architec 
ture  in  several  of  its  developments  appears  to  me  to  be  of 
such  a  character.  All  attempts  to  imitate  it  by  modern 
architects  of  the  greatest  learning  and  genius  appear  flat 
and  tame,  and  are  felt  by  their  authors  to  be  so.  Yet  at  the 
time  the  style  was  living,  there  was  quite  an  abundance  of 
men  capable  of  producing  works  of  this  kind  of  gigantic 
sublimity  and  power.  In  more  than  one  case,  extant  docu 
ments  show  that  the  cathedral  chapters,  in  the  selection  of 
architects,  treated  high  artistic  genius  as  a  secondary  con 
sideration,  as  if  there  were  no  lack  of  persons  able  to  supply 


298  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

that;  and  the  results  justify  their  confidence.  Were  indi 
viduals  in  general,  then,  in  those  ages  possessed  of  such  lofty 
natures  and  high  intellect?  Such  an  opinion  would  break 
down  under  the  first  examination. 

How  many  times  have  men  now  in  middle  life  seen  great 
discoveries  made  independently  and  almost  simultaneously! 
The  first  instance  I  remember  was  the  prediction  of  a  planet 
exterior  to  Uranus  by  Leverrier  and  Adams.  One  hardly 
knows  to  whom  the  principle  of  the  conservation  of  energy 
ought  to  be  attributed,  although  it  may  reasonably  be  con 
sidered  as  the  greatest  discovery  science  has  ever  made. 
The  mechanical  theory  of  heat  was  set  forth  by  Rankine 
and  by  Clausius  during  the  same  month  of  February,  1850; 
and  there  are  eminent  men  who  attribute  this  great  step 
to  Thomson. 5  The  kinetical  theory  of  gases,  after  being 
started  by  John  Bernoulli  and  long  buried  in  oblivion,  was 
reinvented  and  applied  to  the  explanation  not  merely  of  the 
laws  of  Boyle,  Charles,  and  Avogadro,  but  also  of  diffusion 
and  viscosity,  by  at  least  three  modern  physicists  separately. 
It  is  well  known  that  the  doctrine  of  natural  selection  was 
presented  by  Wallace  and  by  Darwin  at  the  same  meeting 
of  the  British  Association;  and  Darwin  in  his  "  Historical 
Sketch  "  prefixed  to  the  later  editions  of  his  book  shows 
that  both  were  anticipated  by  obscure  forerunners.  The 
method  of  spectrum  analysis  was  claimed  for  Swan  as  well 
as  for  Kirchhoff,  and  there  were  others  who  perhaps  had 
still  better  claims.  The  authorship  of  the  Periodical  Law 
of  the  Chemical  Elements  is  disputed  between  a  Russian, 

5  Thomson,  himself,  in  his  article  Heat  in  the  Encyclopedia  Britannica, 
never  once  mentions  the  name  of  Clausius. 


EVOLUTIONARY    LOVE  299 

a  German,  and  an  Englishman;  although  there  is  no  room 
for  doubt  that  the  principal  merit  belongs  to  the  first.  These 
are  nearly  all  the  greatest  discoveries  of  our  times.  It  is 
the  same  with  the  inventions.  It  may  not  be  surprising 
that  the  telegraph  should  have  been  independently  made  by 
several  inventors,  because  it  was  an  easy  corollary  from 
scientific  facts  well  made  out  before.  But  it  was  not  so 
with  the  telephone  and  other  inventions.  Ether,  the  first 
anaesthetic,  was  introduced  independently  by  three  different 
New  England  physicians.  Now  ether  had  been  a  common 
article  for  a  century.  It  had  been  in  one  of  the  pharma 
copoeias  three  centuries  before.  It  is  quite  incredible  that 
its  anaesthetic  property  should  not  have  been  known;  it 
was  known.  It  had  probably  passed  from  mouth  to  ear 
as  a  secret  from  the  days  of  Basil  Valentine;  but  for  long 
it  had  been  a  secret  of  the  Punchinello  kind.  In  New 
England,  for  many  years,  boys  had  used  it  tor  amusement. 
Why  then  had  it  not  been  put  to  its  serious  use?  No  reason 
can  be  given,  except  that  the  motive  to  do  so  was  not  strong 
enough.  The  motives  to  doing  so  could  only  have  been 
desire  for  gain  and  philanthropy.  About  1846,  the  date  of 
the  introduction,  philanthropy  was  undoubtedly  in  an  un 
usually  active  condition.  That  sensibility,  or  sentimental- 
ism,  which  had  been  introduced  in  the  previous  century, 
had  undergone  a  ripening  process,  in  consequence  of  which, 
though  now  less  intense  than  it  had  previously  been,  it  was 
more  likely  to  influence  unreflecting  people  than  it  had  ever 
been.  All  three  of  the  ether-claimants  had  probably  been 
influenced  by  the  desire  for  gain;  but  nevertheless  they  were 
certainly  not  insensible  to  the  agapic  influences. 


3oo  LOVE    AND    CHANCE 

I  doubt  if  any  of  the  great  discoveries  ought,  properly, 
to  be  considered  as  altogether  individual  achievements;  and 
I  think  many  will  share  this  doubt.  Yet,  if  not,  what  an 
argument  for  the  continuity  of  mind,  and  for  agapasticism 
is  here!  I  do  not  wish  to  be  very  strenuous.  If  thinkers 
will  only  be  persuaded  to  lay  aside  their  prejudices  and 
apply  themselves  to  studying  the  evidences  of  this  doctrine, 
I  shall  be  fully  content  to  await  the  final  decision. 


Supplementary  Essay 
THE    PRAGMATISM    OF   PEIRCE 

BY 

JOHN  DEWEY 

THE  term  pragmatism  was  introduced  into  literature  in  the 
opening  sentences  of  Professor  James's  California  Union  address 
in  1898.  The  sentences  run  as  follows:  "  The  principle  of 
pragmatism,  as  we  may  call  it,  may  be  expressed  in  a  variety 
of  ways,  all  of  them  very  simple.  In  the  Popular  Science 
Monthly  for  January,  1878,  Mr.  Charles  S.  Peirce  introduces  it 
as  follows:"  etc.  The  readers  who  have  turned  to  the  volume 
referred  to  have  not,  however,  found  the  word  there.  From 
other  sources  we  know  that  the  name  as  well  as  the  idea  was 
furnished  by  Mr.  Peirce.  The  latter  has  told  us  that  both  the 
word  and  the  idea  were  suggested  to  him  by  a  reading  of  Kant, 
the  idea  by  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,  the  term  by  the 
"  Critique  of  Practical  Reason."  x  The  article  in  the  Monist 
gives  such  a  good  statement  of  both  the  idea  and  the  reason  for 
selecting  the  term  that  it  may  be  quoted  in  extenso.  Peirce  sets 
out  by  saying  that  with  men  who  work  in  laboratories,  the  habit 
of  mind  is  molded  by  experimental  work  much  more  than  they 
are  themselves  aware.  "  Whatever  statement  you  may  make  to 
him,  he  [the  experimentalist]  will  either  understand  as  meaning 
that  if  a  given  prescription  for  an  experiment  ever  can  be  and 
ever  is  carried  out  in  act,  an  experience  of  a  given  description 
will  result,  or  else  he  will  see  no  sense  at  all  in  what  you  say." 
Having  himself  the  experimental  mind  and  being  interested  in 
methods  of  thinking,  "  he  framed  the  theory  that  a  conception , 
that  is,  the  rational  purport  of  a  word  or  other  expression,  lies 

1  See  article  on  "  Pragmatism,"  in  Baldwin's  Dictionary,  Vol.  2.,  p. 
322,  and  the  Monist,  Vol.  15,  p.  162. 

301 


302  THE    PRAGMATISM     OF    PE1RCE 

exclusively  in  its  bearing  upon  the  conduct  of  life;  so  that, 
since  obviously  nothing  that  might  not  result  from  experiment 
can  have  any  direct  bearing  upon  conduct,  if  one  can  define  ac 
curately  all  the  conceivable  experimental  phenomena  which  the 
affirmation  or  denial  of  a  concept  could  imply,  one  will  have 
therein  a  complete  definition  of  the  concept,  and  there  is  abso 
lutely  nothing  more  in  it.  For  this  doctrine,  he  invented  the 
name  pragmatism." 

After  saying  that  some  of  his  friends  wished  him  to  call  the 
doctrine  practicism  or  practicalism,  he  says  that  he  had  learned 
philosophy  from  Kant,  and  that  to  one  "  who  still  thought  in 
Kantian  terms  most  readily,  praktisch  and  pragmatisch  were  as 
far  apart  as  the  two  poles,  the  former  belonging  to  a  region  of 
thought  where  no  mind  of  the  experimentalist  type  can  ever 
make  sure  of  solid  ground  under  his  feet,  the  latter  expressing 
relation  to  some  definite  human  purpose.  Now  quite  the  most 
striking  feature  of  the  new  theory  was  its  recognition  of  an  in 
separable  connection  between  rational  cognition  and  human 
purpose." 2 

From  this  brief  statement,  it  will  be  noted  that  Peirce  con 
fined  the  significance  of  the  term  to  the  determination  of  the 
meaning  of  terms,  or  better,  propositions;  the  theory  was  not,  of 
itself,  a  theory  of  the  test,  or  the  truth,  of  propositions.  Hence 
the  title  of  his  original  article:  How  to  Make  Ideas  Clear.  In 
his  later  writing,  after  the  term  had  been  used  as  a  theory  of 
truth,  —  he  proposed  the  more  limited  "  pragmaticism "  to 
designate  his  original  specific  meaning.3  But  even  with  respect 
to  the  meaning  of  propositions,  there  is  a  marked  difference 
between  his  pragmaticism  and  the  pragmatism  of,  say,  James. 
Some  of  the  critics  (especially  continental)  of  the  latter  would 
have  saved  themselves  some  futile  beating  of  the  air,  if  they 
had  reacted  to  James's  statements  instead  of  to  their  own  as- 

2  Kant  discriminates  the  laws  of  morality,  which  are  a  priori,  from 
rules  of  skill,  having  to  do  with  technique  or  art,  and  counsels  of  prudence, 
having  to  do  with  welfare.     The  latter  he  calls  pragmatic;  the  a  priori 
laws  practical.    See  Metaphysics  of  Morals,  Abbott's  trans.,  pp.  33  and  34. 

3  See  the  article  in  the  Monist  already  mentioned,  and  another  one 
in  the  same  volume,  p.  481,  "The  Issues  of  Pragmaticism." 


THE    PRAGMATISM     OF    PEIRCE  303 

sociations  with  the  word  "  pragmatic."  Thus  James  says  in  his 
California  address:  "  The  effective  meaning  of  any  philosophic 
proposition  can  always  be  brought  down  to  some  particular  con 
sequence,  in  our  future  practical  experience,  whether  active  or 
passive;  the  point  lying  rather  in  the  fact  that  the  experience 
must  be  particular,  than  in  the  fact  that  it  must  be  active" 
(Italics  mine.) 

Now  the  curious  fact  is  that  Peirce  puts  more  emphasis  upon 
practise  (or  conduct)  and  less  upon  the  particular;  in  fact,  he 
transfers  the  emphasis  to  the  general.  The  following  passage  is 
worth  quotation  because  of  the  definiteness  with  which  it  identi 
fies  meaning  with  both  the  future  and  with  the  general.  "  The 
rational  meaning  of  every  proposition  lies  in  the  future.  How 
so?  The  meaning  of  a  proposition  is  itself  a  proposition.  In 
deed,  it  is  no  other  than  the  very  proposition  of  which  it  is  the 
meaning:  it  is  a  translation  of  it.  But  of  the  myriads  of  forms 
into  which  a  proposition  may  be  translated,  which  is  that  one 
which  is  to  be  called  its  very  meaning?  It  is,  according  to  the 
pragmaticist,  that  form  in  which  the  proposition  becomes  ap 
plicable  to  human  conduct,  not  in  these  or  those  special  cir 
cumstances  nor  when  one  entertains  this  or  that  special  design, 
but  that  form  which  is  most  applicable  to  self-control  under 
every  situation  and  to  every  purpose."  Hence,  "  it  must  be 
simply  the  general  description  of  all  the  experimental  phenomena 
which  the  assertion  of  the  proposition  virtually  predicts."  Or, 
paraphrasing,  pragmatism  identifies  meaning  with  formation 
of  a  habit,  or  way  of  acting  having  the  greatest  generality  pos 
sible,  or  the  widest  range  of  application  to  particulars.  Since 
habits  or  ways  of  acting  are  just  as  real  as  particulars,  it  is  com 
mitted  to  a  belief  in  the  reality  of  "  universals."  Hence  it  is 
not  a  doctrine  of  phenomenalism,  for  while  the  richness  of  phe 
nomena  lies  in  their  sensuous  quality,  pragmatism  does  not  in 
tend  to  define  these  (leaving  them,  as  it  were,  to  speak  for 
themselves),  but  "eliminates  their  sential  element,  and  en 
deavors  to  define  the  rational  purport,  and  this  it  finds  in  the 
purposive  bearing  of  the  word  or  proposition  in  question.,''1 
Moreover,  not  only  are  generals  real,  but  they  are  physically 


304  THE    PRAGMATISM    OF    PEIRCE 

efficient.  The  meanings  "  the  air  is  stuffy  "  and  "  stuffy  air  is 
unwholesome  "  may  determine,  for  example,  the  opening  of  the 
window.  Accordingly  on  the  ethical  side,  "  the  pragmaticist  does 
not  make  the  summum  bonum  to  consist  in  action,  but  makes 
it  to  consist  in  that  process  of  evolution  whereby  the  existent 
comes  more  and  more  to  embody  those  generals  .  .  .  ;  in  other 
words,  becomes,  through  action  an  embodiment  of  rational  pur 
ports  or  habits  generalized  as  widely  as  possible." 4 

The  passages  quoted  should  be  compared  with  what  Peirce 
has  to  say  in  the  Baldwin  Dictionary  article.  There  he  says 
that  James's  doctrine  seems  to  commit  us  to  the  belief  "  that 
the  end  of  man  is  action  —  a  stoical  maxim  which  does  not  com 
mend  itself  as  forcibly  to  the  present  writer  at  the  age  of  sixty 
as  it  did  at  thirty.  If  it  be  admitted,  on  the  contrary,  that 
action  wants  an  end,  and  that  the  end  must  be  something  of  a 
general  description,  then  the  spirit  of  the  maxim  itself  .  .  . 
would  direct  us  toward  something  different  from  practical  facts, 
namely,  to  general  ideas.  .  .  .  The  only  ultimate  good  which 
the  practical  facts  to  which  the  maxim  directs  attention  can 
subserve  is  to  further  the  development  of  concrete  reasonableness. 
.  .  .  Almost  everybody  will  now  agree  that  the  ultimate  good 
lies  in  the  evolutionary  process  in  some  way.  If  so,  it  is  not 
in  individual  reactions  in  their  segregation,  but  in  something 
general  or  continuous.  Synechism  is  founded  on  the  notion  that 
the  coalescence,  the  becoming  continuous,  the  becoming  gov 
erned  by  laws,  the  becoming  instinct  with  general  ideas,  are 
but  phases  of  one  and  the  same  process  of  the  growth  of  reason 
ableness.  This  is  first  shown  to  be  true  with  mathematical 
exactitude  in  the  field  of  logic,  and  is  thence  inferred  to  hold 
good  metaphysically.  It  is  not  opposed  to  pragmaticism  .  .  . 
but  includes  that  procedure  as  a  step." 

Here  again  we  have  the  doctrine  of  pragmaticism  as  a  doc 
trine  that  meaning  or  rational  purport  resides  in  the  setting  up 
of  habits  or  generalized  methods,  a  doctrine  passing  over  into 

*  It  is  probably  fair  to  see  here  an  empirical  rendering  of  the  Kantian 
generality  of  moral  action,  while  the  distinction  and  connection  of  "  ra 
tional  purport"  and  "sensible  particular"  have  also  obvious  Kantian 
associations. 


THE    PRAGMATISM    OF    PEIRCE  305 

the  metaphysics  of  synechism.     It  will  be  well  now  to  recur 
explicitly  to  Peirce's  earlier  doctrine  which  he  seems  to  qualify 

—  although,  as  he  notes,  he  upheld  the  doctrine  of  the  reality 
of  generals  even  at  the  earlier  period.    Peirce  sets  out,  in  his 
article  on  the  "  Fixation  of  Belief,"  with  the  empirical  differ 
ence  of  doubt  and  belief  expressed  in  the  facts  that  belief  deter 
mines  a  habit  while  doubt  does  not,  and  that  belief  is  calm 
and  satisfactory  while  doubt  is  an  uneasy  and  dissatisfied  state 
from  which  we  struggle  to  emerge;  to  attain,  that  is,  a  state  of 
belief,  a  struggle  which  may  be  called  inquiry.    The  sole  object 
of  inquiry  is  the  fixation  of  belief.  The  scientific  method  of  fixa 
tion  has,  however,  certain  rivals:    one  is  that  of  "  tenacity"  — 
constant  reiteration,  dwelling  upon  everything  conducive  to  the 
belief,  avoidance  of  everything  which  might  unsettle  it  —  the 
will  to  believe.     The  method  breaks  down  in  practice  because 
of  man's  social  nature;   we  have  to  take  account  of  contrary 
beliefs  in  others,  so  that  the  real  problem  is  to  fix  the  belief  of 
the  community;    for  otherwise  our  own  belief  is  precariously 
exposed  to  attack  and  doubt.    Hence  the  resort  to  the  method 
of  authority.    This  method  breaks  down  in  time  by  the  fact 
that  authority  can  not  fix  all  beliefs  in  all  their  details,  and 
because  of  the  conflict  which  arises  between  organized  traditions. 
There  may  then  be  recourse  to  what  is  "  agreeable  to  reason  " 

—  a  method  potent  in  formation  of  taste  and  in  esthetic  produc 
tions  and  in  the  history  of  philosophy,  —  but  a  method  which 
again  fails  to  secure  permanent  agreements  in  society,  and  so 
leaves  individual  belief  at  the  mercy  of  attack.    Hence,  finally, 
recourse    to    science,    whose    fundamental    hypothesis    is    this: 
"  There  are  real  things,  whose  characters  are  entirely  indepen 
dent  of  our  opinions  about  them;  those  realities  affect  our  senses 
according  to  regular  laws,  and  ...  by  taking  advantage  of  the 
laws  of  perception,  we  can  ascertain  by  reasoning  how  things 
really  are,  and  any  man  if  he  have  sufficient  experience  and  rea 
son  enough  about  it,  will  be  led  to  the  one  true  conclusion."  5 

It    will    be   noted    that    the    quotation    employs    the    terms 
"  reality  "  and  "  truth,"  while  it  makes  them  a  part  of  the  state- 

•  P.  26. 


306  THE    PRAGMATISM    OF    PEIRCE 

ment  of  the  hypothesis  entertained  in  scientific  procedure.  Upon 
such  a  basis,  what  meanings  attach  to  the  terms  "  reality  "  and 
"  truth  "  ?  Since  they  are  general  terms,  their  meanings  must  be 
determined  on  the  basis  of  the  effects,  having  practical  bearings, 
which  the  object  of  our  conception  has.  Now  the  effect  which 
real  things  have  is  to  cause  beliefs;  beliefs  are  then  the  conse 
quences  which  give  the  general  term  reality  a  "  rational  purport." 
And  on  the  assumption  of  the  scientific  method,  the  distinguishing 
/character  of  the  real  object  must  be  that  it  tends  to  produce  a 
single  universally  accepted  belief.  "  All  the  followers  of  science 
are  fully  persuaded  that  the  processes  of  investigation,  if  only 
pushed  far  enough,  will  give  one  certain  solution  to  every  ques 
tion  to  which  they  can  be  applied."  "  This  activity  of  thought 
by  which  we  are  carried,  not  where  we  wish,  but  to  a  foreor 
dained  goal,  is  like  the  operation  of  destiny.  .  .  .  This  great 
law  is  embodied  in  the  conception  of  truth  and  reality.  The 
opinion  which  is  fated  to  be  ultimately  agreed  to  by  all  who 
investigate,  is  what  we  mean  by  the  truth,  and  the  object  repre- 
v  sented  in  this  opinion  is  the  real." 6  In  a  subsequent  essay 
(on  the  "  Probability  of  Induction ")  Peirce  expressly  draws 
the  conclusion  which  follows  from  this  statement;  viz.,  that  this 
conception  of  truth  and  reality  makes  everything  depend  upon 
the  character  of  the  methods  of  inquiry  and  inference  by  which 
'  conclusions  are  reached.  "  In  the  case  of  synthetic  inferences 
we  know  only  the  degree  of  trustworthiness  of  our  proceeding. 
As  all  knowledge  comes  from  synthetic  inference,  we  must  also 
infer  that  all  human  certainty  consists  merely  in  our  knowing 
that  the  processes  by  which  our  knowledge  has  been  derived 
are  such  as  must  generally  have  led  to  true  conclusions  " 7  — 
true  conclusions,  once  more,  being  those  which  command  the 
agreement  of  competent  inquiries. 

Summing  up,  we  may  say  that  Peirce's  pragmaticism  is  a 
doctrine  concerning  the  meaning,  conception,  or  rational  pur 
port  of  objects,  namely,  that  these  consist  in  the  "  effects,  which 
v    might  conceivably  have  practical  bearings,  we  conceive  the  ob- 

6  P.  S6-57-  7  P.   105- 


THE    PRAGMATISM    OF    PEIRCE  307 

ject  of  our  conception  to  have.  Then,  our  conception  of  these 
effects  is  the  whole  of  our  conception  of  the  object."  8  "  Our 

-  idea  of  anything  is  our  idea  of  its  sensible  effects,"  and  if  we  have 
any  doubt  as  to  whether  we  really  believe  the  effects  to  be  sensi 
ble  or  no,  we  have  only  to  ask  ourselves  whether  or  no  we  should 
act  any  differently  in  their  presence.    In  short,  our  own  responses 

v,  -t o  sensory  stimuli  are  the  ultimate,  or  testing,  ingredients  in  our 
conception  of  an  object.  In  the  literal  sense  of  the  word  pragma- 
tist,  therefore,  Peirce  is  more  of  a  pragmatist  than  James. 

He  is  also  less  of  a  nominalist.    That  is  to  say,  he  emphasizes 
l-  much  less  the  particular  sensible  consequence,  and  much  more 
the  habit,  the  generic  attitude  of  response,  set  up  in  consequence 
of  experiences  with  a  thing.    In  the  passage  in  the  Dictionary 
already  quoted  he  speaks  as  if  in  his  later  life  he  attached  less 
importance  to  action,  and  more  to  "  concrete  reasonableness  " 
than  in  his  earlier  writing.    It  may  well  be  that  the  relative  em 
phasis  had  shifted.     But  there  is  at  most  but  a  difference  of 
emphasis.    For  in  his  later  doctrine,  concrete  rationality  means  a 
change  in  existence  brought  about  through  action,  and  through 
action  which  embodies  conceptions  whose  own  specific  existence 
consists  in  habitual  attitudes  of  response.    In  his  earlier  writing, 
the   emphasis  upon  habits,   as   something   generic,  is   explicit. 
^  "What  a   thing  means  is  simply  what  habits  it  involves."9 
More  elaborately,  "  Induction  infers  a  rule.    Now  the  belief  of 
a  rule  is  a  habit.    That  a  habit  is  a  rule,  active  in  us,  is  evident. 
^    That  every  belief  is  of  the  nature  of  a  habit,  in  so  far  as  it  is 
\    of  a  general  character,  has  been  shown  in  the  earlier  papers  of 
this  series."  10 

The  difference  between  Peirce  and  James  which  next  strikes 

*  us  is  the  greater  emphasis  placed  by  the  former  upon  the  method 
'  of  procedure.    As  the  quotations  already  made  show,  everything 

^ultimately  turned,  for  Peirce,  upon  the  trustworthiness  of  the 
procedures  of  inquiry.  Hence  his  high  estimate  of  logic,  as  com 
pared  with  James  —  at  least  James  in  his  later  days.  Hence  also 

s  P.  45.  9  P.  43.  1°  P.  151. 


308  THE    PRAGMATISM     OF    PEIRCE 

his  definite  rejection  of  the  appeal  to  the  Will  to  Believe  — 
under  the  form  of  what  he  calls  the  method  of  tenacity.  Closely 
associated  with  this  is  the  fact  that  Peirce  has  a  more  explicit 
dependence  upon  the  social  factor  than  has  James.  The  appeal 
in  Peirce  is  essentially  to  the  consensus  of  those  who  have  in 
vestigated,  using  methods  which  are  capable  of  employment  by 
all.  It  is  the  need  for  social  agreement,  and  the  fact  that  in  its 
absence  "  the  method  of  tenacity "  will  be  exposed  to  disin 
tegration  from  without,  which  finally  forces  upon  mankind  the 
wider  and  wider  utilization  of  the  scientific  method. 

Finally,  both  Peirce  and  James  are  realists.  The  reasonings  of 
both  depend  upon  the  assumption  of  real  things  which  really 
have  effects  or  consequences.  Of  the  two,  Peirce  makes  clearer 
the  fact  that  in  philosophy  at  least  we  are  dealing  with  the 
conception  of  reality,  with  reality  as  a  term  having  rational  pur 
port,  and  hence  with  something  whose  meaning  is  itself  to  be 
determined  in  terms  of  consequences.  That  "  reality  "  means 
the  object  of  those  beliefs  which  have,  after  prolonged  and 
cooperative  inquiry,  become^  stable,  and  "  truth  "  the  quality  of 
these  belief s,  is  a  logical  consequence  of  this  position.  Thus 
while  "  we  may  define  the  real  as  that  whose  characters  are 
independent  of  what  anybody  may  think  them  to  be  ...  it 
would  be  a  great  mistake  to  suppose  that  this  definition  makes 
the  idea  of  reality  perfectly  clear."  X1  For  it  is  only  the  out- 
v.  come  of  persistent  and  conjoint  inquiry  which  enables  us  to  give 
/intelligible  meaning  in  the  concrete  to  the  expression  "  char 
acters  independent  of  what  anybody  may  think  them  to  be." 
(This  is  the  pragmatic  way  out  of  the  egocentric  predicament.) 
And  while  my  purpose  is  wholly  expository  I  can  not  close  with 
out  inquiring  whether  recourse  to  Peirce  would  not  have  a  most 
beneficial  influence  in  contemporary  discussion.  Do  not  a  large 
part  of  our  epistemological  difficulties  arise  from  an  attempt  to 
define  the  "  real  "  as  something  given  prior  to  reflective  inquiry 
instead  of  as  that  which  reflective  inquiry  is  forced  to  reach  and 
to  which  when  it  is  reached  belief  can  stably  cling? 

11  P.  S3- 


BIBLIOGRAPHY   OF   PEIRCE'S   PUBLISHED     ^ 
WRITINGS  6'*'* 

I.  Writings  of  General  Interest.1 

4.  Three  papers  in  the  Journal  of  Speculative  Philosophy,  Vol.  a 
(1868). 

1.  "Questions    Concerning    Certain    Faculties    Claimed    for 

Man,"  pp.  103-114. 

2.  "Some  Consequences  of  Four  Incapacities,"  pp.  140-157. 

3.  "  Ground  of  Validity  of  the  Laws  of  Logic,"  pp.  193-208. 
These  three  papers,  somewhat  loosely  connected,  deal  mainly  with  the 

philosophy  of  discursive  thought.  The  first  deals  with  our  power  of  in 
tuition,  and  holds  that  "  every  thought  is  a  sign."  The  second,  one  of  the 
most  remarkable  of  Peirce's  writings,  contains  an  acute  criticism  of  the 
Cartesian  tradition  and  a  noteworthy  argument  against  the  traditional 
emphasis  on  "images"  in  thinking.  The  third  contains,  inter  alia,  a 
refutation  of  Mill's  indictment  of  the  syllogism.  The  same  volume  of  the 
Journal  contains  two  unsigned  communications  on  Nominalism  and  on  the 
Meaning  of  Determined. 

B.  Review  of  Fraser's  "  Berkeley,"  in  the  North  American  Review, 

Vol.  113  (1871),  pp.  449-472. 

This  paper  contains  an  important  analysis  on  medieval  realism,  and  of 
Berkeley's  nominalism.  (A  Scotist  realism  continues  to  distinguish  Peirce's 
work  after  this.) 

C.  "Illustrations    of    the    Logic    of    Science,"    in    Popular   Science 

Monthly,  Vols.  12-13  (1877-1878).  Reprinted  in  Pt.  I 
of  this  volume.  The  first  and  second  papers  were  also 
published  in  the  Revue  Philosophique,  Vols.  6-7  (1879). 

D.  Ten  papers  in  the  Monist,  Vols.   1-3    (1891-1893),  and   15-16 

(1905-1906).  The  first  five  are  reprinted  in  Pt.  II  of  this 
volume. 

The  sixth  paper,  "  Reply  to  the  Necessitarians,"  Vol.  3,  pp.  526-570,  is 
an  answer  to  the  criticism  of  the  foregoing  by  the  editor  of  the  Monist, 
Vol.  2,  pp.  56off.;  cf.  Vol.  3,  pp.  68ff.  and  57iff.,  and  McCrie,  "The  Issues 
of  Synechism,"  Vol.  3,  pp.  38off. 

1  The  following  classification  is  arbitrary,  as  some  of  Peirce's  most  sig 
nificant  reflections  occur  in  papers  under  headings  II.  and  III.  It  may, 
however,  be  useful. 

309 


310  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

7.  "What  Pragmatism  Is?"  Vol.  15,  pp.  161-181. 

8.  "  The  Issues  of  Pragmaticism,"  Vol.  15,  pp.  481-499. 

9.  "  Mr.  Peterson's  Proposed  Discussion,"  Vol.  16,  pp.  1478. 
10.  "  Prolegomena  to  an  Apology  for  Pragmaticism,"  Vol.  16, 

PP-  492-S40. 

The  last  four  papers  develop  Peirce's  thought  by  showing  its  agreement 
and  disagreement  with  the  pragmatism  of  James  and  Schiller.  The  last 
paper  contains  his  Method  of  Existential  Graphs. 

E.  "The  Reality  of  God,"  in  the  Hibbert  Journal,  Vol.  7   (1908), 

pp.  96-112.  (This  article  contains  brief  indications  of  many 
of  Peirce's  leading  ideas.) 

F.  Six  Papers  in  the  Open  Court,  Vols.  6-7  (1893). 

1.  "  Pythagorics  "    (on    the    Pythagorean    brotherhood),    pp. 

3375-3377- 

2.  "Dmesis"  (on  charity  towards  criminals),  pp.  3399-3402. 

3.  "The  Critic  of  Arguments  (I.),  Exact  Thinking,"  pp.  3391- 

3394. 

4.  "The  Critic  of  Arguments  (II.),  The  Reader  is  Introduced 

to  Relatives,"  pp.  3415-3419.  (The  last  two  contain  a 
very  clear  succinct  account  of  the  general  character  of 
Peirce's  logic.) 

5.  "What  is  Christian  Faith?"  pp.  3743-3745. 

6.  "  The  Marriage  of  Religion  and  Science,"  pp.  3559-3560. 

G.  Articles  in  Baldwin's  "  Dictionary   of  Philosophy  ":    Individual, 

kind,  matter  and  form,  possibility,  pragmatism,  priority, 
reasoning,  sign,  scientific  method,  sufficient  reason,  syne- 
chism,  and  uniformity. 

H.  "  Pearson's  Grammar  of  Science,"  in  Popular  Science  Monthly, 
Vol.  58  (1901),  pp.  296-306.  (A  critique  of  Pearson's 
conceptualism  and  of  his  utilitarian  view  as  to  the  aim  of 
science.) 

II.  Writings  of  Predominantly  Logical  Interest. 

A.  Five  Papers  on  Logic,  read  before  the  American  Academy  of 
Arts  and  Sciences.  Published  in  the  Proceedings  of  the 
Academy,  Vol.  7  (1867). 

1.  "On  an  Improvement  in  Boole's  Calculus  of  Logic,"  pp. 

250-261.  (Suggests  improvements  in  Boole's  logic,  es 
pecially  in  the  representation  of  particular  propositions. 
The  association  of  probability  with  the  notion  of  rela 
tive  frequency  became  a  leading  idea  of  Peirce's 
thought.) 

2.  "On  the  Natural  Classification  of  Arguments,"  pp.  261- 

287.  (A  suggestive  distinction  between  the  leading 
principle  and  the  premise  of  an  argument.  Contains 
also  an  interesting  note  (pp.  283-284)  denying  the  posi- 


BIBLIOGRAPHY  311 

tivistic  maxim  that,  "no  hypothesis  is  admissible  which 
is  not  capable  of  verification  by  direct  observation.") 

3.  "On  a  New  List  of  Categories,"  pp.  287-298.    The  cate 

gories  are:  Being,  Quality  (Reference  to  a  Ground), 
Relation  (Reference  to  a  Correlate),  Representation 
(Reference  to  an  Interpretant) ,  Substance.  "Logic 
has  for  its  subject-genus  all  symbols  and  not  merely 
concepts."  Symbols  include  terms,  propositions,  and 
arguments. 

4.  "Upon  the  Logic  of  Mathematics,"  pp.  402-412.    "There 

are  certain  general  propositions  from  which  the  truths 
of  mathematics  follow  syllogistically." 

5.  "Upon  Logical  Comprehension  and  Extension,"  pp.  416- 

432.  (Interesting  historical  references  to  the  use  of 
these  terms  and  an  attack  on  the  supposed  rule  as  to 
their  inverse  proportionality.) 

B.  "  Description   of   a   Notation   for   the   Logic   of   Relations,"   in 

Memoires  of  the  American  Academy,  Vol.  9  (1870),  pp. 
317-378.  (Shows  the  relation  of  inclusion  between  classes 
to  be  more  fundamental  than  Boole's  use  of  equality.  Ex 
tends  the  Booleian  calculus  to  DeMorgan's  logic  of  relative 
terms.) 

C.  "  On  the  Algebra  of  Logic,"  American  Journal  of  Mathematics, 

Vol.  3  (1880),  pp.  15-57.  (Referred  to  by  Schroeder  as 
Peirce's  Hauptwerk  in  "Vorlesungen  iiber  die  Algebra  der 
Logik,"  Vol.  i.,  p.  107.) 

£>.  "  On  the  Logic  of  Number,"  American  Journal  of  Mathematics, 
Vol.  4  (1881),  pp.  85-95. 

E.  "Brief  Description  of  the  Algebra  of  Relatives,"  Reprinted  from 

??,  pp.  1-6. 

F.  "  On  the  Algebra  of  Logic:    A  Contribution  to  the  Philosophy  of 

Notation,"  American  Journal  of  Mathematics,  Vol  7  (1884), 
pp.  180-202. 

G.  "A  Theory  of  Probable  Inference"  and  notes  "On  a  Limited 

Universe  of  Marks "  and  on  the  "  Logic  of  Relatives  "  in 
"  Studies   in    Logic   by    members   of   the    Johns   Hopkins 
University,"  Boston,  1883,  pp.  126-203. 
H.  "  The  Regenerated  Logic,"  Monist,  Vol.  7,  pp.  19-40. 

"The  Logic  of  Relatives,"  Monist,  Vol.  7,  pp.   161-217.    (An 
elaborate  development  of  his  own  logic  of  relatives,  by  way 
of  review  of  Schroeder's  book.) 
/.  Miscellaneous  Notes,  etc. 

i.  Review   of   Venn's  "Logic  of   Chance,"   North   American 

Review,  July,  1867. 
a.  "On  the  Application  of  Logical  Analysis  to  Multiple  AI- 


312  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

gebra,"  Proceedings  of  the  American  Academy,  Vol.  10 

(1875),  PP-  392-394- 

3.  "  Note  on  Grassman's  '  Calculus  of  Extension,' "  Proceed 

ings  of  the  American  Academy,  Vol.  13  (1878),  pp.  115- 
116. 

4.  "Note  on  Conversion,"  Mind,  Vol.  i,  p.  424. 

5.  Notes  and  Additions  to  Benjamin  Peirce's  "  Linear  Asso 

ciative  Algebra,"  American  Journal  of  Mathematics, 
Vol.  4  (1881),  pp.  Q2ff.,  especially  pp.  221-229. 

6.  "  Logical    Machines,"    American    Journal    of    Psychology, 

Vol.  i  (1888). 

7.  "Infinitesimals,"  Science,  Vol.  u  (1900),  p.  430. 

8.  "Some  Amazing  Mazes,"  Monist,  Vol.  18  (April  and  July, 

1908),  and  Vol.  19  (Jan.,  1909). 

9.  "On  Non-Aristotelian  Logic"  (Letter),  Monist,  Vol.  20. 
J.  A  Syllabus  of  Certain  Topics  of  Logic.    1903.    Boston.    Alfred 

Mudge  &  Son  (a  four  page  brochure). 

K.  Articles  in  Baldwin's  "Dictionary  of  Philosophy"  on:  laws  of 
thought,  leading  principle,  logic  (exact  and  symbolic), 
modality,  negation,  predicate  and  predication,  probable  in 
ference,  quality,  quantity,  relatives,  significant,  simple,  sub 
ject,  syllogism,  theory,  truth  and  falsity  universal,  universe, 
validity,  verification,  whole  and  parts. 

III.  Researches  in  the  Theory  and  Methods  of  Measurement. 
A.  General  and  Astronomic. 

1.  "On  the  Theory  of  Errors  of  Observation,"  Report  of  the 

Superintendent  of  the  U.  S.  Coast  Survey  for  1870,  pp. 
220-224. 

2.  "Note  on  the  Theory  of  Economy  of  Research,"  Report 

of  the  U.  S.  Coast  Survey  for  1876,  pp.  197-201.  (This 
paper  deals  with  the  relation  between  the  utility  and 
the  cost  of  diminishing  the  probable  error.) 

3.  "Apparatus  for  Recording  a  Mean  of  Observed  Times," 

U.  S.  Coast  Survey,  1877.  Appendix  No.  15  to  Report 
of  1875. 

4.  "Ferrero's  Metodo  dei  Minimi  Quadrati,"  American  Jour 

nal  of  Mathematics,  Vol.  i  (1878),  pp.  55-63. 

5.  "Photometric    Researches,"    Annals    of    the   Astronomical 

Observatory  of  Harvard  College,  Vol.  9  (1878),  pp.  i- 
181. 

6.  "Methods  and  Results.    Measurement  of  Gravity.    Wash 

ington.    1879. 

7.  "  Methods  and  Results.    A  Catalogue  of  Stars  for  Observa 

tions  of  Latitude.    Washington.    1879. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY  313 

8.  "On   the   Ghosts  in   Rutherford's  'Diffraction   Spectra,'" 

American  Journal  of  Mathematics,  Vol.  2   (1879),  pp. 

330-347- 

9.  "  Note  on  a  Comparison  of  a  Wave-Length  with  a  Meter," 

American  Journal  of  Science,  Vol.  18  (1879),  P-  51- 

10.  "A  Quincuncial  Projection  of  the  Sphere,"  American  Jour 

nal  of  Mathematics,  Vol.  2  (1879),  PP-  394>  396. 

11.  "Numerical  Measure  of   Success  of  Predictions,"  Science, 

Vol.  4  (1884),  p.  453. 

12.  "  Proceedings     Assay     Commission "     Washington,     1888. 

(Joint  Reports  on  Weighing.) 
B.  Geodetic  Researches.    The  Pendulum. 

1.  "Measurement  of  Gravity  at  Initial  Stations  in  America 

and  Europe,"  Report  of  the  U.  S.  Coast  Survey,  1876, 
pp.  202-237  and  410-416. 

2.  "  De  1'influence  de  la  flexibilite  du  trepied  sur  1'oscillation 

du  pendule  a  reversion,"  Conference  Geodesique  Inter 
nationale  (1877)  Comptes  Rendus,  Berlin,  1878,  pp.  171- 
187.  (This  paper  was  introduced  by  Plantamour  and 
was  followed  by  the  notes  of  Appolzer.) 

3.  "  On  the  Influence  of  Internal  Friction  upon  the  Correction 

of  the  Length  of  the  Second's  Pendulum,"  Proceedings 
of  the  American  Academy,  Vol.  13  (1878),  pp.  396-401. 

4.  "  On  a  Method  of  Swinging  Pendulums  for  the  Determina 

tion  of  Gravity  proposed  by  M.  Faye,"  American  Jour 
nal  of  Science,  Vol.  18  (1879),  pp.  112-119. 

5.  "Results  of  Pendulum  Experiments,"  American  Journal  of 

Science,  Vol.  20  (1880). 

6.  "Flexure   of  Pendulum  Supports,"  Report  of  the   U.  5. 

Coast  Survey,  1881,  pp.  350-441. 

7.  "On  the  Deduction  of  the  Ellipticity  of  the  Earth  from 

the  Pendulum  Experiment,"  Report  of  the  U.  S.  Coast 
Survey,  1881,  pp.  442-456. 

8.  "Determinations  of  Gravity  at  Stations  in  Pennsylvania," 

Report  of  U.  S.  Coast  Survey,  1883,  Appendix  19  and 
pp.  473-486. 

9.  "  On  the  Use  of  the  Noddy,"  Report  of  the  U.  S.  Coast 

Survey,  1884,  pp.  475-482. 

10.  "  Effect  of  the  Flexure  of  a  Pendulum  upon  the  Period  of 

Oscillation,"  Report  of  the  U.  S.  Coast  Survey,  1884, 
pp.  483-485- 

11.  "On  the  Influence  of  a  Noddy,  and  of  Unequal  Tempera 

ture  upon  the  Periods  of  a  Pendulum,"  Report  of  the 

U.  S.  Coast  and  Geodetic  Survey  for  1885,  pp.  509-512. 

C.  Psychologic.    "  On    Small    Differences    in    Sensation "    (in    co- 


3H  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

operation  with  J.  Jastrow),  National  Academy  of  Sciences 
Vol.  3  (1884),  pp.  i-u. 

IV.  Philologic. 

"Shakespearian  Pronunciation"  (in  cooperation  with  J.  B.  Noyes), 
North  American  Review,  Vol.  98  (April,  1864),  pp.  342-369.' 

V.  Contributions  to  the  Nation. 

Lazelle,  Capt.  H.  M.,  One  Law  in  Nature.     Nation,  Vol.  17,  No.  419. 
Newcomb,  S.,  Popular  Astronomy.    Vol.  27,  No.  683. 
Read,  C,  Theory  of  Logic,  1878.    Vol.  28,  No.  718. 
Rood,  O.  N.,  Modern  Chromatics,  1879.    Vol.  29,  No.  746. 
Note  on  the  American  Journal  of  Mathematics.    Vol.  29,  No.  756. 
Jevons,  W.  S.,  Studies  in  Deductive  Logic,  1880.    Vol.  32,  No.  822. 
Ribot,  Th.,  The  Psychology  of  Attention,  1890.    Vol.  50,  No.  1303. 
James,  W.,  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  1890.    Vol.  53,  Nos.  1357  and 

I3S8. 
Comte,  A.  (F.  Harrison,  editor),  The  New  Calendar  of  Great  Men,  1802 

Vol.  54,  No.  1386. 
Lobatchewsky,  N.   (Translator:    G.  B.  Halsted),  Geometrical  Researches 

on  the  Theory  of  Parallels,  1891.    Vol.  54,  No.  1389. 
Lombroso,  C.,  The  Man  of  Genius,  1891.    Vol.  54,  No.  1391. 
Note  on   William  James'  abridgment  of  his  Psychology,   1892.    Vol.   54, 

No.  1394. 
McClelland,  W.  J.,  A  Treatise  on  the  Geometry  of  the  Circle,  1891.    Vol. 

54,  No.  1395. 

Buckley,  Arabella  B.,  Moral  Teachings  of  Science,  1892.    Vol.  54,  No.  1405. 
Hale,  E.  E.,  A  New  England  Boyhood,  1893.    Vol.  57,  No.  1468. 
Mach,  E.   (Translator:    T.  J.  McCormack),  The  Science  of  Mechanics, 

1893.    Vol.  57,  No.  1475. 

Ritchie,  D.  G.,  Darwin  and  Hegel,  1893.    Vol.  57,  No.  1482. 
Huxley,  T.  H.,  Method  and  Results,  1893.    Vol.  58,  No.  1489. 
Scott,  Sir  Walter,  Familiar  Letters  of  Sir  Walter  Scott.    Vol.  58,  No.  1493. 
Gilbert,  W.  (Translator:    P.  F.  Mottelay),  Magnetic  Bodies.    Vol.  58,  No. 

1494  and  No.  1495. 

Forsyth,  A.  R.,  Theory  of  Functions  of  a  Complex  Variable,  1893;  and 
Harkness,  J.,  A  Treatise  on  the  Theory  of  Functions,  1893 ;  and  Picard, 
E.,  Traite  d'analyse,  1893.    Vol.  58,  No.  1498. 
A  Short  Sketch  of  Helmholtz,  Sept.  13,  1894.    Vol.  59,  No.  1524. 
Windelband,  W.  (Translator:    J.  H.  Tufts),  A  History  of  Philosophy;  and 
Falkenberg,  R.   (Translator:    A.  C.  Armstrong),  History  of  Modern 
Philosophy;  and  Bascom,  J.,  An  Historical  Interpretation  of  Philoso 
phy;  and  Burt,  B.  C.,  A  History  of  Modern  Philosophy.    Vol.  59,  Nos. 
1526  and  1527. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY  315 

Spinoza  (Translators:  W.  H.  White  and  Amelia  H.  Stirling),  Ethics, 
1894.  Vol.  59,  No.  1532. 

Watson,  J.,  Comte,  Mill,  and  Spencer,  1895.    Vol.  60,  No.  1554. 

Jones,  H.,  A  Critical  Account  of  the  Philosophy  of  Lotze,  1895;  and  Eber- 
hard,  V.,  Die  Grundbegriffe  der  ebenen  Geometrie,  1895;  and  Klein, 
F.  (Translator:  A.  Ziwet),  Riemann  and  his  Significance  for  the  De 
velopment  of  Modern  Mathematics,  1895;  and  Davis,  N.  K.,  Elements 
of  Inductive  Logic,  1895.  Vol.  61,  No.  1566. 

Benjamin,  P.,  The  Intellectual  Rise  in  Electricity,  1895.    Vol.  62,  No.  1592. 

Baldwin,  J.  M.,  The  Story  of  the  Mind,  1898.    Vol.  67,  No.  1737. 

Darwin,  G.  H.,  The  Tides  and  Kindred  Phenomena  in  the  Solar  System, 
1898.  Vol.  67,  No.  1747. 

Marshall,  H.  R.,  Instinct  and  Reason,  1898.    Vol.  68,  No.  1774. 

Britten,  F.  J.,  Old  Clocks  and  Watches  and  their  Makers,  1899.  Vol.  69, 
No.  1778. 

Renouvier,  Ch.,  et  Prat,  L.  La  Nouvelle  Monadologie,  1899.  Vol.  69, 
No.  1779. 

Mackintosh,  R.,  From  Comte  to  Benjamin  Kidd,  1899;  and  Moore,  J.  H., 
Better- World  Philosophy,  1899.  Vol.  69,  No.  1784. 

Ford,  P.  L.,  The  Many-sided  Franklin,  1899.    Vol.  69,  No.  1793. 

Avenel,  G.  d',  Le  Mecanisme  de  la  vie  moderne,  1900.    Vol.  70,  No.  1805. 

Reid,  W.,  Memoirs  and  Correspondence  of  Lyon  Playfair,  1899.  Vol.  70, 
No.  1806. 

Stevenson,  F.  S.,  Robert  Grosseteste,  1899.    Vol.  70,  No.  1816. 

Thilly,  F.,  Introduction  to  Ethics,  1900.    Vol.  70,  No.  1825. 

Wallace,  A.  R.,  Studies,  Scientific  and  Social,  1900.    Vol.  72,  No.  1854. 

Sime,  J.,  William  Herschel  and  His  Work,  1900.    Vol.  72,  No.  1856. 

Rand,  B.  (Editor),  The  Life,  Unpublished  Letters,  and  Philosophical  Regi 
men  of  Anthony,  Earl  of  Shaftesbury,  1900;  and  Robertson,  J.  M. 
(Editor),  Characteristics  of  Men,  etc.,  by  Shaftesbury,  1900.  Vol.  72, 
No.  1857. 

Bacon,  Rev.  J.  M.,  By  Land  and  Sea,  1901.    Vol.  72,  No.  1865. 

Jordan,  W.  L.,  Essays  in  Illustration  of  the  Action  of  Astral  Gravitation 
in  Natural  Phenomena,  1900.  Vol.  72,  No.  1876. 

Goblot,  E.,  Le  Vocabulaire  Philosophique,  1901.    Vol.  72,  No.  1877. 

Fraser,  A.  C.  (Editor),  The  Works  of  George  Berkeley,  1901.  Vol.  73, 
No.  1883. 

Frazer,  P.,  Bibliotics,  1901.    Vol.  73,  No.  1883. 

Caldecott,  A.,  The  Philosophy  of  Religion  in  England  and  America,  1901. 
Vol.  73,  No.  1885. 

Review  of  four  physical  books.    Vol.  73,  No.  1887. 

Maher,  M.,  Psychology:  Empirical  and  Rational,  1901.  Vol.  73,  No. 
1892. 

Mezes,  S.  E.,  Ethics,  1901.    Vol.  73,  No.  1895. 

Report  of  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  Philadelphia, 
1901.  Vol.  73,  No.  1899. 


316  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

Crozier,  J.  B.,  History  of  Intellectual  Developments  on  the  Lines  of  Modern 

Evolution.    Vol.  III.,  1901,  Vol.  74,  No.  1908. 
Richardson,  E.  C,  Classification,  Theoretical  and  Practical,  1901.    Vol.  74, 

No.  1913. 
Vallery-Radot,   R.    (Translator:     Mrs.   R.   L.   Devonshire),   The   Life  of 

Pasteur.    Vol.  74,  No.  1914. 

Giddings,  F.  H.,  Inductive  Sociology,  1902.    Vol.  74,  No.  1918. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  Washington, 

D.  C.,  1902.    Vol.  74,  No.  1921. 

Emerson,  E.  R.,  The  Story  of  the  Vine,  1902.    Vol.  74,  No.  1926. 
Joachim,  H.  H.,  A  Study  of  the  Ethics  of  Spinoza,  1901.    Vol.  75,  No. 

1932. 

Review  of  four  chemistry  text-books,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1934. 
Royce,  J.,  The  World  and  the  Individual,  Vol.  II.,   1901.    Vol.   75,  No. 

I93S-     (For  a  review  of  Vol.  I.,  probably  by  Peirce,  see  1900,  Vol.  70, 

No.  1814.) 

Thorpe,  T.  E.,  Essays  in  Historical  Chemistry,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1938. 
Paulsen,  F.,  Immanuel  Kant:    His  Life  and  Doctrine,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No. 

1941. 

Aikens,  H.  A.,  The  Principles  of  Logic,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1942. 
Drude,  P.,  The  Theory  of  Optics,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1944. 
Valentine,  E.  S.,  Travels  in  Space,  1902 ;  and  Walker,  F.,  Aerial  Naviga 
tion,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1947. 
Baillie,  J.  B.,  The  Origin  and  Significance  of  Hegel's  Logic,  1901.    Vol.  75, 

No.   1950. 
Forsyth,  A.  R.,  Theory  of  Differential  Equations,  Vol.  IV.,  1902.    Vol.  75, 

No.  1952. 

Ellwanger,  G.  W.,  The  Pleasures  of  the  Table,  1902.    Vol.  75,  No.  1955. 
Earle,  Alice  M.,  Sundials  and  Roses  of  Yesterday,   1902.    Vol.   75,  No. 

1956. 

Smith,  Rev.  T.,  Euclid:    His  Life  and  System,  1902.    Vol.  76,  No.  1961. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  Washington, 

D.  C.,  1903.    Vol.  76,  No.  1974. 

Hibben,  J.  G.,  Hegel's  Logic,  1902.    Vol.  76,  No.  1977. 
Mellor,  J.  W.,  Higher  Mathematics  for  Students  of  Chemistry  and  Physics, 

1903.    Vol.  76,  No.  1977. 

Sturt,  H.  C.  (Editor),  Personal  Idealism,  1902.    Vol.  76,  No.  1979. 
Baldwin,  J.  M.,  Dictionary  of  Philosophy  and  Psychology,  Vol.  II.,  1902. 

Vol.  76,  No.  1980. 
Note  on  Kant's  Prolegomene  edited  in  English  by  Dr.  P.  Carus,  1903. 

Vol.  76,  No.  1981. 

Smith,  N.,  Studies  in  the  Cartesian  Philosophy,  1902.    Vol.  77,  No.  1985. 
Hinds,  J.  I.  D.,  Inorganic  Chemistry,  1902.    Vol.  77,  No.  1986. 
Clerke,  Agnes  M.,  Problems  in  Astrophysics,  1903.    Vol.  77,  No.  1987. 
Michelson,  A.  A.,  Light  Waves  and  their  Uses,  1903 ;  and  Fleming,  J.  A., 

Waves  and  Ripples  in  Water,  1902.    Vol.  77,  No.  1989. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY  317 

Note  on  Sir  Norman  Lockyer.    Vol.  77,  No.  1794. 

Note  on  British  and  American  Science,  1903.    Vol.  77,  No.  1996. 

Welby,  Lady  Victoria,  What  is  Meaning?  1903;  and  Russell  B,  The  Prin 
ciples  of  Mathematics,  1903.  Vol.  77,  No.  1998. 

Note  on  the  Practical  Application  of  the  Theory  of  Functions,  1903.  Vol. 
77,  No.  1999. 

Fahie,  J.  J.,  Galileo.    Vol.  78,  No.  201.5. 

Halsey,  F.  A.,  The  Metric  Fallacy,  and  Dale,  S.  S.,  The  Metric  Failure  in 
the  Textile  Industry.  Vol.  78,  No.  2020. 

Newcomb,  S.,  The  Reminiscences  of  an  Astronomer,  1903.    Vol.  78,  No. 

2O2I. 

Boole,  Mrs.  M.  E.,  Lectures  on  the  Logic  of  Arithmetic,  1903 ;  and  Bowden, 
J.,  Elements  of  the  Theory  of  Integers,  1903.  Vol.  78,  No.  2024. 

Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  Washington, 
D.  C.,  1904.  Vol.  78,  No.  2026. 

Levy-Bruhl,  L.  (Translator:  Kathleen  de  Beaumont-Klein),  The  Philoso 
phy  of  Auguste  Comte,  1903.  Vol.  78,  No.  2026. 

Turner,  W.,  History  of  Philosophy,  1903.    Vol.  79,  No.  2036. 

Duff,  R.  A.,  Spinoza's  Political  and  Ethical  Philosophy.  Vol.  79,  No. 
2038. 

Allbutt,  T.  C.,  Notes  on  the  Composition  of  Scientific  Papers,  1904.    Vol. 

79,  No.  2039. 

Sylvester,  J.  J.,  The  Collected  Mathematical  Papers  of,  Vol.  I.    Vol.  79, 

No.  2045. 
Renouvier,  Ch.,  Les  Derniers  Entretiens,  1904,  and  Dewey,  J.,  Studies  in 

Logical  Theory,  1903.    Vol.  79,  No.  2046. 
Royce,  J.,  Outlines  of  Psychology.    Vol.   79,  No.  2048. 
Straton,  G.  M.,  Experimental  Psychology  and  its  Bearing  upon  Culture. 

Vol.  79,  No.  2055. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  New  York, 

1904.    Vol.  79,  No.  2057. 
Boole,  Mrs.  M.  E.,  The  Preparation  of  the  Child  for  Science,  1904.    Vol. 

80,  No.  2062. 

Royce,  J.,  Herbert  Spencer,  1904.    Vol.  80,  No.  2065. 

Strutt,  R.  J.,  The  Becquerel  Rays  and  the  Properties  of  Radium,  1904. 

Vol.  80,  No.  2066. 
Schuster,  A.,  An  Introduction  to  the  Theory  of  Optics,  1904.    Vol.  80, 

No.  2071. 

Tindlay,  A.,  The  Phase  Rule  and  its  Application,  1904.    Vol.  80,  No.  2074. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  Washington, 

D.  C.,  1905.    Vol.  80,  No.  2078. 
Flint,  R.,  Philosophy  as  Scientia  Scientiarum,  1904;  and  Peirce,  C.  S.,  A 

Syllabus  of  Certain  Topics  of  Logic,  1903.    Vol.  80,  No.  2079. 
Arnold,  R.  B.,  Scientific  Fact  and  Metaphysical  Reality,  1904,  also  a  Note 

on  Mendeleeffs  Principles  of  Chemistry.    Vol.  80,  No.  2083. 


318  BIBLIOGRAPHY 

Note  on  Ida  Freund's  The  Study  of  Chemical  Composition.    Vol.  80,  No. 

2086. 

Carnegie,  A.,  James  Watt,  1905.    Vol.  80,  No.  2087. 
Ross,  E.  A.,  Foundations  of  Sociology,  1905,  and  Sociological  Papers,  1905, 

published  by  the  Sociological  Society.    Vol.  81,  No.  2089. 
Wundt,   W.    (Translator:     E.   B.   Titchener),    Principles    of    Physiological 

Psychology,  1904.    Vol.  81,  No.  2090. 
Roscoe,  H.  E.,  A  Treatise  on  Chemistry,  Vol.  I.,  1905,  and  de  Fleury,  M., 

Nos  Enfants  au  College,  1905.    Vol.  81,  No.  2097. 
Varigny,  H.  de,  La  Nature  et  la  Vie,  1905.    Vol.  81,  No.  2101. 
Note  on  Mr.  G.  W.  Hill's  Moon  Theory.    Vol.  81,  2103. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,  New  Haven. 

1905.    Vol.  81,  No.  2108. 

Gosse,  E.,  Sir  Thomas  Browne,  1905.    Vol.  81,  No.   2111. 
Rutherford,  E.,  Radio-Activity,  1905.    Vol.  82,  No.  2116. 
Wallace,  A.  R.,  My  Life,  1905.    Vol.  82,  No.  2121. 
Haldane,  Elizabeth  S.,  Descartes.    Vol.  82,  No.  2125. 
Report  on  the  Meeting  of  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences,.  Washington, 

D.  C,  1906.    Vol.  82,  No.  2130. 

Rogers,  H.  J.  (Editor),  Congress  of  Arts  and  Sciences,  Universal  Exposi 
tion,  St.  Louis,  1904.    Vol.  82,  No.  2136. 
Loeb,  J.,  The  Dynamics  of  Living  Matter;  and  Mann,  G.,  Chemistry  of 

the  Proteids.    Vol.  83,  No.  2140. 
Roscoe,  H.  E.,  The  Life  and  Experiences  of  Sir  Henry   Enfield  Roscoe. 

Vol.  83,  No.  2141. 

Marshall,  T.,  Aristotle's  Theory  of  Conduct.    Vol.  83,  No.  2150. 
Joseph,  H.  W.  B.,  An  Introduction  to  Logic.    Vol.  83,  No.  2156. 

OTHER  ARTICLES  AND  REVIEWS 

Old  Stone  Mill  at  Newport,  Science,  4,  1884,  512. 

Criticism  on  "  Phantasms  of  the  Living,"  Proc.  Am  Soc.  Psychical  Re 
search,  Vol.  i,  No.  3  (1887). 

Napoleon  Intime,  The  Independent,  December  21  and  December  28,  1893. 
Decennial  Celebration  of  Clark  University,  Science,  n  (1900),  p.  620. 
Century's    Great   Men    of    Science,    Smithsonian   Institute   Reports,    1900. 
Campanus  Science,  13  (1901),  p.  809. 
French  Academy  of  Science,  N.  Y.  Evening  Post,  March  5,  1904. 


BINDING  SECT 

15  1975 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


B  Peirce,   Charles  Santiago 

945  oanders 

P41C6      Chance,  love  and  logic